Skip to main content

Full text of "Memoir of Andrew Seth Pringle-Pattison"

See other formats


The 
Balfbur  Lectures  on   Realism 


Photo  by 


E.  H.  Yerbur/j  A  Son,  Edinburgh 


The 
Balfour  Lectures  on  Realism 

^Delivered  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh 


BY 


A.   SETH   PRINGLE-PATTISON 

LL.D.,  D.C.L. 

FELLOW   OF  THE   BRITISH   ACADEMY 

SOMETIME   PROFESSOR   OF  LOGIC   AND   METAPHYSIC 

IN  THE   UNIVERSITY  OF   EDINBURGH 


EDITED,    WITH    A 

Memoir  of  the  Author 

BY 

G.   F.   BARBOUR 

D.PHIL.  EDIN. 


EDINBURGH   AND    LONDON 
WILLIAM    BLACKWOOD   6-   SONS   LTD. 

1933 


PRINTED  IN   GREAT  BRITAIN 
ALL  EIGHTS  RESERVED 


PREFACE. 


AMONG  the  writings  of  Professor  Pringle-Pattison  which 
never  appeared  in  a  permanent  form  during  his  lifetime 
the  most  important  was  the  Third  Series  of  Balfour 
Lectures.  These  were  delivered  early  in  1891,  six 
months  before  his  transference  from  the  Chair  of  Logic 
in  the  University  of  St  Andrews  to  the  corresponding 
Chair  in  Edinburgh.  The  history  of  the  Balfour  Lecture 
ship,  and  some  indications  of  the  reasons  which  prevented 
Professor  Seth,  as  he  then  was,  from  publishing  these 
Lectures  on  Realism  as  the  sequel  to  Scottish  Philosophy 
and  Hegelianism  and  Personality,  will  be  found  in 
Chapter  IV.  of  the  Memoir  which  forms  the  earlier  part 
of  the  present  volume.  So  they  need  not  be  set  out  at 
length  here.  But  it  is  well  to  state  in  a  sentence  the 
reasons  which  have  led  to  their  publication  now.  They 
not  only  complete  a  series  of  Lectures  the  earlier  instal 
ments  of  which  awakened  keen  interest  at  the  date  of 
their  publication  and  for  long  after,  but  they  fill  a 
considerable  gap  in  the  record  of  Professor  Pringle- 
Pattison's  philosophical  development,  and  show  how  he 
regarded  the  problems  of  Epistemology  at  the  end  of 
his  first  period  as  a  teacher  and  writer.  Although  they 
have  not  before  appeared  in  volume  form,  they  were 
published  in  the  Philosophical  Review,  under  the  editor 
ship  of  Dr  J.  G.  Schurman  ;  and  those  responsible  for 


vi  PREFACE 

this  volume  desire  to  thank  the  present  editor  of  the 
Review,  and  the  authorities  of  Cornell  University,  by 
whom  it  is  published,  for  their  courtesy  in  allowing  the 
Lectures  to  be  reprinted  here. 

Although  the  Memoir  is  not  a  long  one,  the  number 
of  those  who  have  helped  in  its  preparation  is  very 
considerable.  The  contribution  of  those  who  have 
placed  letters  at  my  disposal  will  be  estimated  by  the 
reader  of  the  Memoir  itself ;  but  I  wish  to  express  my 
special  indebtedness  to  Mr  Norman  Pringle-Pattison 
and  other  members  of  Professor  Pringle-Pattison's 
family  who  have  given  the  most  generous  assistance  ; 
to  Mrs  John  MacCunn,  Mr  J.  B.  Capper  and  Mr  R.  P. 
Hardie  for  valuable  information  and  other  help  ;  and 
to  Mr  William  Menzies  for  the  account  of  the  St  Andrews 
professorship  which  forms  the  greater  part  of  Chapter  V. 
I  am  also  greatly  indebted  to  Mrs  Edgar  Dugdale,  who 
has  given  on  behalf  of  the  late  Earl  of  Balfour's  literary 
executors  permission  to  make  free  use  of  the  correspond 
ence  extending  over  many  years  between  Lord  Balfour 
and  Professor  Pringle-Pattison  ;  and  I  would  extend 
not  less  hearty  thanks  to  Miss  Haldane  for  similar  per 
mission  to  use  letters  to  and  from  Viscount  Haldane, 
and  to  Mrs  de  Glehn  and  Mr  R.  C.  Bosanquet,  who 
have  kindly  allowed  me  to  include  in  Chapter  XL 
unpublished  letters  of  great  value  from  Mr  F.  H.  Bradley 
and  Professor  Bernard  Bosanquet  respectively. 

G.   F.   BARBOUR. 


FINCASTLE,  PERTHSHIRE, 
September  1933. 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 

PREFACE  ....  v 


MEMOIR. 

CHAP. 

I.    EARLY   YEARS.      1856-1878  3 

II.    GERMANY.      1878-1880 2I 

III.  EDINBURGH   AND   CARDIFF.      1880-1887            •             -  33 

IV.  THE   BALFOUR  LECTURES.      1884-189!                .             .  47 
V.    ST  ANDREWS.      1887-189! 58 

VI.    FIRST    YEARS    IN    THE    EDINBURGH    CHAIR.       1891- 

1897       •                          70 

VII.   THE  HAINING.      1898-1914  §3 
VIII.    UNIVERSITY      TEACHING      AND      CORRESPONDENCE 

WITH  FRIENDS.      1898-1914       «...  93 

IX.    GIFFORD   LECTURES   ON   THEISM.      1912-1917             .  115 

X.    THE   WAR  YEARS.      1914-1918       .  .  .  .125 

XI.    LATER   GIFFORD   LECTURES.      1919-1923           .             .  136 

XII.    CLOSING  YEARS.      1923-1931          .  .  .  .149 


viii  CONTENTS 


THE   BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM. 

LECTURE  PAGE 

I.    PSYCHOLOGY,    EPISTEMOLOGY   AND   METAPHYSICS    .       163 

The  need  for  a  clear  distinction  between  Psychology 
and  the  Theory  of  Knowledge — Distinction  between 
the  two  inquiries  drawn  by  Descartes  and  Locke — 
Locke's  subsequent  confusion  of  them — The  reference 
of  ideas  to  a  world  of  reality — How  this  is  dealt  with 
by  subjective  idealists,  e.g.,  Mill — Psychology  is 
either  purely  subjective,  or  (physiological  or  experi 
mental  psychology)  purely  objective — Epistemology 
deals  with  the  reference  to  reality,  i.e.,  the  validity 
of  knowledge — Note  on  the  terms,  Epistemology, 
Philosophy,  Ontology — Epistemology,  a  preliminary 
investigation,  clearing  the  way  for  Metaphysics — Dis 
tinction  to  be  observed  between  the  use  in  Episte 
mology  and  Metaphysics  of  the  terms,  Phenomenon, 
Idealism — Consistent  epistemological  Idealism  leads 
to  Solipsism — Epistemological  Realism  makes  meta 
physical  Idealism  possible — Hegelian  thought  and 
Realism  in  its  Scottish  form  alike  defective  here. 


II.   THE   PROBLEM   OF   EPISTEMOLOGY  .  .  .       183 

Knowledge  is  subjective  as  a  state  or  process  of  the 
knowing  being — But  it  involves  an  objective  refer 
ence — Fundamental  doubts  as  to  the  possibility  of 
knowledge — Hume  and  Spencer  on  the  Realism  of 
ordinary  thinking — The  attitude  of  Reid — Per 
ception  not  explained  by  the  supposition  of  an  un- 
differentiated,  primordial  sensuous  consciousness — 
Function  of  activity,  of  effort  against  resistance,  in 
the  genesis  of  knowledge — Epistemological  Idealism 
only  exists  as  a  criticism  of  Realism — A  critical 
Realism  the  one  sane  Theory  of  Knowledge — Subject 
and  object  are  united  in  knowledge,  but  distinct  in 
existence — The  self,  a  principle  both  of  isolation  and 
communion — Objects  not  '  present  in  '  consciousness 
— Meaning  of  the  trans-subjective — The  assertion  of 
immediate  perception  no  real  solution  of  the  problem. 


CONTENTS  ix 


III.   EPISTEMOLOGY  IN  LOCKE   AND   KANT    .  .  .       2OI 

Locke's  hypothetical  Realism — Distinction  between 
'  idea  '  and  '  idea  of  a  thing/  ignored  by  Locke  and 
denied  by  Hume — Origin  in  Locke  of  the  doctrine  of 
representative  perception — His  other  and  sounder 
doctrine  that  knowledge  is  of  things,  not  of  ideas 
only — Development  of  the  former  by  Berkeley  and 
Hume — Place  of  the  thing-in-itself  in  Kant's  system — 
His  distinction  between  his  doctrine  and  '  Idealism  ' — 
His  criticism  of  Fichte's  subjectivism — Yet  he  main 
tains  the  phenomenalism  which  marked  one  side  of 
Locke's  thinking — His  emphasis  on  the  receptive 
character  of  human  understanding — Identification  of 
the  '  phenomenal  object '  with  real  things — Kant's 
neglect  of  the  '  given,'  a  posteriori,  element  in  cogni 
tion — What  he  means  by  '  experience  ' — Material 
things  are,  for  him,  simply  spatially  arranged  per 
ceptions — His  doctrine  and  Berkeley's,  similarity  and 
difference — His  conception  of  objectivity  ambiguous — 
Recognition  by  others  as  a  test  of  trans-subjective 
reality — '  Consciousness  in  general/  a  pure  abstrac 
tion. 


IV.   THE      EPISTEMOLOGY      OF      NEO-KANTIANISM      AND 

SUBJECTIVE  IDEALISM      .....       225 

Criticism  of  the  Kantian  thing-in-itself  by  Jacobi  and 
others — Parallel  between  the  post-Lockian  and  post- 
Kantian  developments — In  Neo-Kantian  thought 
the  necessity  for  a  transcendental  object  is  subjective 
only — Its  reduction  by  Cohen  to  a  purely  formal 
unity,  or  object-in-general — Similar  reduction  of  the 
subject  to  a  notion  or  category — Cohen's  doctrine  of 
the  self -rounding  world  of  experience — Its  lack  of 
any  real  basis  in  reality — Lange's  hesitating  attempt 
to  provide  this — The  final  result  in  Vaihinger's 
'  Critical  Scepticism  ' — Existence  there  appears  as  a 
self-evolving,  unsupported  illusion — Experience  can 
not  be  thus  divorced  from  the  trans-subjective — 
Intruding  percepts  as  signs  of  causal  connections  out 
side  consciousness — Error  of  interpreting  experience 
in  purely  immanent  terms — The  conception  of  Know 
ledge  dependent  on  the  trans-subjective — Mill's 
attempt  to  provide  this  within  the  limits  of  Empiri- 


CONTENTS 

cism — Ambiguous  character  of  his  '  possible  sensa 
tions  ' — His  covert  reintroduction  of  trans-subjective 
reality — Experience  not  equivalent  to  Knowledge — 
Spencer's  statement  of  the  distinction  as  against 
Mill  and  Bain — We  can  know  an  object  without 
being  it — Neglect  of  Kant's  theory  of  judgment  and 
the  activity  of  Reason  by  his  idealist  followers. 


CONCLUSION       .  253 

Forms  of  knowledge  must  correspond  to  forms  of 
existence  unless  knowledge  is  to  defeat  its  own 
object — Duality  of  knowledge  does  not  imply  meta 
physical  Dualism — Kant's  rejection  of  pre-established 
harmony — The  world,  not  a  brute  fact  external  to 
the  divine  Mind. 


MEMOIR 


OF 

ANDREW  SETH   PRINGLE-PATTISON 

BY 

G.   F.   BARBOUR 


CHAPTER   I. 

EARLY   YEARS. 

1856-1878. 

ANDREW  SETH— in  later  life  ANDREW  SETH  PRINGLE- 
PATTISON — was  born  at  i  West  Claremont  Street, 
Edinburgh,  on  December  20,  1856.  Unlike  that  great 
philosopher  who  would  never  acknowledge  his  birth 
day,  because  he  felt  that  it  linked  him  too  closely 
to  a  vanishing  and  illusory  world,  Seth  felt  a  quiet 
pride  in  those  forebears  whose  life  formed  the  back 
ground  of  his  own.  Nor  can  his  character  be  fully 
understood  without  some  reference  to  that  vigorous, 
if  austere,  intellectual  and  religious  life  which  through 
out  the  nineteenth  century  sent  forth  so  many  lads  of 
Scottish  country  stock  to  be  leaders  of  thought  and 
action  in  their  own  and  other  lands.  The  soil  in  which 
his  life  had  its  roots  is  described  in  the  opening  sen 
tences  of  a  brief  Memoir  of  his  younger  brother  James, 
which  he  wrote  in  1925 — sentences  which  may  be 
quoted  here,  since  they  are  equally  applicable  to  himself. 
He  was  the  second  son  of  Smith  Kinmont  Seth  and 
Margaret  Little,  the  eldest  having  died  in  infancy. 
"  Although  by  birth  a  townsman,  he  came  both  on  the 
father's  and  the  mother's  side  of  country  stock.  His 
paternal  grandfather,  William  Seth,  was  a  well-to-do 
farmer  in  the  east  of  Fife,  latterly  at  Rires,  near  Kil- 
conquhar,  and  many  of  the  boy's  happiest  memories 


4  MEMOIR 

were  of  long  summer  holidays  there  and  the  noble 
prospect  of  the  Firth  of  Forth  which  the  place  com 
manded.  His  mother's  family  had  been  connected 
for  several  generations  with  Langholm,  on  the  Scottish 
Border,  where  they  owned  some  land.  His  maternal 
grandfather,  Andrew  Little,  after  a  voyage  to  America 
in  1805  to  investigate  prospects  there,  eventually 
settled  near  Lauder  in  Berwickshire,  where,  with  the 
aid  of  one  of  his  brothers,  who  remained  unmarried,  he 
purchased  the  farm  of  Middle  Blainslie  in  1814.  The 
two  brothers  farmed  the  place  together  till  1848,  when 
they  found  themselves  able  to  retire  to  Edinburgh  with 
a  small  competence.  Margaret,  the  youngest  but  one 
of  Andrew's  children,  was  then  in  her  eighteenth  year. 
Smith  Seth,  her  future  husband,  the  youngest  of  a  large 
family,  had  entered  the  service  of  one  of  the  Scottish 
banks,  and  removed  to  Edinburgh  about  the  same 
time,  or  soon  after,  on  his  appointment  to  a  clerkship 
in  the  Head  Office  of  the  Commercial  Bank  there. 
The  two  were  married  in  1854,  and  •  •  •  of  their  family 
of  seven,  four  sons  and  two  daughters  grew  up  to  man 
hood  and  womanhood/' l 

When  Andrew  was  still  in  early  childhood  his  father 
passed  through  a  serious  illness,  and  thereafter  the 
parents  were  advised  to  move  from  the  north  of  the 
city  to  a  district  on  the  south  side,  at  a  higher  altitude 
and  above  the  mist  and  '  haar  '  from  the  Firth  of  Forth 
which  so  often  enshrouds  the  valley  of  the  Water  of 
Leith.  His  father's  health  improved,  and  after  more 
than  one  move  the  family  remained  in  the  pleasant 
Grange  district,  where  they  were  within  easy  reach 
of  the  home  of  the  maternal  grandparents  in  Dick 
Place.  Through  the  seventies  they  lived  at  13  Mansion- 
house  Road. 

1  Essays  in  Ethics  and  Religion,  by  James  Seth,  edited  with  a 
Memoir  by  A.  S.  Pringle-Pattison,  ad  init. 


MEMOIR  5 

Andrew  was  from  the  first  a  child  of  bright  and 
eager  mind.  He  knew  his  letters  at  two,  and  could 
read  in  his  fifth  year.  This  suggests  the  precocious 
mental  history  of  John  Stuart  Mill  half  a  century 
before ;  but  happily  his  subsequent  development, 
though  always  rapid,  became  more  normally  so.  When 
he  went  to  school,  his  mother,  though  herself  of  notably 
active  mind,  found  it  hard  to  keep  abreast  of  his  read 
ing.  He  seems  to  have  escaped  the  critical  intolerance 
which  is  a  besetting  fault  of  quickly  developing  youth, 
for  his  younger  brothers  and  sisters,  including  two 
who  were  his  juniors  by  twelve  or  fifteen  years,  always 
remembered  his  invariable  humility  and  helpfulness, 
which  they  felt  were  inherited,  not  from  one  parent, 
but  from  both.  The  younger  brothers  and  sisters  of 
his  friends  were  impressed  by  the  same  thoughtful 
kindness,  and  came  to  love  him  hardly  less  than  did 
the  members  of  his  own  family. 

After  attending  a  small  private  school  near  his  home, 
he  went  to  the  Royal  High  School,  associated  with  the 
early  days  of  Scott,  and  one  of  the  leading  Secondary 
Schools  of  Edinburgh.  His  years  there  were  filled  with 
hard  study,  his  chief  recreation  being  the  long  walks 
on  which  he  accompanied  his  father  or  school  friends. 
Sometimes  he  played  shinty,  a  form  of  hockey  native 
to  Scotland,  and  distinguished  from  the  English  game 
by  its  freedom  from  rules  for  the  protection  of  life  and 
limb. 

The  Rector  of  the  High  School  in  Seth's  day  was 
James  Donaldson,  afterwards  Principal  Sir  James 
Donaldson  of  St  Andrews.  Another  future  Principal 
of  a  Scottish  University,  Sir  George  Adam  Smith,  was 
a  pupil  at  the  High  School,  but,  though  only  a  few  weeks 
older  than  Seth,  was  a  year  ahead  both  at  school  and 
college.  In  the  Rector's  class  in  Classics,  however, 
which  comprised  the  two  senior  years,  they  found 


6  MEMOIR 

themselves  together.  Another  class-fellow,  whose  course 
ran  pan  passu  with  Seth's  and  whose  friendship  he 
valued  increasingly  during  more  than  sixty  years,  was 
John  Brainerd  Capper,  the  son  of  an  English  artist 
in  impaired  health,  who  had  settled  in  Edinburgh 
mainly  for  the  education  of  his  children.  "  We  lived 
not  far  apart,"  Mr  Capper  writes,  "  and  our  evenings 
were  often  spent  in  coaching  each  other  for  examina 
tions  in  which  we  were  both  to  compete,  all  special 
knowledge  individually  acquired  being  thrown  into  a 
common  stock."  *  In  the  final  year  in  the  High  School 
(1872-3),  Capper  beat  Seth  by  a  very  narrow  margin 
in  the  comprehensive  examination  for  the  High  School 
Club  Prize ;  but  neither  gained  the  Dux  medal,  then 
awarded  to  the  head  of  the  Latin  class  alone.  It  went  to 
a  boy  who  concentrated  for  the  purpose  on  that  special 
subject,  whereas  the  two  friends  aimed  at  a  wider 
circle  of  attainment.  In  those  days  the  Scottish  schools 
and  universities  already  treated  English  literature  as 
a  central  subject,  and  it  was  often  admirably  taught 
— a  feature  of  their  work  which  did  not  a  little  to  out 
weigh  the  more  profound  classical  scholarship  of  the 
English  Public  Schools.  The  senior  English  master  in 
the  High  School,  John  Merry  Ross,  was  one  of  these 
thorough  and  inspiring  teachers  of  English  ;  and  the 
love  of  Latin  and  Greek  which  Seth  acquired  in  Donald 
son's  class  was  at  least  equalled  by  the  appreciation 
of  English  poetry  which  Ross  did  much  to  awaken. 

Seth  went  on  with  Capper  and  A.  M.  Stalker,  another 
close  friend,  to  the  University  of  Edinburgh  in  the  late 
autumn  of  1873.  More  than  fifty  years  later  a  dis 
tinguished  colleague  of  Seth's,  Professor  W.  P.  Pater- 
son,  described  how,  as  a  younger  boy  at  the  Royal 
High  School,  he  had  watched  "  that  colossal  figure 

1  Andrew  Seth  Pringle-Pattison  (Proceedings  of  the  British  Academy, 
Vol.  xvii.). 


MEMOIR  7 

leaving  the  School  to  pass  on  to  the  University,  covering 
himself  with  glory/'  The  University  was  in  those  days, 
as  Professor  Paterson  added,  "  a  remarkable  nursery 
and  feeding-ground  of  talent/'  It  was  passing  through 
a  period  of  change,  though  many  years  were  still  to  pass 
before  some  of  the  more  important  developments  were 
completed. 

There  was  as  yet  no  University  Union  or  University 
residence ;  for  most  students  there  was  little  social 
and  no  athletic  life.  But  the  intellectual  life  was 
of  the  keenest,  and  there  was  full  opportunity 
for  independent  reading,  as  well  as  unhurried  com 
panionship,  in  the  long  vacation  which  followed  the 
six  strenuous  months  of  the  winter.  In  the  Faculty 
of  Arts  the  graduation  course  was  strictly  prescribed, 
every  student  being  required  to  pass  in  Humanity 
(Latin),  Greek,  English  Literature,  Logic  and  Meta 
physics,  Moral  Philosophy,  Mathematics,  and  Natural 
Philosophy  (Physics).  Only  when  these  seven  subjects 
had  been  gone  through  on  the  Pass  standard  was  it 
possible  to  take  additional  subjects  or  to  read  for 
Honours.  This  standard  was  not,  indeed,  a  severe  one, 
and  much  of  the  work  in  the  ordinary  classes  was  of 
the  type  now  covered  in  Secondary  Schools  ;  yet,  for 
a  student  beginning  at  fifteen  or  sixteen,  as  was  then 
usual,  and  proceeding  to  Honours,  the  course  was 
exacting  enough,  and  for  the  few  who,  like  Seth,  took 
two  Honours  groups,  the  years  of  student  life  were 
crowded  and  strenuous. 

The  professors  in  the  Faculty  of  Arts  in  the  seventies 
formed  a  distinguished  group.  Tait,  the  Professor  of 
Natural  Philosophy,  was  the  friend  and  fellow-worker 
of  Kelvin,  and  one  of  the  greatest  scientific  teachers 
of  his  time.  Blackie,  in  the  Greek  chair,  was  a  pic 
turesque  figure,  about  whom  many  legends  gathered. 
But  the  three  professors  who,  by  personality  and  teach- 


8  MEMOIR 

ing,  left  a  deep  impress  on  the  life  of  Andrew  Seth  were 
William  Young  Sellar,  David  Masson  and  Alexander 
Campbell  Fraser.  The  training  in  Latin  begun  under 
Donaldson  was  continued  under  Sellar,  a  man  whose 
genial  and  generous  nature  was  clothed  in  something 
of  the  gravitas  of  the  old  Roman  world,  and  whose 
friendship  enriched  the  life  of  his  pupil  for  many  years. 
In  visits  to  the  home  of  Sellar  and  his  brilliant  wife, 
the  foundation  was  laid  of  a  later  and  lifelong  friend 
ship  ;  for  in  after  years  one  of  the  daughters  of  the 
house,  Mrs  John  MacCunn,  and  her  husband,  the  Pro 
fessor  of  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Liverpool, 
took  a  special  place  in  the  inner  circle  of  his  intimates. 

The  Professor  of  English  Literature  was  also  a  man 
of  distinguished  character  and  achievement,  once  de 
scribed  by  Thomas  Carry le  in  these  words  :  c<  David 
Masson,  sincere  and  sure  of  purpose ;  very  brave,  for 
he  has  undertaken  to  write  a  history  of  the  universe 
from  1608  to  1674,  calling  it  a  Life  of  John  Milton."  l 
Sellar's  treatment  of  Lucretius  and  Virgil,  and  Masson's 
of  Milton  and  Wordsworth,  together  led  Seth  towards 
that  view  of  the  unity  of  the  highest  poetic  and  philo 
sophic  insight  which  is  implicit  in  much  of  his  writing, 
and  to  which  he  gave  deliberate  expression  in  the 
Preface  to  his  Gifford  Lectures  on  The  Idea  of  God. 
The  teaching  of  these  two  men  helped  also  to  mould 
that  admirable  prose  style — always  clear  and  felicitous 
and  not  seldom  eloquent — which  never  failed  him 
during  fifty  years  of  authorship.2 

But  the  master  influence  of  his  years  at  the  University 
was  that  of  Campbell  Fraser,  whose  class  he  entered 
in  1874,  and  whom  he  succeeded  as  Professor  of  Logic 
and  Metaphysics  seventeen  years  later.  In  Sir  James 

1  Quoted  by  Campbell  Fraser,  Biographia  Philosophica,  p.  246. 
B  Cf.  Lord  Haldane's  tribute  to  these  men,  especially  Sellar,  in  his 
Autobiography,  pp.  6-8. 


MEMOIR  9 

Barrie's  An  Edinburgh  Eleven  there  is  a  witty  descrip 
tion  of  the  venerable  professor  who  taught  self-confident 
undergraduates  to  "  wonder  if  they  existed  strictly 
so-called,"  and  who  "  led  his  classes  into  strange  places  and 
said  he  would  meet  them  there  again  next  day."  But  he 
continues  in  a  more  serious  vein,  "  Metaphysics  may  not 
trouble  you,  as  it  troubles  him,  but  you  do  not  sit  under 
the  man  without  seeing  his  transparent  honesty  and 
feeling  that  he  is  genuine.  In  appearance  and  in  habit 
of  thought  he  is  an  ideal  philosopher,  and  his  com- 
munings  with  himself  have  lifted  him  to  a  level  of 
serenity  that  is  worth  struggling  for." 

Campbell  Eraser's  character  and  teaching  are  clearly 
reflected  in  his  Biogmphia  Philosophica,  a  book  which 
is  less  known  than  its  remarkable  qualities  warrant. 
Its  opening  chapter  records  the  memories  of  a  boy  in 
the  Highland  manse  of  Ardchattan,  first  looking  out 
on  the  wonder  of  the  universe  in  days  when  George  IV. 
was  on  the  throne,  and  when  it  was  still  possible  to  talk 
with  a  venerable  lady  who  had  reached  womanhood 
when  her  brother  was  killed  at  Culloden,  or  with  a  man 
who  had  guided  Johnson  and  Boswell  in  their  journey 
across  Lorn.  It  ends  with  the  retrospect  of  a  philosopher 
who  in  his  eighty-fifth  year  is  able  to  say,  "  The  per 
plexing  doubts  about  the  universe,  in  which  I  newly 
found  myself  in  youth,  have  led  to  deeper  faith  in  the 
immanent  Divine  Spirit,  transforming  death  from  a 
movement  in  the  dark  into  a  movement  in  Omnipotent 
Goodness ;  trusted  when  it  withdraws  us  from  this 
embodied  life,  still  unable  to  picture  what  lies  in  the 
future." 

But  in  1874  the  publication  of  Campbell  Eraser's 
Philosophy  of  Theism  was  twenty,  and  of  his  Biogmphia 
Philosophica  thirty,  years  off.  He  had  not  then  given 
so  clear  a  form  to  his  ultimate  philosophical  convic 
tions  ;  but  on  the  basis  of  his  long  study  of  Berkeley 


io  MEMOIR 

he  was  gradually  leading  his  abler  students  from  an 
intellectual  interpretation  of  the  world  as  intelligible, 
orderly,  trustworthy,  to  the  further  conviction  that  it 
subserved  the  ends  of  moral  and  spiritual  beings.  As 
the  goal  of  their  progress  he  pointed  to  a  "  rational 
Faith- venture,"  which  he  later  summarised  as  the 
belief  that  "  nature  in  experience  is  really  the  language 
of  God,  and  that  Divine  Order  is  supreme  and  universal." 
Andrew  Seth's  debt  to  Campbell  Fraser  is  best  under 
stood  from  the  words  of  his  Inaugural  Lecture  on  his 
return  to  Edinburgh  in  1891.  "  Seventeen  years  ago 
I  entered  the  Junior  Logic  class  of  this  University,  with 
a  mind  opening  perhaps  to  literature,  but  still  sub 
stantially  with  a  schoolboy's  views  of  existence  ;  and 
there,  in  the  admirably  stimulating  lectures  to  which  I 
listened,  a  new  world  seemed  to  open  before  me.  What 
the  student  most  needs  at  such  a  period  is  to  be  intel 
lectually  awakened.  ...  He  has  to  be  induced  to  ask 
himself  the  world-old  questions,  and  to  ponder  the  pos 
sible  answers.  Above  all,  the  listener  should  be  made 
to  feel  that  the  questions  of  which  the  Professor  speaks 
are  not  merely  information  which  he  communicates— 
that  they  are  to  him  the  most  real  things  in  the  world, 
the  recurring  subjects  of  his  deepest  meditation.  All 
this  his  students  found  realised  in  Professor  Fraser 's 
teaching.  .  .  .  The  sense  of  mystery  and  complexity  in 
things,  which  he  brought  so  vividly  home  to  us,  inspired 
a  wise  distrust  of  extreme  positions  and  of  systems  all  too 
perfect  for  our  mortal  vision.  This  union  of  dialectical 
subtlety  with  a  never-failing  reverence  for  all  that  makes 
man  man,  and  elevates  him  above  himself,  lives  in  the 
memory  of  many  a  pupil  as  no  unworthy  realisation  of  the 
ideal  spirit  of  philosophy.  I  shall  count  myself  happy  if, 
with  his  mantle,  some  portion  of  his  spirit  shall  be  found 
to  have  descended  upon  his  successor.  I  hope  that,  in 
the  days  to  come,  the  dingy  but  famous  classroom  will 


MEMOIR  ii 

be  distinguished  as  of  old  by  searching  intellectual 
criticism  and  impartial  debate,  not  divorced  from  that 
spirit  of  reverence  and  humility  which  alone  can  lead 
us  into  truth."  l 

Alongside  or  even  in  some  measure  counter  to  the 
placid  stream  of  Campbell  Eraser's  Berkeleian  theism, 
there  flowed  other  currents  in  the  philosophical  thought 
of  this  decade  in  Edinburgh.  For  living  in  the  city, 
though  not  teaching  in  the  University,  was  Dr  James 
Hutchison  Stirling,  whom  Andrew  Seth  described  a  few 
years  later  as  being  "  for  distinctively  metaphysical 
acumen  probably  not  surpassed  by  any  man  living."  2 
This  may  sound  an  exaggerated  estimate,  but  it  repre 
sented  the  writer's  deliberate  opinion  of  the  first  British 
thinker  who  expounded  in  a  thorough  and  sympathetic 
way  the  philosophy  of  Hegel.  It  is  true  that  the  title 
of  Hutchison  Stirling's  chief  book,  The  Secret  of  Hegel 
(published  in  1865,  twelve  years  before  Edward  Caird's 
Philosophy  of  Kant],  invited  the  easy  witticism  that 
the  Secret  had  been  successfully  kept  by  the  learned 
author ;  but  to  the  keener  and  more  penetrating 
students  of  those  years,  his  pioneer  work,  followed  by 
that  of  Green  and  Caird,  made  possible  a  new  under 
standing  of  German  idealism.  This  tendency,  in  con 
trast  to  the  prevailing  English  empiricism,  and  to 
Campbell  Eraser's  via  media,  afforded  full  scope  to  the 
"  searching  intellectual  criticism  and  impartial  debate  " 
referred  to  in  the  Inaugural  Address  just  quoted.  The 
chief  scene  of  this  debate  was  the  Philosophical  Society 
of  the  University.  There  the  name  of  Robert  Adam- 
son,  afterwards  Professor  of  Logic  in  Glasgow  University, 

1  Man's  Place  in  the  Cosmos,  and  Other  Essays,  p.  25  f.     Later  in 
the  same  volume  (pp.  218  ff.)  is  reprinted  a  long  appreciation,  with 
hardly  a  note  of  criticism,  of  Campbell  Eraser's  Philosophy  of  Theism, 
which  Seth  contributed  to  the  Quarterly  Review  in  1898. 

2  In  an  unsigned  review  in  the  Scotsman  of  Dr  Stirling's  Text-book 
to  Kant. 


12  MEMOIR 

who  had  graduated  in  1871,  was  still  mentioned  with  a 
respect  not  unmingled  with  awe  by  those  who  followed 
in  the  middle  seventies ;  and  of  the  brilliant  group  of 
that  period,  D.  G.  Ritchie,  W.  R.  Sorley  and  R.  B. 
Haldane  became  personal  friends  of  Seth.  Fifty  years 
after,  Seth  wrote  :  "  Haldane  was  an  active  member 
of  this  Society  as  long  as  he  remained  in  Edinburgh, 
and  it  was  there  that  I  first  made  his  acquaintance, 
though  it  was  only  later,  after  my  own  return  from  two 
years'  study  in  Germany,  that  our  acquaintance  ripened 
into  intimacy  and  a  lifelong  friendship."  l  Another  of 
the  group  was  Alexander  Mitchell  Stalker,  who  found 
his  life-work  in  another  field,  as  Professor  of  Medicine 
in  University  College,  Dundee.  Stalker  had  already 
at  the  High  School  been  a  class-fellow,  and  formed  a 
third  in  the  intimate  friendship  of  Seth  and  J.  B.  Capper. 
Before  referring  to  the  discussions  in  which  the  friends 
explored  the  high  region  where  philosophy  and  theology 
meet,  we  may  turn  to  Seth's  tributes  to  two  of  the  great 
writers  who  made  an  ineffaceable  mark  on  his  mind  in 
these  years.  First  stands  the  teaching  of  Carlyle,  in 
whom  the  students  of  Edinburgh  felt  an  almost  personal 
pride.  Thirty  years  later  Seth  wrote,  in  the  Intro 
duction  to  a  volume  of  Carlyle's  Essays  which  he  edited  : 
"  The  Rectorship  of  a  Scottish  University  is  no  hall 
mark  of  literary  or  philosophical  distinction,  but  when 
Carlyle  was  elected  Rector  of  the  University  of  Edin 
burgh  in  1865,  by  the  students  of  his  alma  mater,  it  was 
instinctively  felt  to  be  the  fitting  tribute  of  eager  and 
ingenuous  youth  to  the  greatest  of  living  Scotsmen 
and  one  of  the  chief  intellectual  and  moral  forces  of 
the  century.  In  the  seventies  (I  speak  of  my  own  under 
graduate  days)  Carlyle's  hold  upon  the  younger  genera- 

1  R.  B.  Haldane  (Proceedings  of  the  British  Academy,  Vol.  xiv.). 
For  the  influence  of  the  Philosophical  Society,  cf.  the  Memoir  of 
James  Seth  already  referred  to,  pp.  xvi  f. 


MEMOIR  13 

tion  was  in  no  way  relaxed.  The  Goethean  psalm  of 
life,  of  which  he  was  so  fond — and  which  in  his  own 
rendering  has  a  deeper  organ-tone  than  the  original- 
still  chanted  itself  in  many  a  youthful  heart  as  a  real 
'  road-melody  or  marching  music  of  mankind/  ' 

The  unique  contribution  to  his  spiritual  development 
of  the  poetry  of  Wordsworth  appears  clearly  in  the 
record  of  his  vacations  of  1874  and  the  two  following 
summers.  This  is  preserved  in  long  journals  and  journal 
letters,  written  in  the  minute  but  singularly  clear  hand 
writing  which  changed  its  character  very  little  as  the 
years  passed.  Earlier  holidays  had  often  been  spent 
at  Rires,  his  own  description  of  which  has  already  been 
quoted.  In  April  1874  he  was  there  again  for  ten  days. 
'  The  weather  was  superb  to  idle  and  loll  about  the 
fields,"  he  notes.  "  I  had  In  Memoriam  and  Jane 
Eyre  with  me.  My  eyes  were  weak,  I  remember,  and  I 
wore  a  green  shade."  Thus  early,  unremitting  study 
had  caused  that  weakness  of  eyesight  which,  although 
it  never  caused  grave  anxiety,  troubled  him  at  intervals 
throughout  life  and  added  to  the  burden  of  his  work. 

In  autumn,  after  spending  August  at  Largs  on  the 
Firth  of  Clyde,  he  was  back  at  Rires,  and  it  was  then 
that,  on  Capper's  recommendation,  he  took  up  the 
study  of  Wordsworth.  The  following  winter  was  a 
crowded  one,  for  it  included  some  teaching  as  well  as 
much  study.  During  these  months,  while  Campbell 
Eraser's  lectures  were  opening  the  vistas  of  philosophic 
thought  before  him,  "  Carlyle's  marching  music  of  man 
kind  "  used  to  ring  in  his  mind  on  his  evening  walks 
home.  "  For  a  long  time,"  he  continues,  "  that  was  my 
main  spiritual  food.  All  through  the  winter  I  was 
engaged  in  following  out  everything  connected  with 
the  Wordsworths  and  so  becoming  acquainted  with 
Coleridge  and  De  Quincey.  Judge  of  my  delight  when 
the  Gray  Essay  was  announced — subject,  Wordsworth. 


14  MEMOIR 

I  discovered  it  one  morning  in  the  end  of  March  just 
before  going  to  Tait's  [class],  and  at  once  resolved  to 
write  it ;  and  the  plan  soon  sprang  up  of  a  trip  to  the 
Lakes." 

A  few  days  later  he  crossed  the  Border  for  the  first 
time  on  a  solitary  expedition  to  the  Wordsworth  country. 
After  walking  from  Windermere  Station  to  Ambleside, 
he  found  lodgings—"  a  delightful  parlour  and  bedroom 
(white  curtains  and  other  things  to  match)  for  los.  a 
week  "  ;  and  his  letter  expressed  the  hope  that  his 
mother  would  not  think  the  room  too  dear.  For  a  week 
he  tramped  the  valleys  round,  visiting  Rydal,  Hawks- 
head  and  the  many  other  spots  especially  associated 
with  the  poet,  and  exploring  the  Langdale  valley  and 
the  Kirkstone  Pass.  During  the  last  three  days  of  the 
expedition  he  covered  much  ground.  On  the  first  he 
walked  by  Dunmail  Raise  to  Keswick ;  next  day  he 
visited  Borrowdale  and  Southey's  grave  at  Cross- 
thwaite  ;  and  on  the  final  morning  he  climbed  Skiddaw 
before  catching  a  train  north  at  mid-day. 

Through  the  summer,  in  the  intervals  of  other  work, 
Seth  was  engaged  on  his  essay,  which  must  have  been 
one  of  considerable  length  ;  for  it  was  not  completed 
till  late  in  August  at  Brodick  in  the  Isle  of  Arran.  The 
months  of  work  which  he  gave  to  it  wrought  the  poetry 
of  Wordsworth  into  the  fabric  of  his  thought,  and  he 
speaks  of  the  blending  during  these  months  of  Carlyle's 
prophetic  message  with  the  Wordsworthian  influence. 
This  month  in  Arran  (August  1875),  like  other  West 
Coast  holidays,  he  spent  in  reading,  varied  by  some 
boating  and  fishing,  two  ascents  of  Goatfell,  and  other 
walks  with  his  father  and  younger  brothers  and  some 
times  with  other  companions.  Among  these  was 
Robert  Todd,  a  friend  of  singularly  gracious  character, 
whose  early  death  not  long  after  was  a  cause  of  great 
grief  to  the  Seths'  whole  circle.  Twice  during  the 


MEMOIR  15 

month  Andrew  went  off  for  two  days — the  first  time 
alone  round  the  north  of  the  island,  the  second  time  with 
his  brother  James  to  the  south.  On  this  occasion  they 
found  a  hospitable  welcome  in  a  farm  at  Corriecravie 
looking  towards  Ailsa  Craig.  The  journal  notes  how 
heartily  the  two  lads  (aged  eighteen  and  fifteen) 
were  received,  how  they  shared  in  the  warmth  of  a 
glorious  peat  fire  and  "listened  to  the  simple,  mirth 
ful  talk  "  of  their  kind  hosts,  as  all  those  who  had  been 
at  work  on  the  farm  gathered  in.  Their  bedroom,  with 
its  uneven  clay  floor,  opened  off  the  kitchen,  and  after 
a  supper  of  scones,  cheese  and  new  milk,  they  lay  in 
bed  listening  to  the  Gaelic  speech  in  the  kitchen,  broken 
now  and  then  by  peals  of  hearty  laughter. 

Seth  was  no  naturalist,  for  botany  and  zoology 
seldom  entered  into  a  liberal  education  in  the  Scotland 
of  that  day  ;  but  he  was  keenly  observant  of  the  broader 
effects  of  natural  scenery  as  well  as  of  much  beauty  in 
detail,  and  the  influence  of  Wordsworth  comes  out  in 
many  a  sentence  describing  light  and  shadow  on  hill 
and  sea,  or  the  changeful  aspects  of  the  sky.  At  one 
point  he  recalls  the  "  absolute  terror  "  which  took  hold 
upon  him  when,  on  an  earlier  visit  to  Arran  in  1871, 
he  first  reached  the  top  of  Goatfell  and  looked  down  into 
Glen  Rosa,  2000  feet  below,  and  across  to  the  jagged 
peaks  which  guard  its  head.  His  spirit  was  in  a  high 
degree  receptive  of  the  influences  of  nature  in  her  various 
moods. 

In  the  spring  of  1876  Seth  broke  new  ground  by  his 
first  expedition  to  the  Continent.  With  a  fellow-student, 
Thomas  Gilray,  afterwards  a  professor  of  English 
Literature  in  New  Zealand,  he  crossed  from  Leith  to 
Rotterdam,  whence  they  made  their  way  to  Cologne 
and  the  Rhine.  A  summer  semester  at  the  University  of 
Heidelberg  was  the  object  of  their  journey ;  and  from 
the  first  weeks  of  their  residence  Seth's  letters  are  full 


16  MEMOIR 

of  appreciation  of  that  German  life  with  which  a  few 
years  later  he  was  to  form  the  closest  of  personal  ties. 
The  beauty  of  the  town  and  its  surroundings,  the 
inexhaustible  walks  along  the  valley  of  the  Neckar, 
up  the  many  side  valleys  which  converge  upon  it,  on 
the  wooded  hills  above,  and  the  rooms  found  by  the  two 
Scots  lads  with  wide  views  from  their  lofty  windows — 
these  things  and  many  more  are  described  ;  nor  does  the 
furniture  escape  notice,  for  being  less  in  quantity  than 
in  the  British  houses  of  the  day,  it  can  be  well  seen, 
and  is  all  of  fine  quality.  Other  features  appeal  to  him 
less,  such  as  the  unpunctual  and  casual  ways  of  pro 
fessors  and  others — for  Prussian  efficiency  had  not 
spread  to  the  Rhineland  sixty  years  ago — and,  it  need 
hardly  be  said,  the  custom  of  duelling.  Church  singing 
he  feels  too  slow,  and  he  weighs  the  arguments  for  and 
against  the  continental  Sunday.  "  A  great  many 
people/'  he  writes,  "  get  no  rest  at  all,  so  that  upon  the 
whole  I  think  the  continental  peoples  wrong  themselves 
in  not  having  a  more  complete  day  of  rest.  Scotland, 
of  course,  errs  nearly  as  far  in  the  opposite  direction. 
England,  perhaps,  hits  the  mark  more  nearly." 

At  the  university  he  highly  appreciated  the  brilliant 
lectures  of  Kuno  Fischer,  and,  soon  after  the  semester 
began,  reported  that  he  could  follow  these  quite  easily. 
In  July  he  was  going  through  Fischer's  History  of 
Modern  Philosophy  at  the  rate  of  fifty  pages  a  day, 
and  by  the  end  of  the  summer  he  had  not  only  mastered 
German,  but  laid  the  foundation  of  the  wide  knowledge 
of  the  history  of  philosophy  which  served  him  well  in 
later  years.  Through  the  writings  of  Carlyle  he  had 
already  come  to  realise  the  greatness  of  Goethe,  and 
closer  study  of  his  poems  was  undertaken  as  a  preparation 
for  a  short  visit  to  Frankfurt  after  the  session  closed. 

His  debt  at  this  time  to  his  mother's  sister,  Miss 
Isabella  Little,  ought  not  to  pass  unnoted,  for  a  series 


MEMOIR  17 

of  long  letters  is  addressed  to  his  "  learned  aunt  "  ; 
and  it  is  clear  that  he  owed  to  her  not  only  occasional 
financial  help,  but  the  stimulating  comradeship  of  an 
alert  and  enterprising  mind.  It  is  chiefly  in  his  letters 
to  her  that  he  discusses  such  subjects  as  Sabbatarianism 
and  the  Old  Catholic  movement  led  by  Dr  Dollinger. 
At  this  time  she  was  engaged  in  the  study  of  Greek, 
and  one  letter  from  Heidelberg  gave  advice  as  to  the 
peculiarities  of  verbs  in  pi.  But  eighteen  months  later, 
just  when  her  nephew  was  about  to  graduate,  she 
evidently  threatened  to  navigate  seas  where  he  could  no 
longer  act  as  pilot  and  mentor,  and  he  put  in  a  note  of 
warning  :  "  I  am  afraid,  speaking  from  report,  that 
you  will  find  Hebrew  more  difficult  to  tackle  than 
Greek.  We  have  an  old  Hebrew  lexicon  which  you  once 
bought.  If  you  really  begin,  you  shall  get  it  on  the 
first  opportunity." 

Before  we  complete  this  brief  account  of  Seth's 
Lehrjahr  in  Edinburgh  and  pass  on  to  his  Wanderjahr 
—his  second  and  longer  time  of  study  in  Germany- 
it  is  needful  to  give  some  account  of  the  trend  of  his 
religious  thought.  It  was  impossible  for  any  serious 
student  in  Scotland  during  the  seventies  to  disregard 
the  effect  of  new  scientific  or  philosophic  theories 
upon  the  traditional  religious  beliefs  of  the  society 
around  him.  The  bearing  on  these  of  the  Darwinian 
theory  of  evolution  was  being  discussed  on  every  hand. 
The  summer  of  1876,  which  Seth  spent  peacefully  in 
Heidelberg,  saw  the  Free  Church  of  Scotland,  to  which 
he  belonged,  stirred  by  the  beginning  of  the  fierce  and 
prolonged  controversy  aroused  by  the  critical  views  of 
William  Robertson  Smith,  then  a  young  professor  of 
Old  Testament  Language  and  Literature  in  the  Church's 
College  in  Aberdeen.  These  two  new  lines  of  dis 
cussion — the  evolutionary  and  the  critical — were  vigor 
ously  followed  out  by  laymen  as  well  as  by  experts,  and 

B 


18  MEMOIR 

brought  to  a  sharp  issue  the  relation  of  the  new  learning 
to  the  old  theology.  Further,  as  we  have  already  seen, 
the  view  of  the  world  to  which  Campbell  Fraser  pointed 
the  way  had  a  theological  as  well  as  a  strictly  philoso 
phical  aspect ;  and  the  study  of  the  German  idealists 
brought  Seth  from  another  angle  to  see  the  importance 
of  the  Philosophy  of  Religion  as  linking  metaphysics 
with  theology.  A  survey  written  in  July  1877,  of  his 
intellectual  development  during  the  three  previous 
years,  gives  an  intimate  and  moving  view  of  the  process 
by  which  he  passed  from  the  orthodoxy  of  his  earlier 
upbringing  to  a  religious  outlook  in  harmony  with  the 
new  knowledge  of  the  time. 

He  notes  that  the  spring  of  1874  was  that  of  the  visit 
of  Moody  and  Sankey,  the  American  evangelists,  to 
Edinburgh  ;  and  that  their  visit  coincided  with  the  time 
when  he  was  beginning  to  think  on  serious  matters. 
'  They  were  not  without  some  effect  on  me.  I  remember 
being  deeply  moved  by  their  parting  address."  The 
following  winter  was  that  in  which  he  entered  Camp 
bell  Eraser's  class ;  and  he  records  that  keen  com 
petition  between  A.  M.  Stalker  and  himself  was  accom 
panied  by  much  friendly  discussion  of  Berkeley,  Hamilton 
and  other  thinkers,  when  "  everything  was  delightfully 
fresh/'  The  winter  saw  an  increasing  intimacy  between 
Stalker,  Seth  and  Capper  ;  and  the  last-named,  now  the 
only  survivor  of  the  three  friends,  recalls  in  how  pur 
poseful  a  way  Seth  set  himself  to  this  task  of  revaluation 
—as  in  later  life  to  more  practical  tasks — without  out 
ward  clatter  or  disturbance,  or  visible  evidence  of 
Sturm  und  Drang,  but  with  a  quiet  determination  to  go, 
in  Plato's  phrase,  wherever  the  argument  might  lead. 

A  year  later  the  influence  of  George  Eliot  and  Matthew 
Arnold  had  become  not  less  strong  than  that  of  Carlyle 
and  Wordsworth.  "  In  Adam  Bede  George  Eliot  first 
gained  her  prophetic  hold  over  me.  It  was  a  time  of 


MEMOIR  19 

opening  up,  aided  by  the  influence  of  nature  around  me 
and  my  studies  in  Wordsworth.  The  direction  was 
pantheistic,  and  was  not  checked  by  Robertson,  who 
supplied  the  moral  element." l  This  refers  to  the 
holiday  in  Arran  already  described,  which  was  con 
tinued  with  J.  B.  Capper  and  his  parents  at  Ballach- 
allan,  a  farm  overlooking  the  Tay  Valley  some  miles 
above  Dunkeld.  "  Capper  and  I  used  to  stroll  for  a 
quarter  of  an  hour  or  so  just  before  going  to  bed  under 
the  deep  blue  and  sparkling  lights  of  a  September  night, 
with  the  Tay  gleaming  in  its  shingly  bed  below  :  talk 
runs  deep  at  such  seasons  ...  it  turned  a  good  deal  on 
'  the  All '  and  Personal  and  Impersonal.  ...  I  began 
Romola,  which  moved  me  profoundly  and  left  its 
abiding  mark  on  my  life.  I  remember  incidentally 
that  we  used  to  frighten  Mr  and  Mrs  Capper  rather  by 
our  Berkeleianism  and  our  firm  conviction  that  it 
must  be  either  spirit  or  matter,  not  both.  Carlyle's  essay 
on  Novalis  is  also  associated  with  these  days."  The 
fragment  ends  with  the  following  winter  in  Edinburgh, 
when  Seth  had  "  devoured "  Literature  and  Dogma 
and  God  and  the  Bible;  and  he  and  Stalker  counted 
it  a  special  privilege  that  they  were  enabled,  through 
the  exertions  of  Mr  Capper,  to  hear  Matthew  Arnold 
lecture  on  Butler.  He  then  adds  an  unconscious  touch 
of  hero-worship  :  "  We  handled  his  MS.  afterwards  in 
the  reporter's  hands." 

Such  were  some  of  the  influences  that  helped  him  on 
the  first  stage  of  his  pilgrimage  towards  the  theism  which 
was  his  final  creed.  The  next  step  appears  in  a  remark 
able  passage  of  autobiography  in  Hegelianism  and 
Personality  (2nd  ed.,  p.  63  f.),  which  probably  describes 
the  two  years  which  followed  his  first  visit  to  Germany. 
After  referring  to  Green's  view  of  the  "  eternal  Self  " 

1  F.  W.  Robertson  of  Brighton,  whose  Sermons  and  Life  Seth  was 
also  reading. 


20  MEMOIR 

as  creating  "  the  manifold  individual  selves  "  which  we 
know,  he  continues  : — 

"  Probably  no  one  who  has  really  lived  in  this 
phase  of  thought  can  fail  to  remember  the  thrill  with 
which  the  meaning  of  the  new  principle  first  flashed 
upon  him,  and  the  light  which  it  seemed  to  throw  upon 
old  difficulties.  It  had  become  impossible,  with  due 
regard  to  the  unity  of  things,  to  conceive  God  as  an 
object,  as  something  quite  external  to  ourselves  ;  and, 
on  the  other  hand,  there  seemed  nothing  but  a  relapse 
into  ordinary  Pantheism,  with  its  submergence  of  self- 
consciousness,  and  all  that  hangs  thereby,  in  a  general 
life,  which  reason  and  conscience  alike  declare  to  be 
inferior  to  our  own.  But,  in  this  dilemma,  the  universal 
consciousness  seemed  to  rise  upon  us  as  a  creative  power 
which  was  not  without  us,  but  within — which  did  not 
create  a  world  of  objects  and  leave  it  in  dead  independ 
ence,  but  perpetually  unrolled,  as  it  were,  in  each  of 
us  the  universal  spectacle  of  the  world.  The  world  wras 
thus  perpetually  created  anew  in  each  finite  spirit, 
revelation  to  intelligence  being  the  only  admissible 
meaning  of  that  much-abused  term,  creation.  We  had 
here  a  new  and  better  Berkeleianism,  for  God  in  this 
system  (so  it  seemed)  was  not  an  unknown  Spirit, 
hidden,  as  it  were,  behind  the  screen  of  phenomena  ; 
God  was  not  far  from  any  one  of  us,  nay,  He  was  within 
us,  He  was  in  a  sense  our  very  Self." 


21 


CHAPTER   II. 

GERMANY. 

1878-1880. 

IN  the  spring  of  1878  Andrew  Seth  completed  his  five 
years'  course  at  Edinburgh  University,  where  his 
brother  James  was  already  following  in  his  steps.  He 
graduated  with  first  class  Honours  both  in  Classics  and 
in  Philosophy,  then  a  rare,  and  in  later  days  an  almost 
unknown,  distinction  at  Edinburgh.  The  high  promise 
which  he  had  already  shown  was  brought  to  the  notice 
of  Dr  Martineau  by  Mr  Jasper  John  Capper,  the  father 
of  his  friend,  who  had  some  acquaintance  with  the 
great  Unitarian  thinker ;  and  this  helped  to  secure  for 
Seth  a  Hibbert  travelling  scholarship,  after  an  inter 
view  in  London  in  July.  A  similar  scholarship  was 
granted  at  the  same  time  to  a  Canadian  student,  who 
had  worked  with  him  in  the  Honours  classes  during  the 
previous  winter,  and  who  became  a  lifelong  friend — 
Jacob  Gould  Schurman.  Dr  Schurman's  later  career 
was  both  varied  and  distinguished.  He  became  a 
citizen  of  the  United  States  and  President  of  Cornell 
University,  and  like  many  other  American  scholars, 
achieved  high  distinction  in  the  public  service.  He  was 
chosen  as  President  of  the  Commission  to  the  Philip 
pine  Islands  in  1899,  and  afterwards  filled  various 
diplomatic  posts.  After  the  war  he  was  appointed 


22  MEMOIR 

American    ambassador,    first    to    China    and    then    to 
Germany. 

During  a  holiday  with  his  family  at  Pirnmill  in  Arran, 
we  find  Seth  deeply  engaged  in  a  fresh  study  of  the 
Critique  of  Pure  Reason  as  a  preparation  for  his  sojourn 
in  Germany.  In  October  the  two  Hibbert  scholars 
set  out,  Schurman  going  to  Heidelberg  to  study  under 
Kuno  Fischer,  and  Seth  to  Berlin,  where  his  chief 
teacher  was  Zeller,  the  well-known  historian  of  Greek 
philosophy.  As  regards  his  main  object,  a  deeper 
understanding  of  the  great  German  idealists,  he  found 
that  the  German  universities  had  little  help  to  give ; 
for  other  forms  of  thought  than  the  Hegelian  were  in 
the  ascendant,  and  Kant  was  studied  chiefly  for  the 
sake  of  his  Theory  of  Knowledge,  interpreted,  in  the 
main,  in  an  agnostic  sense.1  This  accounts  for  such 
impatient  obiter  dicta  in  his  letters  as  that  the  worst  place 
for  the  study  of  German  idealism  was  Germany,  and 
that  lectures  were  to  be  looked  on  as  "  one  of  the  main 
obstructives  to  study."  "  Study,"  in  this  sense,  was 
provided  for  immediately  after  his  arrival,  when  he 
spent  £5,  2s.  on  complete  editions  of  Kant  and  Hegel 
—a  sum  equal  to  the  whole  cost  of  his  outward  journey. 
Yet  Zeller's  learning  and  thoroughness  impressed  him, 
and  he  found  the  lectures  of  Paulsen,  a  leader  among 
the  younger  thinkers,  acute  and  stimulating,  though 
he  describes  him  as  prone  to  give  the  latest  scientific 
theory  as  a  basis  of  philosophy—  •"  not  the  deeper 
results  of  Kant  and  Hegel :  for  that  a  jest  is  enough." 
It  is  of  interest  to  note  that  Seth  heard  him  lecture  in 
a  semi-private  conversational  class  on  Hume's  Dialogues 
on  Natural  Religion,  which  he  himself  made  the  starting- 
point  a  generation  later  of  his  most  important  book, 
The  Idea  of  God.  At  the  end  of  the  year  he  recorded 

1  Cf.  Lecture  IV.  in  the  present  volume,  "  The  Epistemology  of 
Neo-  Kantianism . ' ' 


MEMOIR  23 

his  impression  that  the  younger  thinkers,  in  their 
enthusiasm  for  the  Darwinian  conception  of  evolution, 
and  their  materialistic  bent  tinged  with  the  metaphysical 
influence  of  Schopenhauer,  had  failed  to  gain  that 
"  mental  equanimity  tempered  by  reverence  "  for  which 
he  looked  in  the  true  philosopher. 

The  letter  to  A.  M.  Stalker  in  which  certain  of  these 
intellectual  impressions  are  expressed  touches  lightly 
on  an  experience  which  in  the  end  influenced  Seth 
more  profoundly  and  contributed  more  to  his  life's 
happiness  than  all  the  lectures  which  he  ever  attended. 
This  was  his  introduction  to  German  home  life  in  the 
family  of  Herr  Albrecht  Stropp,  with  whom  he  boarded. 
In  earlier  days  Herr  Stropp  had  been  a  manorial  pro 
prietor  (Rittergutsbesitzer)  in  Silesia,  not  far  from  Breslau  ; 
but  his  capital  had  been  dissipated  by  two  serious  losses, 
caused  by  the  fault  of  one  man  and  the  misfortune  of 
another  with  whom  he  had  business  relations.  He 
then  obtained  a  minor  post  in  a  Government  office  in 
Berlin,  and  struck  Seth  as  "  very  gentle  and  kindly," 
but  "  a  little  crushed  by  the  world."  Frau  Stropp  was 
not  less  kindly,  but  of  a  more  vigorous  temperament, 
and  for  years  had  worked  hard  and  cheerfully  to  repair 
the  family  fortunes.  Their  daughter  Eva,  who  had 
received  a  good  education  among  the  Moravians,  was 
interested  in  literature,  French  and  English  as  well 
as  German.  Her  first  contribution  to  the  philosophical 
studies  of  the  young  Scotsman  was  of  a  somewhat 
quaint  kind.  She  knew  something  of  the  household  of 
the  celebrated  von  Hartmann,  and  evidently  hinted 
that  his  pessimism  might  be  attributed  in  part  to 
domestic  circumstances.  Directed  by  Fraulein  Stropp, 
Seth  walked  out  to  the  northern  suburbs  of  Berlin, 
and  saw  the  great  pessimist,  much  muffled  in  furs,  study 
ing  in  the  winter  sunshine  on  a  veranda — a  small  man 
with  an  impressive  head. 


24  MEMOIR 

The  friendship  thus  begun  between  Seth  and  Eva 
Stropp  ripened  steadily  into  a  deeper  attachment ; 
and  at  the  end  of  the  winter  Seth  wrote  to  Capper  that 
he  had  been  reading  the  Midsummer  Night's  Dream 
and  Winter's  Tale  with  her,  and  sent  him  some  original 
lines  which  let  his  friend  see  clearly  the  trend  of  his 
feelings.  Another  letter  told  that  he  had  "  read  some 
of  Shelley's  splendid  lyrics  with  purged  eyesight."  Next 
winter  he  was  invited  to  come  from  Leipzig  and  share  the 
Christmas  festivities  of  the  Stropp  household  as  a  welcome 
guest.  His  letters  home  said  little  at  that  time — perhaps 
significantly  little — of  the  daughter  of  the  house,  but 
four  or  five  years  later  he  had  the  happiness  of  returning 
to  claim  her  as  his  bride. 

Neither  this  growing  attachment  nor  his  constant 
application  to  the  work  which  had  brought  him  to 
Germany  prevented  Seth  from  observing  the  political 
life  around  him.  The  old  Kaiser  had  not  long  before 
escaped  an  attempted  assassination,  and  great  cele 
brations  were  organised  to  mark  his  next  entry  into 
Berlin.  Seth  was  one  of  a  large  body  of  students  who 
marched  six  abreast  in  the  procession ;  but,  while 
ready  to  show  respect  to  the  Emperor  personally,  he 
had  little  liking  for  the  militarism  which  was  even  then 
dominant.  He  was  shocked  by  the  violent  ant i- Jewish 
feeling  of  the  day,  and  by  the  severe  Bismarckian  regime 
which  came  near  closing  the  university  reading-room 
because  two  or  three  journals  of  a  moderate  socialist 
type  were  found  there.  The  official  attitude  to  Socialism 
is  described  in  a  letter  to  Stalker,  which  brings  in  a 
name,  then  scarcely  known  in  Britain,  but  only  too 
well  known  a  generation  later  :— 

"  Treitschke's  standing  motto  against  the  possibility 
of  Socialism  is,  Keine  Kultur  ohne  Dienstboten — i.e.,  we 
must  have  a  lower  class  to  perform  the  menial  services  of 
life.  This  is  not  very  convincing,  for  there  is  no  degrada- 


MEMOIR  25 

tion  in  the  services  themselves ;  and,  as  someone 
remarked  to  me  :  Why  not  reverse  the  motto  and  say, 
Keine  Dienstboten  ohne  Kultur  ?  " 

At  the  end  of  this  winter  Seth  expressed  in  a  letter 
to  his  father  what  he  then  felt  about  a  lifetime  devoted 
to  the  study  of  philosophy  : — 

"  The  result  of  philosophy  is  to  show  us  how  much 
we  know,  and  how  much  it  is  absurd  to  expect  we 
should  know.  This  merit  of  philosophy  is  especially 
insisted  on  by  Kant.  For  the  rest,  there  is  no  need  to 
defend  philosophy,  as  it  has  always  existed  and  will 
continue  to  exist  so  long  as  men  continue  to  think.  .  .  . 
Nevertheless  after  a  certain  time  one  wishes  to  give  up 
'  thinking  about  thinking/  to  use  a  phrase  of  Carry le's, 
and  to  grapple  with  more  tangible  material — in  litera 
ture,  history,  politics,  &c.  I  would  not  care  to  go  on 
reading  pure  philosophy  all  my  life  or  for  very  many 
years." 

After  Easter  1879  Seth  went  on  to  Jena,  attracted, 
not  by  any  special  philosophical  teaching — the  day  of 
Eucken  was  not  yet — but  by  the  association  with 
Hegel,  the  opportunity  which  the  quiet  university  town 
of  about  8000  inhabitants  gave  for  hard  reading,  and 
the  neighbourhood  of  Weimar  and  the  Thiiringerwald. 
There  he  found  John  Haldane,  a  younger  brother  of 
his  friend,  studying  science,  and  a  group  of  Scots  theo 
logical  students  which  included  John  Herkless  and  Lewis 
Muirhead.1  Living  was  cheap  in  Jena — £i  a  week 
covered  everything — and  reserved  seats  in  the  little 
theatre  cost  only  6d.  Haldane  found  Seth  naturally  shy 
and  reserved,  and  only  gradually  came  to  know  him 
well ;  but  on  May  7  he  wrote  to  his  brother  Richard 
that  he  liked  Seth  much,  and  had  taken  him  to  Haeckel's 

1  I  owe  most  of  the  facts  in  the  two  following  paragraphs  to  Pro 
fessor  J.  S.  Haldane.  The  others  named  were  afterwards  known  as 
Principal  Sir  John  Herkless  of  St  Andrews  University  and  Dr  L.  A. 
Muirhead,  author  of  The  Eschatology  oj  Jesus. 


26  MEMOIR 

class.  Haeckel  began  with  "  a  sort  of  history  of  philo 
sophy/'  laying  much  stress  on  the  early  lonians,  especi 
ally  those  who  could  be  classed  as  Monists ;  and  he 
had  much  to  say  about  Kant's  nebular  hypothesis, 
but  nothing  about  his  philosophy.  "  He  is  a  capital 
lecturer,"  Haldane  added,  "  and  has  wonderful  eyes." 
But  the  beaux  yeux  of  Haeckel's  then  fashionable 
materialistic  Monism  did  not  tempt  Seth  away  from  his 
first  love  ;  and  his  approach  to  philosophy  remained  to 
the  end  what  Carlyle  and  Wordsworth  had  made  it- 
ethical  and  humanist,  rather  than  scientific. 

These  two  friends  soon  formed  with  the  Scottish 
students  of  theology  a  circle  which  met  for  two  hours  a 
week  to  read  Hegel's  Rechtsphilosophie.  It  was  from 
this  semester  that  Seth's  profound  knowledge  of  Hegel 
began,  though  he  confessed  to  Stalker  that  he  found  the 
Logik  "  an  utterly  inhuman  book."  His  letters  home 
told  of  a  formidable  working-day.  The  others  frequently 
tried  to  entice  him  out,  and  Muirhead's  triumph  was 
great  when  he  succeeded  in  bringing  Seth  down  from  the 
Absolute,  represented  by  Hegel,  to  "  the  concrete,"  in 
the  form  of  Lichtenhainer  or  some  other  light  beer  con 
sumed  in  a  country  biergarten  at  the  end  of  a  walk 
through  the  surrounding  woods.  On  these  long  walks 
many  questions  of  theology  as  well  as  philosophy  came 
under  review ;  and  the  lectures  which  Seth  most 
appreciated  during  this  summer  were  those  of  Hilgen- 
feld,  a  New  Testament  scholar  who  sought  to  correct 
the  critical  excesses  of  the  "  Tubingen  School "  a 
generation  before,  and  who  gave  him  a  new  sense  of  the 
vital  relation  between  the  life-history  of  St  Paul  and 
his  epistles. 

The  summer's  work  was  broken  by  a  visit  to  Weimar 
to  hear  the  Rheingold  and  Walkure,  then  seldom  per 
formed  even  in  Germany,  in  the  famous  little  theatre. 
At  Whitsuntide  Stalker,  who  was  studying  medicine  in 


MEMOIR  27 

Leipzig,  came  for  a  walking-tour  through  the  Thuringer- 
wald,  in  the  course  of  which  Ilmenau,  the  Wartburg  and 
other  famous  scenes  were  visited.  A  few  lines  may  be 
quoted  from  a  blank-verse  lyric  which  Seth  afterwards 
sent  to  his  companion,  which  suggest  that  he  had 
fallen  under  the  spell  of  Tennyson  as  well  as  that  of 
Wordsworth — 

Day  after  day  our  steps  lay  through  the  pines, 

Shut  in  a  valley-land  of  old  romance, 

Where  German  love  flowed  o'er  in  German  song 

That  lingers  still,  like  bird-notes  in  the  boughs. 

And  looking  from  some  hillside  on  the  woods, 

As  on  a  sea,  we  felt  our  life  till  now 

A  far-off  background,  like  the  circling  plain 

Seen  through  the  distance  in  the  sunny  haze. 

And  like  a  dim  noise  heard  through  dreams  by  one 

Who  lays  him  in  the  grass  beside  a  brook, 

And,  while  he  leans  his  head  upon  his  arm, 

Hears  still  the  axe's  stroke  deep  in  the  woods — 

So  dim  to  us  the  sounds  of  men  below, 

The  clash  of  creeds,  the  traffic  of  the  mart, 

The  sage  still  pressing  on  to  grasp  the  world 

And  read  the  great  God-mystery.    So  dim, 

Or  as  the  jangling  of  the  cattle-bells, 

Like  faery  music  heard  across  the  vale, 

They  lulled  us  in  our  dream. 

After  the  close  of  the  session  at  Jena  Seth  made  his 
way  by  Bayreuth  and  Nurnberg  to  Passau.  From  that 
splendidly  situated  old  town  he  went  down  the  Danube 
by  river  steamer,  and  from  Vienna  he  turned  westward 
to  the  Salzkammergut,  where  he  had  his  first  experience 
of  walking  in  the  Alps.  In  the  course  of  one  ascent  he 
was  overtaken  by  a  rainstorm,  which  reduced  his 
clothes  and  boots  to  a  sodden  and  pulp-like  condition. 
It  proved  a  matter  of  some  difficulty  to  secure  a  carriage 
to  drive  him  into  Salzburg,  where  his  luggage  with  a 
much-needed  change  of  raiment  awaited  him ;  and 


28  MEMOIR 

he  wrote  that  in  his  soaked  and  collarless  state  he  was 
sure  he  had  been  taken  for  a  tramp. 

After  a  short  visit  to  Scotland  he  returned  for  a 
winter  in  Leipzig  and  a  summer  with  Schurman  in 
Gottingen,  which  in  some  ways  repeated  the  history 
of  his  year  in  Berlin  and  Jena.  A  hard  winter  of  the 
Central  European  type  gave  notable  opportunities  of 
skating.  Music  was  a  great  and  growing  delight ;  and 
philosophy  allowed  him  a  margin  of  leisure  to  take 
advantage  of  the  musical  gifts  of  the  family  with  whom 
he  lodged,  as  well  as  of  concert  and  opera.  A  Mozart 
cycle  and  his  first  hearing  of  Siegfried  especially  delighted 
him.  Muirhead  was  with  him  at  both  universities, 
and  together  they  continued  to  read  Hegel,  and  quoted 
Faust  in  Auerbach's  Keller.  Eight  volumes  of  Fichte 
joined  the  Kant  and  Hegel  on  his  bookshelf,  and  occu 
pied  much  of  his  time  through  the  early  months  of  1880. 
At  the  same  time  he  built  up  a  library  of  German 
literature,  giving  special  attention  to  lyrical  and  ballad 
poetry ;  and  as  he  was  buying  books  for  Schurman  as 
well,  the  bookseller  treated  him  with  marked  respect. 
When,  as  already  mentioned,  he  revisited  Berlin  as  the 
guest  of  the  Stropp  family,  he  saw  somewhat  more  of 
Schurman,  and  wrote  to  Stalker  regarding  him  :  {<  He 
is  a  thoroughly  good  fellow,  always  fresh  and  enthusi 
astic.  I  had  the  greatest  interest  in  talking  to  him  : 
my  heart  warmed  within  me,  even  to  the  extent  of  wish 
ing  to  write  my  Hibbert  essay."  Schurman  took  him 
twice  to  Zeller's  house,  where  he  was  impressed  by  the 
gracious  personalities  of  both  Zeller  and  his  wife — a 
daughter  of  the  leader  of  the  Tubingen  School,  Ferdinand 
Christian  Baur.  Of  Zeller  he  wrote  : — 

"He  is  a  simple,  unassuming  old  man ;  Schurman 
says  he  is  one  of  the  few  Germans  who  seem  to  have  a 
real  interest  in  philosophical  problems  as  living  ques 
tions.  .  .  .  Most,  you  know,  look  at  them  in  a  dead, 


MEMOIR  29 

'  history  of  philosophy  '  way.  ...  Zeller  seems  to  be 
very  much  at  one  with  Strauss  on  most  points — at  least 
in  spirit.  Strauss  was  little  more  than  mentioned,  but 
one  could  trace  the  almost  affectionate  reverence  with 
which  he  looked  to  him  as  to  a  more  brightly  gifted 
spirit.  It  was  apropos  of  a  letter  he  had  written  to 
Strauss  urging  him  to  undertake  a  life  of  Lessing." 

It  was  the  fame  of  Hermann  Lotze  which  chiefly 
drew  Seth,  Muirhead  and  Schurman  to  Gottingen,  and 
Seth  had  heard  much  of  it  from  R.  B.  Haldane,  who  had 
studied  there  six  years  before.  Schurman  was  already 
an  enthusiastic  admirer,  and  infected  his  companions 
with  his  own  high  hopes  of  what  they  might  gain  from 
the  one  great  German  idealist  of  that  epoch.  But, 
looking  back  after  fifty  years,  Dr  Schurman  writes  : 
"  Unfortunately  the  great  man  gave  in  the  summer 
semester  of  1880  only  elementary  courses  for  beginners, 
and  he  had  no  seminar.  After  a  short  time  we  dropped 
out  of  the  lectures,  and  concentrated  on  the  writing  of 
our  theses  for  the  Hibbert  Trustees.  .  .  .  We  owed  much 
to  Gottingen — but  nothing  to  the  professors."  1  This 
estimate  may  be  supplemented  by  sentences  from  two 
letters  to  Stalker.  On  April  25,  soon  after  reaching 
Gottingen,  Seth  wrote  :  "  We  have  heard  two  lectures 
of  Lotze's  on  Praktischen  Philosophic.  His  face  has  the 
quaint  old-fashioned  intelligence  of  a  little  shoemaker, 
but  is  sweet  in  its  expression.  .  .  .  The  Metaphysik  we 
leave  because  it  would  break  up  the  forenoon,  and  read 
his  book  instead."  Two  months  later  he  recorded  a 
visit  to  Lotze,  who  was  busy  revising  his  Logik. 
"  Mill  he  called  a  langweiliger  Schwdtzer,  and  said  one 
could  not  afford  to  publish  books  like  the  Logic  in 
Germany."  "  I  have  read,"  the  passage  concludes, 

1  Quoted  by  J.  B.  Capper  in  his  Biographical  Sketch  of  Pringle- 
Pattison — Proc.  of  British  Academy,  Vol.  xvii.  But  cf.  Haldane's 
notable  tribute  to  Lotze,  Selected  Addresses  and  Essays,  pp.  186-7. 


30  MEMOIR 

"  more  than  half  the  Metaphysik,  most  of  it  with  sober 
profit/' 

Seth's  attitude  to  Fichte  at  this  time  was  not  dis 
similar,  for  a  certain  impatience  had  followed  the 
enthusiasm  of  his  first  deep  plunge  into  Fichte 's  thought 
the  previous  winter,  and  he  found  it  "  growingly  unsatis 
factory/'  while  it  proved  a  toilsome  matter  to  make  an 
abstract  of  the  Wissenschaftslehre.  Yet  both  Fichte  and 
Lotze  left  a  deep  imprint  on  his  thinking,  Fichte  by  the 
intensely  ethical  character  of  his  thought,  and  Lotze  by 
his  "  undaunted  reassertion  of  the  fundamental  truth 
of  the  view  of  the  world  implied  in  moral  or  spiritual 
experience."  The  permanence  of  Lotze's  influence  in 
particular  is  shown  by  the  frequent  references  in  Seth's 
later  writings  ;  and  his  deliberate  judgment  was  that 
Lotze  had  "  exercised  a  more  pervasive  influence  than 
usually  falls  to  the  lot  of  any  one  who  is  not  a  thinker 
of  first-rate  originality  and  genius."  1 

Seth's  attitude  to  Hegel  at  the  end  of  his  Lehrjahr 
in  Germany  can  also  be  gathered  from  the  letter  to 
Stalker  last  quoted  :  "  My  essay  is  probably  much  more 
Hegelian  in  tone  than  I  am  myself,  but  it  will  only 
modestly  insist  towards  the  end  that  Hegel  did  not 
know  everything.  .  .  .  The  prevailing  sentiment  of  the 
philosophical  detachment  of  the  Gottingen  brigade  is 
that  passage  in  Faust  (alas,  in  Mephistopheles'  mouth)— 

'  Grau,  theuerer  Freund,  ist  alle  Theorie, 
Und  griin  des  Lebens  goldener  Baum.' 

When  shall  we  be  able  to  pluck  and  eat  of  the  fruit 
of  that  tree  ?  " 

Seth  had  an  opportunity  of  relaxing  from  the  intense 
application  of  these  two  years  during  some  pleasant 

1  The  Philosophical  Radicals,  and  other  Essays,  p.  150 — from  a 
review  of  Jones'  Philosophy  of  Lotze,  originally  published  in  1895. 


MEMOIR  31 

weeks  spent  in  Paris  in  the  early  autumn  of  this  year. 
He  was  joined  by  Capper,  who  had  for  some  time  been 
on  the  staff  of  the  Times,  and  in  his  welcome  company 
was  able  to  compare  the  dramatic  art  of  the  Theatre 
frangais  with  that  of  Leipzig  and  Berlin ;  nor  did  his 
love  of  things  German  blunt  his  sense  of  the  charm  of 
France.  But  at  this  point  we  must  follow  out  the  history 
of  the  Hibbert  essay,  which  had  gradually  taken  shape 
at  Gottingen. 

Its  title  then  was  "  The  Permanent  Results  of  the 
Kantio-Hegelian  Philosophy  "  ;  but  before  its  publica 
tion  early  in  1882  the  title  was  altered  to  "  The  Develop 
ment  from  Kant  to  Hegel/'  and  at  the  special  request 
of  the  Trustees  a  second  section  was  added  on  the  Phil 
osophy  of  Religion  in  the  two  great  idealists.  The  book 
has  been  long  out  of  print ;  but  the  chapters  on  the 
Philosophy  of  Religion  were  reprinted  by  the  author 
twenty-five  years  later  in  The  Philosophical  Radicals. 

The  first  impression  that  the  book  makes  is  that  of  a 
clearness  and  maturity  very  notable  in  an  author, 
still  under  twenty-five,  who  is  faced  by  a  complex  and 
abstract  subject.  The  gift  of  lucid  exposition  which 
marked  all  his  writings  is  already  fully  developed.  The 
chapter  on  Fichte,  which  cost  him  so  much  labour, 
is  the  longest  in  the  book,  and  is  a  model  of  clear  state 
ment  and  tempered  appreciation  and  criticism.  The 
chapter  on  Schelling  alone  makes  a  somewhat  strict 
demand  on  the  reader's  attention,  for  even  Seth's  skill 
as  expositor  was  hardly  equal  to  the  task  of  making  his 
philosophy  in  its  varied  phases  easily  intelligible  in 
sixteen  pages.  But  when  he  passes  to  Hegel  he  is  on 
ground  which,  difficult  as  it  is,  he  has  thoroughly 
explored,  and  over  which  he  moves  with  freedom. 

The  fact  that  Seth  had  already  grasped  clearly  the 
main  principles  of  his  future  thinking  and  teaching 
may  be  shown  by  two  quotations,  one  from  each  section 


32  MEMOIR 

of  the  book.  In  his  opening  pages  Seth  deals  with  Kant's 
doctrine  of  the  thing-in-itself,  and  asks  whether  "  the 
Kantian  demand  to  know  noumena  as  something 
behind,  and  different  from,  phenomena,  is  anything 
more  than  the  desire  to  know  and  not  to  know  a  thing 
at  the  same  time,"  and  continues  :  "  For,  if  we  merely 
exchange  human  thought  for  some  other  kind  of  thought, 
we  are  no  better  off  than  before  as  regards  a  knowledge 
of  realities,  seeing  that  the  realities,  in  being  known, 
must  be  equally  coloured  by  the  nature  of  this  new 
thought."  This  argument  that,  while  we  try  to  criticise 
and  systematise  our  knowledge,  we  must  accept  know 
ledge  so  criticised  as  a  true  avenue  to  the  reality  of 
things,  and  not  as  a  misleading  screen  separating  us 
for  ever  from  them,  runs  through  all  Seth's  writing  on 
epistemology  ;  and  not  less  characteristic  in  another 
sphere  is  his  account  of  the  relation  between  the  ethical 
and  the  religious  consciousness.  Without  religious 
experience,  he  contends,  man  "is  an  atom  struggling 
in  vain  with  the  evil  of  his  own  nature,  and  possibly,  too, 
with  the  misery  of  surrounding  circumstances.  If  he 
is  to  be  successful  in  the  struggle,  he  must  be  persuaded 
that  he  is  not  alone,  or,  in  the  language  of  religion,  that 
God  is  for  him,  and  that  nothing,  therefore,  can  be 
ultimately  against  him.  The  triumph  that  he  only 
anticipates  in  himself  and  others  he  must  conceive  as 
secure  of  fulfilment — in  fact,  as  already  fulfilled  in  the 
eternal  purpose  of  God."  l 

1  The  Philosophical  Radicals,  p.  270. 


33 


CHAPTER   III. 

EDINBURGH   AND   CARDIFF. 

1880-1887. 

IT  was  natural  that  Seth's  brilliant  record  up  to  this 
point  should  gain  him  a  post  as  a  teacher  of  philosophy, 
and  several  months  before  he  returned  from  Germany 
he  was  asked  by  Professor  Campbell  Fraser  to  succeed 
his  friend,  W.  R.  Sorley,  in  the  position  of  class  assistant 
in  Logic  and  Metaphysics.  He  readily  accepted,  and  his 
work  in  this  capacity  began  in  the  late  autumn  of  1880. 
A  distinction  which  fell  to  him  at  this  time  was  the 
Ferguson  Philosophical  Scholarship.  It  was  much 
prized,  as  being  open  to  graduates  with  Honours  in 
Philosophy  of  the  four  Scottish  universities.  In  holding 
it  he  was  preceded  by  R.  B.  Haldane,  and  in  1882  his 
brother  James  gained  the  same  honour.  In  this  con 
nection  Lord  Haldane  tells  in  his  Autobiography  an 
incident  which  illustrates  Andrew  Seth's  scrupulous 
loyalty  to  his  friends.  Haldane  had  decided  to  take 
the  Degree  of  Doctor  of  Science  in  Philosophy,  the  only 
higher  degree  then  open  in  Edinburgh  to  students  with 
philosophical  honours.  He  submitted  for  the  purpose 
a  thesis  on  Immortality,  which  was  turned  down  by  the 
examiners — on  the  instance,  strangely,  of  a  professor 
of  Science  with  strictly  orthodox  religious  views — not 
because  it  was  philosophically  incompetent,  but  because 

c 


34  MEMOIR 

it  was  theologically  heterodox.  Seth,  he  adds,  was 
so  moved  by  his  friend's  experience  that  he  refused 
to  send  in  a  thesis  of  his  own  for  this  degree. 

In  a  letter  to  Stalker,  Seth  speaks  of  an  esssay  on 
Immortality  by  Haldane — presumably  embodying  the 
chief  part  of  the  rejected  thesis — as  "  indirect  in  treat 
ment/'  but  "  a  very  closely  and  strongly  reasoned 
essay."  A  passage  in  another  letter  to  the  same  friend 
towards  the  end  of  1882  indicates  his  attitude  to  a 
question  constantly  discussed  in  the  seventies.  Referring 
to  Seeley's  Ecce  Homo  he  says  :  "  Being  fresh  from 
Matthew  Arnold  I  struck  at  the  acceptance  of  miracles 
in  the  earlier  part  of  the  book.  Now  one  can  approach 
all  these  things  in  a  more  objective  and  historic 
interest. " 

Seth's  work  as  assistant  to  Professor  Fraser  was 
largely  tutorial,  and  involved  much  correcting  of 
examination  papers.  It  was  congenial,  in  that  it  brought 
him  into  close  touch  with  his  old  teacher,  and  placed 
him  in  a  line  of  men  who  were  rapidly  gaining  positions 
of  influence  in  the  philosophical  world.  But  it  gave 
little  opportunity  for  independent  lecturing,  and  the 
salary  was  only  £40.  So  he  turned  to  journalism  to 
supplement  it.  J.  B.  Capper  gave  him  an  introduction 
to  Charles  Cooper,  an  able  and  forceful  Yorkshireman, 
then  editor  of  the  Scotsman.  From  reviewing  volumes 
of  poetry  and  philosophy,  Cooper  soon  promoted  Seth 
to  the  writing  of  leading  articles,  and  for  nearly  two 
years  he  contributed  largely  along  both  lines.  Nor  were 
either  reviews  or  leaders  of  a  flimsy  nature.  A  column 
and  a  quarter  (about  1200  words)  was  the  standard 
length  ;  for  the  newspaper  reader  of  that  period  had 
greater  determination  and  fewer  distractions  than  his 
easily  wearied  successor  of  to-day. 

Cooper  expressed  privately  his  warm  admiration  for 
Seth's  journalistic  gifts ;  and  during  one  vacation 


MEMOIR  35 

month — July  1882,  the  month  of  the  bombardment  of 
Alexandria — when  he  was  almost  unassisted  in  his 
editorial  work,  he  asked  Seth  to  come  down  night  after 
night  to  work  at  the  office.  The  harvest  of  that  month's 
work  included  twenty-one  leaders  of  the  length  named. 
Regarding  German  politics  he  was  naturally  well 
informed,  and  the  following  is  worth  quoting  as  an 
example  of  his  foresight.  Bismarck,  he  writes  in  May 
1881,  "  has  created  a  position  so  unique  that  it  is  next 
to  impossible  to  imagine  Germany  without  him.  His 
retirement  or  death,  when  it  occurs,  will  inevitably 
throw  more  power  into  the  hands  of  the  Parliamentary 
parties  ;  but  they  have  been  tutored  into  submission 
so  long  that,  when  the  strong  hand  is  removed,  they 
may  be  expected  to  stagger  considerably  before  righting 
themselves." 

In  addition  to  foreign  politics  the  young  leader- 
writer  was  turned  loose  on  the  field  of  Scots  ecclesi- 
asticism,  and  took  full  advantage  of  the  then  attitude 
of  the  Scotsman  to  pillory  the  "  unco  guid,"  the  ultra- 
orthodox  and  the  extreme  wing  of  Sabbatarians.  A 
leader  which  combines  sarcasm  with  psychological 
insight  is  on  the  Meeting  of  Extremes,  in  which  he 
compares  the  characteristics  of  the  farthest  right  wing 
of  the  Scottish  Kirk  with  those  of  the  Communist  left 
in  French  politics,  and  tells  a  pleasant  story  of  two 
French  Communists  who,  wishing  to  mark  their  son 
as  a  true  revolutionist,  decided  to  call  him  Lucifer 
Blanqui  Vercingetorix,  and  were  virtuously  indignant 
when  the  maire  of  their  commune  refused  to  register  a 
child  so  amazingly  named.  Another  leader,  with  the 
titles  "  Cardinals  Begg  and  Manning,"  points  out  how 
much  there  was  in  common  between  the  ultramontanism 
of  Dr  Begg,  a  once  famous  Edinburgh  minister  of  extreme 
orthodoxy,  and  that  of  Cardinal  Manning,  who  had 
claimed  in  a  sermon  delivered  in  Glasgow  that  Scotland 


36  MEMOIR 

traditionally  possessed  not  a  few  characteristic  notes  of 
Catholic  truth. 

In  a  graver  mode  are  two  other  contributions  to  the 
Scotsman — the  first  a  leader  on  the  death  of  Carlyle, 
published  in  February  1881  ;  the  other,  a  long  and 
elaborate  critique  of  Parsifal,  written  after  a  visit  to 
Bayreuth  eighteen  months  later.  Only  a  few  sentences 
can  be  quoted  from  the  conclusion  of  each. 

"  Carlyle  was  often  unjust  to  the  spirit  of  constitu 
tionalism  and  of  science,  and  he  made  light  of  their 
triumphs.  But  his  impassioned  denunciations  were 
able  to  do  no  harm  to  what  is  good  in  these  two  great 
tendencies  of  modern  life,  while  they  had  their  use  in 
impressing  on  men  the  essential  importance  of  personal 
worth  and  effort  as  the  sole  source  of  moral  health.  .  .  . 
Many  will  remember  at  this  time  the  noble  words  he 
spoke  on  the  death  of  his  own  great  master,  Goethe, 
and  will  feel  that  here  again  they  stand  at  the  end  of 
'  the  being  and  the  working  of  a  faithful  man/  Like 
Goethe,  he  had  touched  the  extreme  limit  of  human 
life,  and  in  his  case,  too,  the  end  came  gently.  His 
work  remains,  and  the  lessons  he  has  taught  us,  even 
when  the  voice  that  uttered  them  is  dumb/' 

Of  Parsifal  Seth  wrote :  "  Wagner  has  certainly 
aimed  very  high.  Whether  he  has  produced  a  work 
which  is  an  artistic  whole,  I  can  hardly  say.  ...  A 
dramatic  character  must  certainly  be  denied  to  the 
work.  The  action  that  takes  place  is  purely  symbolical, 
and  the  interest  of  the  hearer  is  concentrated  on  what 
may  be  called  the  decorative  parts  of  the  music — on 
the  double  celebration  of  the  sacrament,  the  march  of 
Gurnemann  and  Parsifal  to  the  temple  in  the  first  act, 
and  the  sanctified  glory  of  the  spring  in  the  third.  In 
the  whole  of  the  last  act,  indeed,  there  is  nothing  which 
we  would  willingly  part  with  in  the  music.  But  this 
bears  out  the  criticism  just  made,  for  the  act  is  simply 


MEMOIR  37 

a  succession  of  religious  offices."  After  drawing  a  parallel 
with  the  Second  Part  of  Faust,  the  writer  concluded : 
"  Wagner's  musical  genius  has  saved  him  to  a  great 
extent  in  spite  of  himself ;  but  in  adventuring  upon  the 
arid  ground  of  a  carefully  calculated  symbolism,  he  has 
certainly  entered  a  territory  dangerous  to  art." 

These  extracts  show  something  of  the  range  of  Seth's 
interests  at  this  time  ;  yet  he  found  time  for  other 
varied  activities  in  the  summer  and  autumn  of  1882. 
For  three  weeks  he  took  the  senior  Greek  classes  in  the 
Royal  High  School  while  the  rector  was  absent,  and 
reported  that  he  had  "  kept  order  and  learned  a  great 
deal  of  Greek,"  but  that,  though  he  felt  he  had  got  on 
well  with  the  boys,  he  was  not  drawn  to  the  career  of 
a  schoolmaster.  After  returning  from  Bayreuth  by 
Treves  and  Paris,  he  joined  the  Campbell  Frasers  at 
Grasmere.  He  found  there  J.  W.  Mackail,  a  friend  and 
class-fellow  of  five  years  before,  and  with  his  hosts  met 
Matthew  Arnold  at  Fox  How. 

About  the  same  time  reviews  of  From  Kant  to  Hegel 
began  to  arrive  from  both  sides  of  the  Atlantic,  and  to 
his  great  amusement  a  professor  from  Providence,  N.J., 
making  a  round  of  celebrities  in  the  British  universities, 
appeared  on  the  author's  doorstep.  In  autumn  he 
summoned  up  courage  to  advertise  a  series  of  lectures 
for  the  ladies  of  Edinburgh  on  English  poetry,  and  wrote 
to  Stalker  of  the  embarrassment  which  he  felt  when  a 
large  number  of  their  mutual  friends  enrolled  for  the 
class  :  "  Think  also  of  lecturing  on  Don  Juan  next 
Monday  in  these  circumstances.  Your  prayers,  lieber 
Freund,  your  prayers  !  " 

A  venture  of  greater  importance  undertaken  at  the 
same  time  was  a  volume  of  Philosophical  Essays.  To 
understand  its  origin  we  must  go  back  to  the  previous 
year,  1881,  when  a  group  of  young  Hegelians,  including 
Adamson,  Seth  and  R.  B.  Haldane,  felt  that  some 


38  MEMOIR 

step  must  be  taken  to  show  their  profound  dissatisfaction 
with  the  conduct  of  Mind,  under  the  editorship  of  Pro 
fessor  Groom  Robertson.  Its  general  attitude  was  that 
of  the  empiricism  so  long  dominant  in  England ;  nor 
was  this  unnatural,  as  it  had  been  founded,  and  was 
largely  financed  and  its  policy  controlled,  by  Alexander 
Bain,  who  since  the  death  of  John  Stuart  Mill  had  been 
the  recognised  leader  of  Associationist  thought.  In 
their  desire  for  a  fuller  opportunity  than  was  granted 
in  its  pages  for  the  exposition  of  their  own  philosophical 
faith,  the  younger  idealists  had  the  moral  support  of 
T.  H.  Green,  Edward  Caird  and  Wallace  ;  and  it  would 
appear  that  Sidgwick  and  Campbell  Eraser  gave  them  a 
more  guarded  encouragement.  For  a  time  the  two 
youngest  of  the  group,  Seth  and  Haldane,  thought  of 
starting  a  new  philosophical  journal ;  but  by  the  spring 
of  the  following  year  they  had  exchanged  this  plan  for 
that  of  a  volume  which  might  serve  in  some  manner  as 
a  manifesto  of  the  younger  idealists.  This  more  modest 
scheme  proved  acceptable  to  those  who  controlled  the 
policy  of  Mind,  and  Croom  Robertson,  who  had  been 
vigorously  assailed  by  Seth  in  his  letters  to  Haldane  a 
few  months  before,  promised  to  do  what  he  could  to 
further  it. 

At  this  point,  on  March  26,  1882,  Thomas  Hill  Green 
died  in  his  forty-sixth  year  ;  and  this  event  formed  one 
of  the  foci  round  which  the  thought  of  the  essayists 
finally  found  its  orbit,  as  the  centenary  of  the  publica 
tion  of  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  formed  the  other. 
In  reprinting  twenty-five  years  later  his  own  essay  on 
"  Philosophy  as  Criticism  of  Categories,"  with  which 
the  volume  opened,  Seth  wrote  as  follows  :  "It  was  the 
first  paper  in  a  volume  of  Essays  in  Philosophical  Criti 
cism,  published  in  1883,  m  somewhat  belated  con 
nection  with  the  centenary  of  the  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason.  The  volume  was  dedicated  to  the  memory  of 


MEMOIR  39 

Thomas  Hill  Green,  who  died  in  the  previous  year,  and 
some  prefatory  pages  by  Dr  Edward  Caird  contained  a 
fine  tribute  to  the  spirit  of  Green's  life  and  teaching.  .  .  . 
The  second  essay,  on  '  The  Relation  of  Philosophy  to 
Science/  was  the  work  of  the  present  Secretary  of  State 
for  War,  in  collaboration  with  his  brother,  Dr  J.  S. 
Haldane.  The  other  contributors  were  (to  give  them 
their  later  titles)  Professor  Bernard  Bosanquet,  Pro 
fessor  W.  R.  Sorley,  Professor  W.  P.  Ker,  Professor 
Henry  Jones,  Dr  James  Bonar,  Professor  T.  B.  Kil- 
patrick  of  Knox  College,  Toronto,  and  the  late  Professor 
D.  G.  Ritchie  of  St  Andrews.  This,  it  will  be  admitted, 
was  a  band  of  which  the  editors  had  no  reason  to  be 
ashamed.  The  ideas  of  the  book  were  then  compara 
tively  unfamiliar,  and  the  writing  of  the  youthful 
authors  was  often,  perhaps,  unnecessarily  difficult,  but 
the  critics  were  at  least  unanimous  in  recognising  the 
sincerity  and  scientific  purpose  which  animated  the 
volume/' l 

The  estimate  in  the  last  sentence  quoted  describes 
with  accuracy  Seth's  introductory  essay.  The  idea  of 
Philosophy  as  making  clear  the  order  and  relation  of 
the  various  forms  of  knowledge  by  criticising  the  cate 
gories  which  they  habitually  use  has  often  been  worked 
out  since  ;  but  it  had  then  the  merit  of  freshness,  though 
his  statement  of  it  showed,  as  he  himself  hints,  less  than 
the  usual  lucidity  of  his  philosophical  writing.  In  the 
Preface  to  the  volume,  Dr  Edward  Caird  stated  that 
the  essays  were  written  quite  independently,  and  that 
the  unity  which  ran  through  the  volume  was  due  to 
"  a  certain  community  of  opinion  in  relation  to  the 
general  principle  and  method  of  philosophy/'  The 
double  origin  of  the  book  naturally  influenced  its  char 
acter.  Its  connection  with  the  centenary  of  the  Critique 
showed  itself  in  the  attention  paid  to  the  Kantian 
1  Preface  to  The  Philosophical  Radicals. 


40  MEMOIR 

theory  of  Knowledge,  a  field  in  which  Seth  had  already 
shown  himself  an  expert.  But  more  important  was  its 
character  as  a  tribute  to  the  memory  of  T.  H.  Green. 
The  pervasiveness  and  depth  of  his  influence  stand  out 
clearly  when  we  recall  that  his  two  most  important 
works,  the  Prolegomena  to  Ethics  and  the  Principles  of 
Political  Obligation,  were  only  published  from  his 
lecture  notes  after  the  essays  were  written,  and  that 
only  four  of  the  ten  essayists  had  come  under  his  per 
sonal  influence  at  Oxford.  Yet  the  spirit  of  Green's 
idealism  runs  through  the  volume ;  and  its  editors 
might  well  feel  that,  in  bringing  their  notable  band  of 
contributors  together  within  six  months  of  his  death, 
they  had  raised  a  fitting  monument  to  one  of  the  greatest 
teachers  of  ethics — of  moral  philosophy  in  the  fullest 
sense — that  England  has  ever  known. 

One  incidental  advantage  to  Seth  was  that  part  of 
the  editorial  work  was  done  during  a  visit  to  the  Hal- 
danes'  home  at  Cloan ;  and  this  beautiful  spot  on  the 
slope  of  the  Ochils,  looking  across  Strathearn  north  and 
west  to  the  higher  hills  of  the  Grampian  range,  became 
a  frequent  scene  of  holiday  visits  in  later  years.  Another 
friendship  which  proved  a  decisive  factor  in  his  life 
began  at  this  time.  He  had  been  impressed  by  reading 
Mr  A.  J.  Balfour 's  Defence  of  Philosophic  Doubt,  pub 
lished  originally  in  1879,  and  wrote  to  the  young  phil 
osopher-statesman  inviting  him  to  give  an  address  to 
the  Edinburgh  University  Philosophical  Society,  of 
which  we  have  already  heard.  Mr  Balfour  agreed  to 
come,  and  a  lasting  friendship  between  the  two  thinkers 
was  established,  one  early  fruit  of  which  was  the  founda 
tion  of  the  Balfour  Philosophical  Lectureship  which 
will  be  described  in  the  next  chapter. 

By  the  year  1883,  Seth  was  anxious  to  secure  an 
independent  position.  Young  as  he  was,  his  name  had 
already  become  widely  known ;  and  for  a  time  he 


MEMOIR  41 

thought  of  accepting  a  chair  in  California.  But  an 
opening  occurred  nearer  home  through  the  foundation 
of  a  philosophical  chair  in  Cardiff.  The  steps  by  which 
Seth  came  to  hold  it  may  be  told  in  the  words  of  one 
who  became  a  lifelong  friend,  Miss  Price,  afterwards 
Mrs  Harding :  "  My  father  was  one  of  the  Gover 
nors  of  the  newly  founded  University  of  South  Wales 
and  Monmouthshire  in  which  we  were  all  keenly  inter 
ested  ;  and  he  came  home  from  the  meeting  at  which 
Viriamu  Jones  had  been  appointed  Principal  full  of 
admiration  for  the  Scotch  philosopher  who  had  also 
put  in  for  the  post/'  But  the  chair  of  Philosophy  to 
which  Seth  was  appointed  was  much  better  adapted  to 
his  bent  than  the  administrative  work  of  the  principal- 
ship  would  have  been.  Mrs  Harding  goes  on  to  describe 
the  excitement  in  the  quiet  town  of  Cardiff  when  all 
the  new  life  poured  into  it.  Mr  Price  was  a  great  reader 
of  philosophy,  and  as  in  those  days  hardly  anyone  in 
Cardiff  shared  his  enthusiasm,  he  took  the  earliest 
opportunity  to  make  Seth's  acquaintance,  and  enrolled 
as  a  student  of  the  new  college  in  order  to  attend  Seth's 
lectures,  which  he  much  valued  and  enjoyed.  He  often 
spoke  of  the  perfection  of  his  language,  and  said  that 
if  the  professor  paused  it  was  never  for  lack  of  a  word, 
but  because  he  was  choosing  between  several  the  one 
which  would  most  accurately  express  his  meaning. 

Among  his  colleagues  was  one  who  was  already  a 
friend — W.  P.  Ker,  in  later  years  Professor  of  English 
Literature  in  University  College,  London.  Ker  was  a 
brilliant  and  many-sided  man,  who  had  gone  from 
Glasgow  University  to  Balliol  as  Snell  Exhibitioner, 
and  who,  before  he  made  English  Literature  the 
subject  of  his  life  work,  was  assistant  to  Professor 
Sellar  in  the  Latin  chair  in  Edinburgh.  His  years  at 
Balliol  under  Green  and  A.  C.  Bradley  had  given  him  a 
deep  interest  in  the  Philosophy  of  Art — the  subject  of 


42  MEMOIR 

his  contribution  to  Essays  in  Philosophical  Criticism. 
Thus  Seth  and  Ker  had  many  links,  in  their  friendship 
for  the  Sellar  family,  in  their  idealist  creed,  and  in  their 
common  enthusiasm  for  literature,  classical  and  modern, 
but  especially  for  the  great  English  poets.  The  friend 
ship  cemented  in  the  four  years  of  close  co-operation  at 
Cardiff  lasted  unbroken  till  W.  P.  Ker's  death  in  1923. 
It  has  been  said  of  him  that  "  the  Cardiff  years,  strenuous 
as  they  were,  lived  on  in  his  memory  as  a  cheerful, 
not  to  say  '  jolly  '  affair  of  pioneers."  "  There  is  some 
thing  good  in  education/'  he  said  in  retrospect,  "  when 
it  beats  up  a  crew  of  adventurers  and  puts  them  in  a 
stockade  to  hold  against  the  enemy."  l 

Other  friendships  formed  in  Cardiff  were  with  Pro 
fessor  Claude  Thompson,  an  excellent  field  naturalist, 
whose  long  tramps  with  Ker  were  sometimes  shared  by 
Seth,  and  Mr  W.  P.  James,  afterwards  High  Bailiff  of 
Cardiff,  who  combined  with  legal  knowledge  a  keen 
and  alert  interest  in  philosophy.  As  was  natural  when 
a  university  college  had  been  newly  started  in  an  area 
mainly  industrial,  there  was  only  a  restricted  number  of 
students  who  could  fully  respond  to  such  teaching  as 
that  of  Seth  and  Ker ;  so  the  former  founded  a  senior 
class  of  men  who  had  passed  beyond  the  undergraduate 
stage.  Within  this  there  was  an  inner  circle  formed  for 
the  study  of  Hegel,  consisting  of  Seth,  Ker,  James  and 
Roberts,  then  Professor  of  Greek  at  Cardiff  and  after 
wards  Principal  at  Aberystwyth.  They  never  went 
beyond  the  Preface  to  the  Phenomenology  ;  but  of  that 
they  made  a  translation,  which  remained  to  show  the 
spirit  of  thoroughness  in  which  they  approached  that 
formidable  work.  Less  exacting  were  the  meetings  of 
a  literary  society  called  '  The  Fortnightly ' ;  and  there 

1  I  am  allowed  by  Mrs  John  MacCunn  to  quote,  here  and  later, 
from  a  privately  printed  memorial  volume,  written  by  her  husband 
and  herself,  entitled  Our  Friend,  W.  P. 


MEMOIR  43 

were  also  reading  parties  in  which  Seth  acted  as  one 
of  the  guides  into  the  arcana  of  Browning,  and  shared 
with  his  friends  his  own  enthusiasm  for  Heine. 

Cardiff  was  within  easy  reach  of  much  beautiful 
country  even  before  the  coming  of  the  motor ;  and 
Seth  often  walked  with  members  of  the  Price  family 
and  other  friends  over  the  heights  from  which  the  hills 
of  Somerset  and  Devon  could  be  seen  across  the  Bristol 
Channel.  On  clear  days  the  Brecon  Beacons  could  be 
seen  towering  to  the  north ;  and  the  younger  members 
of  the  party  looked  on  with  eagerness  and  amusement 
when  W.  P.  Ker  took  off  his  hat  to  the  mountains  of 
Wales.  Seth's  beard  already  gave  him  a  somewhat 
venerable  appearance  as  a  teacher,  but  Mrs  Harding 
recalls  him  on  these  hill  walks  as  "  tall,  lithe,  active, 
full  of  talk  and  fun." 

To  this  busy,  friendly  life  he  brought  his  bride  in  the 
autumn  of  1884,  and  she  was  warmly  welcomed  by  the 
whole  circle.  Andrew  Seth  and  Eva  Stropp  were 
married  in  Berlin  in  July,  and  James  Seth  went  from 
Jena,  where  he  was  studying,  to  support  his  brother 
on  this  occasion.  The  weeks  immediately  following  the 
wedding  were  spent  in  Eva's  home  country  of  Silesia. 
In  the  Riesengebirge  she  was  introduced  to  the  pleasures 
of  hill-climbing,  then  an  unfamiliar  occupation  for 
German  girls ;  and  from  Warmbrunn  they  went  on  to 
Gnadenfrei,  where  she  had  been  at  school  among  the 
Moravians.  "  We  wanted  to  visit  it  together,"  her 
husband  writes  to  his  mother.  "  It  lies  pleasantly  and 
is  very  quiet.  We  went  to  church  this  morning  to  the 
Herrnhuter  service.  The  large  hall  so  well  filled  was 
an  interesting  and  impressive  sight :  all  very  simple. 
The  only  drawback  we  found  was  that  we  had  to  go  in 
at  different  doors  and  sit  in  different  parts  of  the  church  " 
— truly  a  hard  fate  on  the  second  Sunday  of  their 
wedded  life. 


44  MEMOIR 

So  began  forty-four  years  of  unity  in  heart  and  pur 
pose,  and  so  was  laid  the  foundation  of  that  home  life 
whose  development  we  shall  trace  in  later  pages.  But 
if  this  year  brought  happiness  almost  unmingled,  that 
which  followed  brought  bereavement.  In  1885  Vera 
Margaret,  the  eldest  child  of  Andrew  and  Eva  Seth, 
was  born  and  died  at  Cardiff.  When  the  child's  illness 
had  become  serious,  the  father  wrote  to  a  friend  that 
he  was  "  weary  with  watching  and  anxiety,"  and  felt 
unable  to  meet  his  class.  A  few  days  before  Christmas 
the  end  had  come,  and  the  lives  of  the  parents  were 
deeply  marked  by  this  early  sorrow.  In  the  same  year 
the  death  of  Seth's  father  at  the  age  of  fifty-nine  broke 
up  the  home  in  Edinburgh  ;  and  in  1887,  after  James 
Seth  had  been  appointed  to  a  philosophical  chair  at 
Halifax,  Nova  Scotia,  his  mother  and  her  younger 
children  followed  him  to  make  their  home  for  a  time 
beyond  the  Atlantic.  Andrew  Seth  wrote  that  this 
parting  from  his  mother  seemed  "  almost  like  a  fore 
taste  of  the  final  separation  "  ;  but  happily,  as  a  later 
chapter  will  show,  the  parting  was  only  for  a  time. 

Before  the  Seths  left  Cardiff  another  German  bride 
joined  the  circle  of  friends  associated  with  University 
College.  Professor  W.  N.  Parker,  one  of  the  scientists 
on  the  staff,  married  a  daughter  of  the  famous  biologist, 
August  Weismann,  and  Mrs  Parker  naturally  received 
a  warm  welcome  from  her  fellow-countrywoman  and 
her  Scottish  husband. 

During  the  series  of  political  crises  in  the  years  1885 
and  1886,  Seth  had  little  difficulty  in  determining  his 
course.  His  recent  connection  with  the  Scotsman,  which 
now  took  a  strong  line  against  Home  Rule,  and  his 
growing  friendship  with  Mr  Balfour,  may  have  assisted 
him  to  do  so.  But  his  admiration  for  Mr  Gladstone  had 
always  been  of  a  qualified  kind,  and  he  now  wrote  that 
his  feelings  about  him  were  "  quite  unphilosophical." 


MEMOIR  45 

Yet  his  enthusiasm  for  the  Unionist  cause  was  not 
sufficient  to  take  him  to  a  meeting  addressed  by  Mr 
Balfour,  who  was  still  introduced  in  the  provinces  as 
"  a  nephew  of  Lord  Salisbury/'  Seth  was  content  to 
wait  at  home  till  the  speaker's  effort  was  over  and 
he  had  been  driven  round  a  great  part  of  Cardiff  by 
an  inefficient  cabman  who  had  no  idea  of  the  young 
professor's  whereabouts.  There  followed,  however,  a 
talk  on  philosophy,  prolonged  far  into  the  night. 

While  at  Cardiff  Seth  contributed  a  philosophical 
survey  twice  a  year  to  the  Contemporary  Review,  and 
also  wrote  several  articles  for  the  Ninth  Edition  of  the 
Encyclopaedia  Britannica.  One  of  these  is  mentioned 
in  a  letter  dated  November  30,  1886,  to  Dr  S.  S.  Laurie, 
the  first  Professor  of  Education  in  the  University  of 
Edinburgh,  to  whose  friendship  Seth  often  acknow 
ledged  his  debt,  as  well  as  to  Laurie's  Metaphysica  and 
other  philosophical  writings  :— 

"  I  delayed  acknowledging  your  Lectures  on  Univer 
sities  till  I  could  send  you  more  than  merely  a  message 
of  thanks.  ...  I  must  congratulate  you  on  the  pro 
duction  of  a  most  interesting  and  useful  book.  I  was 
specially  interested  in  all  you  say  about  mediaeval 
education,  because  I  had  some  imperfect  glimpses  at 
the  subject  by  the  way  in  reading  for  my  article 
'  Scholasticism  '  in  the  Britannica.  I  should  have  been 
quite  glad  to  have  had  it  then.  ...  I  venture  to 
think  it  is  well-timed  with  reference  to  the  movement 
of  University  Reform  in  Scotland  and  possible  legisla 
tion  in  the  near  future.  Nothing  could  be  better  at  such 
a  time  than  to  spread  some  knowledge  of  the  actual 
history  of  such  institutions. 

"  In  reference  to  what  you  say — '  We  may  yet  see 
restored  both  in  England  and  Scotland  the  hostels  of 
the  Middle  Ages  ' — it  may  be  of  interest  to  you  to  know 
that  the  question  of  establishing  a  hostel  for  men  has 


46  MEMOIR 

been  repeatedly  under  discussion  here,  the  very  name 
being  used.  We  have  one  for  women,  called  Aberdare 
Hall.  It  is  probable  that  in  course  of  time,  if  a  general 
hostel  is  not  established,  the  religious  bodies  may 
combine  to  have  a  hostel  (or  may  separately  estab 
lish  hostels)  for  theological  students  coming  to  us  for 
their  Arts  course.  At  Bangor,  I  believe,  the  Church 
has  already  established  such  a  hostel.  They  don't 
quite  trust  the  unlimited  freedom  of  the  Scotch  system 
here." 

From  Cardiff,  Seth's  eyes  were  often  turned  north 
ward  ;  and  though  the  part  of  his  life  spent  outside 
Scotland  was  relatively  small,  his  two  years  in  Germany 
and  four  years  in  South  Wales  prepared  him  in  many 
ways  for  his  notable  career  as  a  teacher  of  Philosophy 
in  the  universities  of  his  own  land. 


47 


CHAPTER   IV. 

THE   BALFOUR   LECTURES. 

1884-1891. 

DURING  Seth's  residence  in  Cardiff  he  began  to  be 
known  beyond  the  circle  of  specialists  in  philosophy  to 
whom  his  first  writings  were  addressed.  This  wider 
reputation  came  with  the  publication  of  Scottish  Philo 
sophy  in  1885,  followed  by  Hegelianism  and  Personality 
two  years  later.  The  latter  was  not,  indeed,  published 
until  shortly  after  his  appointment  to  St  Andrews 
University  in  the  autumn  of  1887,  but  the  lectures 
which  it  contained  were  given  before  he  left  Cardiff. 
Both  series  were  delivered  in  Edinburgh  University 
under  the  Balfour  Philosophical  Lectureship.  We  have 
seen  how  Mr  Balfour  was  invited  to  deliver  to  the 
University  Philosophical  Society  a  paper,  to  which  he 
referred  long  after  as  his  first  public  lecture  on  a  philo 
sophical  subject.  In  his  Chapters  of  Autobiography 
(Ch.  V.)  he  describes  the  sequel :  "  Out  of  this  Edinburgh 
episode  there  sprung  not  merely  the  personal  friendship 
to  which  I  have  referred,  but  also  an  arrangement  under 
which  Professor  Pringle-Pattison  delivered  two  sets  of 
'  Balfour '  Lectures,  one  devoted  to  Hegel,  the  other  to 
the  philosophers  of  the  Scottish  School.  Since  then  he 
has  made  contributions  to  our  philosophic  literature, 
original  in  matter  and  admirable  in  style.  But  surely 


48  MEMOIR 

the  full  promise  of  this  later  harvest  was  already  given 
in  the  two  modest  volumes  with  which  he  began  the 
series/' 

The  Balfour  Lectureship  was  unusual  in  that  it  was 
only  held — and  was  only  intended  to  be  held — by  one 
man.  Mr  Balfour  may  have  wished  to  help  forward 
a  scheme  then  under  discussion  for  the  delivery  of 
short  courses  of  special  lectures  within  the  University 
by  instituting  one  such  course ; x  but  his  main  object 
undoubtedly  was  to  draw  out,  or  at  least  to  hasten, 
the  original  contribution  which  he  felt  Seth  had  the 
power  to  make  to  philosophical  thought.  So  Seth 
twice  returned  from  Cardiff  to  deliver  these  courses  in 
his  old  University.  The  first  was  inscribed  "  gratefully 
and  affectionately  "  to  Professor  Campbell  Fraser,  who 
took  an  active  interest  in  the  progress  of  Mr  Balfour's 
generous  scheme. 

In  the  opening  paragraphs  of  Scottish  Philosophy  Seth 
indicates  that  his  choice  of  subject  has  been  in  part 
influenced  by  patriotism,  but  his  main  reason  is  that 
"  though  the  Idealists  are  constantly  discharging  their 
heavy  artillery  against  the  Empiricists  and  Agnostics, 
the  matter  does  not  seem,  somehow,  to  be  brought  to  a 
vital  issue  ;  the  cannonade  appears  to  pass  harmlessly 
over  the  enemy's  head."  This  difficulty  he  traces  in 
part  to  the  unfamiliar  and  highly  German  form  given 
by  the  Idealists  to  their  argument — which  suggests  that 
two  years'  teaching  in  Cardiff  had  increased  his  sense 
of  the  value  of  lucidity — and  he  expresses  the  hope 
that  "  some  progress  may  be  made  towards  bringing 
the  opposing  armies  within  fighting  range  of  one  another, 
if  we  turn  our  attention  nearer  home." 

With  this  in  view  he  proceeds  to  survey  the  dis 
integration  of  knowledge  in  the  development  from 
Locke  to  Hume,  and  ends  with  the  epigram  :  "  Scepti- 

1  Scottish  Philosophy,  Preface. 


MEMOIR  49 

cism  is  the  bridge  by  which  we  pass  from  one  system, 
or  family  of  systems,  found  wanting,  to  another  age 
with  its  fuller  grasp  of  truth/'  This  bridge — or  at  least 
some  arches  of  it — he  finds  in  the  neglected  writings  of 
Thomas  Reid ;  and  in  the  central  part  of  the  book  he 
sets  himself  to  "  interpret  the  much-abused  Reid  accord 
ing  to  his  better  self."  While  making  no  claim  that 
Reid's  writings  are  comparable  in  depth  or  originality 
to  those  of  Kant,  he  contends  that  Reid  grasped  the 
essential  point  of  any  effective  answer  to  Hume,  and 
that  his  "  vindication  of  perception  as  perception  "  and 
his  "  assertion  that  the  unit  of  knowledge  is  an  act  of 
judgment "  supply  important  parts  of  the  required 
answer. 

The  later  lectures  show  how  the  relativism  which 
still  remained  in  Kant's  Theory  of  Knowledge  reap 
peared  in  Sir  William  Hamilton,  against  whom  Seth 
argues  that  "  in  knowing  the  phenomenon,  we  know 
the  object  itself  through  and  through — so  far,  of  course, 
as  we  do  know  it,  so  far  as  it  really  has  become  a 
phenomenon  for  us."  In  the  closing  paragraphs  of  the 
book  he  adumbrates  a  position  which,  he  claims,  is  in 
line  with  the  best  traditions  in  Scottish  thought  as 
"  reversing  the  deductive  method  of  Fichte  and  Hegel." 
"  The  ultimate  unity  of  things  is  what  we  stretch  for 
ward  to,  what  we  divine,  but  what  we  never  fully  attain. 
It  is  our  terminus  ad  quern ;  it  is  never  so  fully  within  our 
grasp  that  we  can  make  it  in  turn  our  terminus  a  quo, 
and,  placing  ourselves,  as  it  were,  at  the  crisis  of  creation, 
proceed  to  deduce  step  by  step  the  characteristics  of 
actual  existence  in  nature  and  in  man."  l  This  last 
thought  was  one  to  which  Seth  often  recurred.2 

The  lectures  were  well  received,  and  no  tribute  can 

1  4th  ed.,  pp.  96,  176,  220. 

2  Cf.  Man's  Place  in  the  Cosmos,  pp.  191,  227,  242  f.  ;    The  Idea  of 
God,  p.  165  f. 

D 


50  MEMOIR 

have  given  their  author  more  satisfaction  than  that 
paid  by  the  founder  of  the  lectureship,  whose  appre 
ciation  was  expressed  in  a  letter  as  long  and  exhaustive 
as  a  review  article.  Seth  had  the  pleasure  laudari  a 
laudato  when  he  read  Mr  Balfour's  judgment  on  the 
style  :  "It  seems  to  me  as  nearly  perfect  as  a  philoso 
phical  style  can  be — concise  ;  agreeable  ;  extraordinarily 
lucid ;  never  unnecessarily  technical,  yet  never  sacri 
ficing  the  substance  to  the  phrase ;  with  none  of  the 
sonorous  prolixity  which  has  too  often  been  the  char 
acteristic  of  Lectures  on  Philosophy,  and  especially  (I 
am  afraid)  of  Scotch  Lectures  on  Philosophy."  The 
matter  of  the  lectures  received  the  same  generous  recog 
nition  ;  and  the  writer  went  on  to  point  out  various 
difficulties  not  yet  made  clear — such  as  the  bearing  of 
Seth's  view  of  knowledge  on  the  Law  of  Causation  and 
on  the  knowledge  of  other  selves — as  topics  which  might 
well  be  developed  in  a  further  course. 

There  is  one  criticism  of  Scottish  Philosophy  lying,  as 
it  were,  on  the  surface  which  demands  a  word  of  com 
ment.  It  may  be  asked  whether  it  is  not  a  paradox 
to  treat  Hume  and  Hamilton  as  being  outside  the  main 
current  of  the  Scottish  philosophical  tradition,  and 
whether  the  stream  does  not  reduce  itself  to  a  mere 
trickle  when  it  is  identified  with  the  thought  of  Reid 
and  Dugald  Stewart.  In  reply  it  may  be  pointed  out 
that  in  the  nineteenth  century,  especially  on  the  Conti 
nent,  the  '  common-sense '  school  founded  by  Reid 
was  regularly  referred  to  by  historians  of  philosophy 
as  the  distinctively  Scottish  one,  and  that  it  had  con 
siderable  influence  on  Cousin  and  others  in  France. 
But  it  is  more  important  to  note  that  in  Seth's  own 
view  it  had  not  ended  with  the  early  nineteenth  century, 
but  that,  especially  in  the  teaching  of  Campbell  Fraser, 
there  was  found  an  idealism  which  was  not  for  an 
intellectual  elite  only — an  idealism  which  preserved  the 


MEMOIR  51 

rights  of  the  common  man  by  interpreting  his  ethical 
and  religious  experience,  as  well  as  by  vindicating  the 
fundamental  trustworthiness  of  his  knowledge  of  the 
external  world.  In  this  movement  Seth  now  definitely 
took  his  place. 

His  early  works  were  all  largely  occupied  in  treating 
the  Kantian  theory  of  knowledge  ;  and  a  letter  to  Mr 
W.  P.  James  in  March  1886  shows  the  spirit,  at  once 
sane  and  humorous,  in  which  he  regarded  the  task  of 
interpretation  :— 

"  Certainly  the  phenomenalism  and  dualism  are  not 
the  valuable  part  of  Kant ;  they  have  to  be  dropped, 
if  we  are  going  to  get  any  further.  But  they  are  so 
patently  there  in  the  historical  individual  called  Kant 
that  one  wearies  eventually  of  persistent  attempts  to 
minimise  them.  It  is  of  no  use  to  say  '  This  is  Kant/ 
when  somebody  else  constructs  you  quite  another  Kant 
and  refuses  to  accept  yours.  The  feeling  then  comes 
to  be — show  him  for  once  as  he  is  with  all  his  imper 
fections  on  his  head  and  then  off  to  the  lumber-room 
with  him.  Let  us  shape  our  philosophy  as  we  please, 
but  what  is  gained  by  calling  it  Kantianism  ?  Nothing, 
so  far  as  I  can  see,  but  endless  historical  disputation. 
To  prove  to  you,  however,  that  I  am  rigidly  just  to 
the  two  methods  of  treating  Kant,  it  is  enough  to 
remark  that  I  have  myself  used  both — the  developmental 
in  an  essay  in  Essays  in  Philosophical  Criticism  and  the 
bare  historical  in  my  Lectures  on  Scottish  Philosophy. 
In  this  way  I  have  it  in  my  power  to  refer  my  critics 
from  Philip  drunk  to  Philip  sober,  leaving  them  to 
take  their  choice  as  to  which  is  which/' 

As  has  already  been  stated,  the  Second  Series  of  Balfour 
Lectures  followed  the  first  at  an  interval  of  two  years, 
but  there  is  a  wide  space  between  the  two  little  books, 
both  in  respect  of  their  method  and  of  the  impression 
which  they  made. ,  For  Hegelianism  and  Personality 


52  MEMOIR 

had  a  polemical  character  not  previously  seen  in  Seth's 
writings.1  The  opening  lectures,  it  is  true,  on  '  Kant 
and  Neo-Kantianism  '  and  '  Fichte  '  showed  the  same 
traits — clearness  of  exposition  and  criticism  as  a  pro 
paedeutic  to  ultimate  construction — as  his  earlier  essays 
in  the  same  field.  But  when  he  went  on  to  deal  with 
Hegel  and  his  successors,  he  showed  that  he  could 
wield  a  keener  blade  than  he  had  previously  used  ;  and 
to  the  surprise  of  many  readers  its  edge  was  directed 
chiefly  against  aspects  of  that  Hegelian  or  neo-Hegelian 
thought  of  which  he  had  previously  appeared  as  an 
exponent.  It  is  true  that  he  had  never  shown  an  un 
critical  or  unqualified  acceptance  of  Hegel's  system  as 
a  system.  In  the  closing  words  of  From  Kant  to  Hegel 
he  had  expressed  his  conviction  that  the  strength  of 
Hegelianism  lay  most  of  all  in  its  philosophy  of  history. 
Hegel,  he  used  to  tell  his  students,  possessed  "  probably 
the  richest  mind  that  had  been  devoted  to  philosophy 
since  Aristotle " ; 2  and  his  appreciation  of  the  light 
thrown  by  Hegel  on  many  aspects  of  knowledge,  history 
and  art  never  varied.  But  this  little  book  represented  a 
change  of  emphasis  of  a  quite  decided  kind.  The  in 
fluence  of  Mr  Balfour's  criticisms  of  contemporary 
transcendentalism  was  seen  in  this  new  attitude,  though 
the  main  factor  in  causing  it  was  Seth's  own  growing 
sense  that  certain  tendencies  in  Hegel  and  post-Hegelian 
idealism  imperilled  those  ethical  and  religious  positions 
to  which  he  always  firmly  adhered.  Thus  the  spear 
head  of  his  argument  was  directed  against  such  elements 
in  Hegelianism  as  the  attempt  to  deduce  Reality  from 
Pure  Thought,  the  disparagement  of  the  Time-process 
and  of  the  struggle  and  progress  of  moral  personalities 
within  that  process,  the  deification  of  the  philosopher, 

1  The  title  orginally  in  view  was  "  Hegelianism  and  Human  Person 
ality  "  ;   but,  partly  in  deference  to  Campbell  Fraser's  opinion,  it  was 
shortened  by  the  omission  of  the  adjective. 

2  Cf.  Man's  Place  in  the  Cosmos,  p.  94. 


MEMOIR  53 

which  carries  with  it  the  idea  of  God  as  deprived  of  self- 
existence  and  having  "  His  only  reality  in  the  con 
sciousness  of  the  worshipping  community."  l 

Against  any  such  tendency  to  undervalue  the  ex 
perience  of  human  striving  personalities  when  it  tes 
tifies  to  contact  with  a  reality  not  fully  defined  by  the 
processes  of  abstract  thought,  Seth  launched  not  only 
argument  but  a  succession  of  epigrams,  such  as  :  "A 
living  dog  is  better  than  a  dead  lion,  and  even  an  atom 
is  more  than  a  category."  "  Both  philosophy  and 
religion  bear  ample  testimony  to  the  almost  insuper 
able  difficulty  of  finding  room  in  the  universe  for  God 
and  man."  "  Each  Self  is  an  unique  existence,  which 
is  perfectly  impervious,  if  I  may  so  speak,  to  other  selves 
—impervious  in  a  fashion  of  which  the  impenetrability 
of  matter  is  a  faint  analogue."  2  These  were  among 
the  most  often  quoted  of  his  utterances ;  and  the  last 
phrase  in  particular  aroused  much  pointed  criticism,  so 
that  in  his  Gifford  Lectures  he  felt  impelled  to  qualify 
it  carefully.3  Indeed,  the  interval  of  twenty-five  years 
between  the  Balfour  and  Gifford  Lectures  brought  about 
a  change  of  outlook  both  in  physics  and  psychology 
which  to  a  great  extent  robbed  the  analogy  of  its 
appositeness.  But  to  the  underlying  idea  of  the  moral 
Self  as  autonomous  Seth  always  adhered. 

A  letter  to  Mr  W.  P.  James  in  December  1887  throws 
additional  light  upon  Seth's  meaning  : — 

"  My  contention  is  that  our  knowledge  of  a  thing, 
even  if  supposed  adequate,  is  one  thing  and  the  existence 
of  the  thing  itself  is  another.  I  do  not  mean  to  fall 
back  into  relativity  :  let  our  knowledge  be  as  true  as 
it  likes,  as  correct  a  rendering  of  the  essence  of  the 
thing,  still  it  is  a  rendering  of  the  thing,  not  the  thing 

1  Hegelianism  and  Personality,  2nd  ed.,  p.  197. 

2  Op.  cit.,  pp.  131,  162,  227. 
9  The  Idea  of  God,  p.  389  f. 


54  MEMOIR 

itself.  I  think  this  is  pretty  clear  when  we  produce  our 
own  thought  to  infinity  (as  it  were).  Must  it  not  also 
be  true  of  the  divine  thought  qua  thought — at  least  in 
regard  to  anything  that  can  be  said  in  any  sense  to  exist 
on  its  own  account  ? 

"  But  you  are  quite  at  one  with  me  when  you  say 
that  '  the  substance  of  a  stone,  even  when  transparently 
rational,  is  ultimately  impervious  '  ;  and  I  in  turn  am 
quite  at  one  with  you  when  you  try  to  imagine  that 
'  our  personalities  might  be  in  a  still  higher  sense  im 
pervious  though  contained  in  the  higher  spirit/  I 
think  I  have  expressed  myself  in  very  similar  words 
somewhere  in  the  book. 

"  Several  passages  may  seem  to  assert  absolutely 
independent  individuals.  That  would  be  a  philosophical 
absurdity  quite  contrary  to  my  intention,  but  in  com 
bating  an  opinion  one  always  tends  to  overstate  the 
opposite  view.  I  was  aiming  at  some  such  higher  spirit, 
but  asserting  within  it  a  relative  independence  of  lower 
spirits.  Representing  it  metaphorically,  we  should  be 
so  many  centres  of  personality  contained  within  a 
being  who  would  have  his  own  great  centre,  distinct 
from  the  minor  ones.  Ordinary  Hegelians  seem  to  me 
to  make  one  centre  do  duty  for  all,  thus  denying  the 
separateness  or  imperviousness  of  the  different  selves. 
It  is  here,  as  I  think,  that  the  confusion  of  an  epistemo- 
logical  with  a  metaphysical  result  comes  in  harmfully. 

"  At  the  same  time  I  fully  admit  that  the  problem 
of  this  relative  independence  remains  as  dark  as  ever, 
and  is  not  even  touched  in  my  book.  Theosophy  is  a 
dreadful  bog  to  get  into.  The  British  public  won't 
stand  it.  Better  write  a  treatise  on  golf  than  a  third 
course  on  such  a  subject." 

But  before  we  pass  on  to  the  third  course,  we  may 
note  that  the  second  found  some  of  its  most  severe 
critics  among  those  who  had  joined  with  Seth  in  writing 


MEMOIR  55 

Essays  in  Philosophical  Criticism  only  four  years  earlier. 
They  felt,  not  unnaturally,  that  one  of  their  leaders  had, 
in  Plato's  phrase,  "  laid  hands  on  his  father,  Par- 
menides,"  and  that  their  own  competence  as  philoso 
phical  thinkers  had  been  somewhat  sharply  called  in 
question.  Into  the  controversy  which  followed  there  is 
no  need  to  enter  now.  Seth  said,  in  his  Preface  to  the 
second  edition  of  the  book  five  years  later :  "  The 
criticism  it  has  encountered  must  be  regarded  as  a 
wholesome  stirring  of  the  philosophic  waters  "  ;  and 
later  chapters  will  show  that,  whatever  temporary 
coolness — or  heat — may  have  followed  its  publication, 
several  of  Seth's  former  collaborators,  not  least  the 
Haldanes,  remained  close  friends  long  years  after. 
Indeed,  as  early  as  November  1888,  Richard  Haldane 
wrote  that,  in  view  of  a  further  statement  by  Seth, 
he  was  greatly  relieved  to  find  that  they  were  "  so 
nearly  at  one  about  Hegelianism  "  ;  and  that,  though 
he  was  far  from  accepting  some  elements  in  the  book, 
he  had  never  ceased  to  think  that  "  as  against  construc 
tive  Hegelianism  "  it  was  the  most  formidable  piece  of 
work  that  had  appeared.  Another  contributor  to  the 
early  volume,  Professor  D.  G.  Ritchie,  noted  that  in 
the  second  edition  of  Hegelianism  and  Personality,  Seth 
modified  his  statement  that  separate  individuals  were 
"  absolutely  and  for  ever  exclusive,"  and  said  instead : 
"  Whatever  be  the  mode  of  their  comprehension  within 
the  all-containing  bounds  of  the  divine  life,  it  is  certain 
that,  as  selves,  it  is  of  their  very  essence  to  be  rela 
tively  independent  and  mutually  exclusive  centres  of 
existence/'  "  With  the  revised  version  of  this  passage/' 
Professor  Ritchie  added,  "  I  am  delighted  to  find  myself 
in  agreement."  I 

As  soon  as  the  second  series  of  Balfour  Lectures  was 

1  Darwin  and  Hegel  (1893),  p.  100  n.    The  references  in  Hegelianism 
and  Personality  are  :    ist  ed.,  p.  64  ;   2nd  ed.,  p.  69. 


56  MEMOIR 

published,  Mr  Balfour  wrote,  on  December  20,  1887, 
saying  that  the  success  of  the  Lectureship  had  even 
exceeded  his  expectations,  and  suggesting  that  a  third 
course  should  be  given.  He  added  considerately  :  "  Take 
your  own  time  about  it."  Seth  availed  himself  both  of 
the  invitation  and  of  the  attached  permission  ;  and 
three  years  passed  before  he  reported  to  Mr  J.  B. 
Capper  that  he  was  busy  preparing  the  course,  which, 
however,  "  showed  a  strange  reluctance  to  get  itself 
written."  He  also  wrote  to  Professor  Laurie  :  "  My 
lectures,  according  to  the  shape  they  have  taken, 
will  deal  mainly  with  our  old  friend  (or  enemy  ?) 
the  external  world.  The  Neo-Kantian  treatment  of 
'  the  object '  will  come  in  for  consideration  .  .  . 
'  Knowledge  and  Reality  or  Idealism  and  Realism ' 
would,  I  think,  correctly  describe  the  subject,  but  a 
double  title  is  perhaps  a  mistake."  Finally,  the  course 
was  announced  as  on  Realism.  A  few  weeks  before  the 
lectures  were  delivered  Seth  wrote  to  Mr  Balfour : 
'  This  epistemological  question  seems  to  me  very 
ambiguously  dealt  with  by  modern  Kantians  and  Neo- 
Hegelians,  and  equally  so  by  empirical  idealists — so 
that  I  hope  what  I  have  to  say  may  not  be  altogether 
untimely." 

As  the  Lectures  form  the  latter  part  of  the  present 
volume  there  is  no  call  for  comment  on  them  here,  but 
a  word  is  perhaps  needed  as  to  their  subsequent  history. 
Immediately  after  the  delivery  of  the  Lectures,  Seth 
wrote  to  Professor  Laurie  :  "  I  am  determined  to  keep 
them  in  hand  and  work  the  subject  out  before  publishing, 
treating  all  sides  of  it  and  guarding  against  misappre 
hension."  But  this  intention  was  not  fully  accom 
plished.  Later  in  1891  Seth  was  appointed  to  succeed 
Professor  Campbell  Fraser  in  Edinburgh  University ; 
and  Mr  Balfour  agreed  that  publication  in  the  Philoso- 


MEMOIR  57 

phical  Review  l  would  serve  the  immediate  purpose  of 
bringing  them  before  the  students  of  philosophy,  until 
the  writer  should  have  time  for  the  thorough  revision 
which  he  had  in  mind.  But  the  larger  responsibilities 
which  Seth  found  awaiting  him  in  Edinburgh,  and 
perhaps  also  some  shifting  in  his  central  interest  from 
epistemology  to  other  branches  of  philosophy,  caused 
this  revision  to  be  postponed.  Although  he  still  had  it 
in  mind  in  the  summer  of  1893,  it  was  finally  abandoned  ; 
so  it  is  only  now  that  the  third  series  of  Balfour  Lectures 
can  take  its  place  beside  the  familiar  volumes  containing 
the  first  and  second  series. 

1  The  Review  was  edited  by  Dr  Schurman,  who  was  at  this  time 
Dean  of  the  Sage  School  of  Philosophy  in  Cornell  University. 


CHAPTER  V. 

ST  ANDREWS. 

1887-1891. 

IN  the  summer  of  1887  the  Chair  of  Logic,  Rhetoric 
and  Metaphysics  in  the  University  of  St  Andrews  became 
vacant  through  the  death  of  Professor  Spencer  Baynes, 
editor  of  the  Encyclopedia  Britannica.  Seth  applied 
for  and  was  appointed  to  the  chair,  which  embraced  the 
two  subjects  of  his  special  love,  Philosophy  and  Litera 
ture.  His  departure  caused  great  regret  to  his  Cardiff 
friends,  and  he  left  them  with  a  like  regret,  but  with 
no  hesitations,  saying  :  "At  last  my  own  country  sees 
fit  to  provide  me  with  bread."  Several  of  these  friends 
found  their  way  gladly  to  the  Seths'  new  home, 
'  Mayfield/  during  the  years  they  remained  in  St 
Andrews  —  years  of  strenuous  work  and  tranquil 
happiness. 

Soon  after  arriving,  Seth  wrote  to  W.  P.  James  :  "I 
am  not  yet  in  a  state  to  correspond  with  my  friends, 
being  involved  for  my  sins  in  the  mysteries  of  Celtic 
and  Anglo-Saxon  Literature.  The  former,  I  believe, 
is  a  nemesis  for  leaving  Wales.  .  .  .  We  like  the  place 
here,  but  often  think  back  to  Cardiff  and  Cardiff  friends. 
The  students  are  a  pleasant  set  of  fellows.  I  have  35 
for  Logic  and  Psychology  and  24  for  Literature."  Among 
these  was  one  from  a  Perthshire  village,  William  Menzies, 


MEMOIR  59 

afterwards  one  of  His  Majesty's  Inspectors  of  Schools, 
to  whom  we  are  indebted  for  the  vivid  account  of  Seth's 
work  and  influence  which  follows. 


"  Andrew  Seth  was  at  St  Andrews  in  the  late  eighties 
of  last  century,  the  period  during  which  I  was  fortunate 
enough  to  be  a  student  there.  His  influence  in  these 
years  was  undoubtedly  the  strongest  in  the  University, 
and  for  some  of  us  it  is  not  too  much  to  say  that  the 
University  was  transformed  by  it.  He  was  then  in  his 
early  prime,  and  various  circumstances  no  longer  ex 
isting  contributed  to  strengthen  the  authority  he  would 
normally  have  exercised  anywhere  in  virtue  of  his 
personality  and  his  outstanding  gifts  as  a  teacher  and 
thinker. 

"At  St  Andrews  in  those  days  life  was  quiet  and 
favourable  to  meditation  and  study.  The  University 
dominated  the  little  town.  It  was  the  townsfolk's  chief 
concern,  and  living  for  the  students  was  incredibly 
cheap  and  good.  The  great  Girls'  School  was  still  quite 
small,  and  even  golf  was  little  talked  of.  It  was  possible 
to  be  acquainted  with  student  golfers  of  championship 
form  and  to  be  scarcely  aware  that  they  played  the 
game.  The  difference  in  the  interest  excited  by  golf 
then  and  now  is  well  brought  out  by  a  small  incident 
that  occurred  as  late  as  the  summer  of  1890.  Observing 
in  the  course  of  a  walk  across  the  links  with  Seth  a  large 
group  of  one  or  two  hundred  people,  I  said,  "  What 
crowd  can  that  be  ?  "  The  professor  raised  his  eyes, 
and,  after  studying  the  group  for  some  seconds,  re 
marked,  "  I  think  that  must  be  the  Golf  Champion 
ship."  Besides  golf  there  was  football,  and  for  some 
of  us  drilling  or  Saturday  shooting  practice  in  con 
nection  with  the  '  O.T.C.,'  or  the  Volunteer  Corps, 
standing  in  those  days  for  the  present-day  '  O.T.C.' 

Walking  was  the  commonest  recreation  or  means  of 
taking  exercise.  Summer  sessions  were  non-existent, 


60  MEMOIR 

nor  were  there  any  women  students,  and  tennis,  dancing 
and  evening  parties  were  virtually  unknown.  Univer 
sity  lecturing  practically  finished  at  two  o'clock,  and  the 
afternoons  and  evenings  were  free.  It  was  a  simple 
mode  of  life,  centred  mainly  round  the  intellectual 
activity  of  the  University  and  ignoring  many  import 
ant  social  factors ;  but  there  was  an  absence  of  dis 
traction  about  it  and  a  not  unwholesome  austerity 
which  assisted  study  and  prepared  us  for  a  thorough 
appreciation  of  good  teaching. 

"  Nor  in  the  conditions  prevailing  within  the  Univer 
sity  itself  was  there  anything  likely  to  hinder  the  im 
mediate  recognition  of  a  new-comer  of  Seth's  calibre. 
The  Chair  of  Moral  Philosophy  was  then  held  by  William 
Knight,  the  well-known  editor  of  Wordsworth,  whose 
main  interest  was  Literature.  As  a  teacher  of  Philosophy 
he  was  not  effective.  Lewis  Campbell  in  the  Greek 
Chair  was  a  revered  figure.  Attainments  such  as  his 
would  have  graced  any  university,  and  his  mere  presence 
amongst  us  was  an  uplifting  influence  of  singular  value. 
But  it  has  to  be  admitted  that  the  best  of  Campbell 
was  in  his  published  works  ;  his  class  lecturing  was  not 
comparable  to  Seth's.  Later  on  Burnet  in  Campbell's 
Chair  was  a  power  in  the  University,  but  that  was 
after  Seth  left.  In  my  own  time  the  strongest  indi 
vidual  influence  was  undoubtedly  Seth's.  For  some  few 
of  us  he  was  almost  the  one  thing  that  counted,  and  to 
all  of  us  he  meant  a  great  deal. 

"  It  must  not  be  forgotten  that  at  that  time  under  the 
regime  of  the  old  seven  subjects  curriculum,  since  so 
unfortunately  given  up,  Philosophy  was  an  obligatory 
subject  ;  and  the  influence  of  philosophy  professors, 
therefore,  embraced  the  whole  body  of  students,  and 
was  not  confined,  as  it  might  be  now,  to  a  limited  section. 
Seth,  moreover,  was  also  Professor  of  English,  and 
throughout  his  term  at  St  Andrews  he  was  thus  doubly 
in  contact  with  all  Arts  students,  and  that  by  means  of 
two  of  the  most  important  and  vitalising  subjects  in  the 
whole  curriculum.  The  impression  which  he  made  on 


MEMOIR  61 

his  arrival  was  instantaneous,  and  it  was  lasting.  From 
the  first  he  seemed  to  embody  all  those  qualities  which 
the  Scottish  student  most  desires  in  his  professor,  and 
to  which  even  the  least  thoughtful  of  them  pay  an 
instinctive  homage.  I  can  recall  his  inaugural  address, 
the  tall,  slightly  stooping  figure,  the  measured  delivery, 
the  pensive  youthful  face  and  the  thick  hair  abundantly 
sprinkled  with  grey  ;  and  I  remember  the  ingenuous 
answer  made  me  by  a  fellow-student  on  my  referring 
after  the  address  to  those  signs  of  age  in  one  so  young, 
'  When  you  have  done  as  much  "  grinding  "  as  him 
perhaps  your  own  hair  will  be  just  as  white/ 

"A  small  matter  worth  noting,  for  it  is  a  significant 
tribute  to  Seth's  personality,  was  the  invariably  sober 
demeanour  of  the  students  in  his  classroom.  Even  in 
his  absence  they  were  relatively  quiet,  with  a  general 
avoidance  of  the  noisy  and  harmless  demonstrations 
common  elsewhere.  Indeed  they  behaved  less  like  St 
Andrews  students  of  those  days  than  people  waiting 
for  a  service  in  church. 

"  In  thinking  of  his  teaching  at  St  Andrews  the  main 
characteristics  that  come  back  to  me  at  this  distance 
of  time  are  :  the  extraordinarily  convincing  nature  of 
his  exposition,  TreiOa)  ris  eTretcdOi^ev  eVl  TO £9  %etXecrt^ ; 
the  uniform  lucidity  and  finish  of  his  language  ;  the 
closely  knit  coherence  and  cogency  of  his  argument ; 
and  the  inspiring  level  of  sober  eloquence  to  which 
it  would  insensibly  rise  on  rare  occasions  under  the 
pressure  of  the  thought  behind  it. 

"  He  did  not  disdain  picturesque  locutions,  and  the 
felicitous  use  of  such  expressions,  whether  his  own  or 
borrowed,  was  common  enough  with  him  to  make  it  a 
feature  of  his  lecturing  style.  '  The  rivets  of  experi 
ence/  '  the  spout  behind  the  clouds/  show  what  is 
meant.  The  impression  which  his  ordinary  lecturing 
style  merely  as  language  made  on  the  ear  was  peculiarly 
satisfying  ;  and  I  am  tempted  to  connect  with  this 
characteristic  as  in  some  degree  accounting  for  it  the 
practice  implied  in  an  admonition  which  he  once  gave 


62  MEMOIR 

myself  for  the  improvement  of  my  class  essays  :  '  You 
should  first  sound/  he  said,  '  each  sentence  to  yourself 
before  putting  it  down  on  paper/  He  was  not  averse 
to  poetical  quotation  and  in  his  philosophy  lectures 
quoted  occasionally,  though  but  sparingly  and  never 
merely  for  the  sake  of  ornament.  In  his  lectures  on 
English,  on  the  other  hand,  his  taste  for  literature  and 
his  intense  love  of  good  poetry  came  fully  and  power 
fully  to  light.  It  was  this  quality  above  everything 
else  which  inspired  and  shaped  his  English  lectures, 
and  would  have  lent  them  almost  alone  a  perfectly 
adequate  degree  of  life  and  character.  His  course  was 
unpretentiously  conceived — Seth  was  but  an  amateur 
in  English — but  the  lecturer's  great  power  of  appre 
ciation  and  his  even  more  singular  power  of  communi 
cating  his  own  appreciation  to  others  were  in  themselves 
more  than  sufficient  to  make  it  a  memorable  experience. 

"  He  was  sensible  to  all  kinds  of  poetry,  and  in  those 
days  showed  a  special  fondness  for  Keats ;  but  his 
temperamental  affinity  for  the  more  elevated  kind  where 
Literature  and  Philosophy  meet  was  obvious.  With 
Wordsworth,  Dante,  Goethe  and  the  Shakespeare  of  the 
Tragedies  he  was  thus  in  his  proper  element,  and  I 
have  heard  him  read  out  with  fervour  in  his  thrillingly 
beautiful  voice — in  what  connection  I  cannot  now  recall 
—the  whole  of  the  great  passage  on  the  misery  of 
Human  Life  from  the  Third  Book  of  Lucretius.  Verses 
of  his  own  composition  appeared  on  several  occasions  in 
the  College  Magazine.  Their  finished  form  and  grave 
beauty  of  sentiment  were  highly  characteristic,  and 
Lewis  Campbell,  a  fastidious  judge,  thought  extremely 
well  of  them. 

"  In  lecturing  on  the  poets  he  quoted  a  great  deal. 
In  fact  the  more  important  the  poet  the  longer  and 
the  more  numerous  became  the  passages  quoted.  It 
was  as  if  his  chosen  method  was  to  stand  aside  as  far  as 
possible  and  let  us  see  or  rather  hear  the  poet  for  our 
selves.  Whatever  the  reason  there  is  no  doubt  that  in 
adopting  this  procedure  he  was  happily  inspired,  if  only 


MEMOIR  63 

because  of  his  voice,  which  was  low,  clear  and  instantly 
and  faithfully  responsive  to  every  shade  of  thought  and 
feeling — a  voice  in  fact  made  for  speaking  verse  just  as 
it  should  be  spoken.  Lines  said  as  he  could  say  them 
would  often  impress  themselves  at  once  and  perma 
nently  on  the  mind,  and  there  were  many  I  thus  remem 
bered.  Here  are  a  few — 

'  After  life's  fitful  fever  he  sleeps  well.' 

'  To-morrow,  and  to-morrow,  and  to-morrow, 
Creeps  in  this  petty  pace  from  day  to  day 
To  the  last  syllable  of  recorded  time. 
And  all  our  yesterdays  have  lighted  fools 
The  way  to  dusty  death.' 

'  Full  on  this  casement  shone  the  wintry  moon 
And  threw  warm  gules  on  Madeline's  fair  breast.' 

'  If  this  fail, 

The  pillared  firmament  is  rottenness 
And  earth's  base  built  on  stubble/ 

'  Yet  some  there  be  that  by  due  steps  aspire 

To  lay  their  just  hands  on  that  golden  key 
That  opes  the  palace  of  eternity.' 

These  are  only  a  few  among  many  lines  of  English 
poetry  which  I  have  never  read  since  without  being 
reminded  of  Seth  and  the  exact  tone  of  voice  in  which 
he  delivered  them  when  I  first  heard  them  read  out  by 
him  in  the  English  classroom  at  St  Andrews.  One  small 
circumstance  connected  with  his  reading  of  the  passage 
from  Marlowe's  Tamburlaine  beginning — 

'  The  thirst  of  reign  and  sweetness  of  a  crown 
That  caused  the  eldest  son  of  heavenly  Ops 
To  thrust  his  doting  father  from  his  chair,' 

lingers  in  my  memory.  In  the  course  of  this  passage 
occur  the  words  :  '  Still  climbing  after  knowledge  in- 


64  MEMOIR 

finite/  Seth  must  have  felt  their  force  very  strongly; 
for,  after  finishing  the  passage,  he  returned  to  them 
for  a  moment  and  kept  repeating  them  in  a  half  whisper 
to  himself.  They  had  evidently  struck  a  highly 
sympathetic  chord  in  his  imagination 

"  In  both  Philosophy  and  Literature  Seth's  own  pre 
dilection  was  for  depth  and  solidity  rather  than  mere 
extensiveness,  and  wide  discursive  reading  on  the  sub 
jects  of  his  lecture  was  not  a  habit  which  he  much 
encouraged.  Acting  himself  on  the  principle  of  multum 
non  multa,  he  led  us  to  think  that  it  was  much  better 
for  us  at  that  stage  to  spend  our  time  in  wrestling  for 
ourselves  with  the  problems  of  Philosophy,  as  they 
occurred  in  the  writings  of  two  or  three  representative 
thinkers,  than  in  reading  what  had  been  said  about  them 
by  commentators  and  historians.  So,  though  he  did  not 
actually  dissuade  us  from  discursive  accessory  reading 
and  indeed  recommended  at  the  beginning  of  each  course 
a  number  of  works  for  consultation  and  reference,  he 
would  in  his  own  lectures  refer  to  these  but  slightly, 
confining  his  attention  almost  entirely  to  the  class- 
books  prescribed.  What  these  were  in  the  Ordinary 
Class  I  cannot  recall.  In  the  Advanced  Class,  which 
was  the  really  important  one,  for  it  was  in  it  that  the 
professor  gave  of  his  best  and  that  the  significance  of 
Philosophy  was  first  revealed  to  us,  the  works  studied 
were  :  Mill's  Logic,  the  Thecetetus  in  the  Greek,  and, 
much  the  most  important  of  all,  The  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason.  Seth,  I  remember,  was  very  sympathetic  with 
Mill  and  very  good  and  full  on  the  Thecetetus,  the  subject 
of  which  probably  had  a  special  attraction  for  him  at 
the  time  because  of  his  own  preoccupation  with  the 
question  of  Epistemology.  It  was  on  Kant,  however, 
approached  by  a  series  of  excellent  lectures  on  his  pre 
decessors  from  Descartes  downwards,  amongst  which 
the  lectures  on  Leibnitz  and  an  impressive  and  elevated 
exposition  of  Spinoza  stand  conspicuously  out  in  my 
recollection,  that  the  main  part  of  the  professor's  work 


MEMOIR  65 

in  this  course  was  concentrated.  He  gave  us  lecture 
after  lecture  on  the  Critique  in  the  endeavour  to  make 
us  realise  by  different  methods  of  approach  that  with 
this  work  we  had  reached  the  great  clearing-house  of 
modern  Philosophy  and  were  in  living  contact  with  all 
its  main  problems. 

"  In  the  course  of  the  session  we  wrote  several  essays, 
one  of  them  on  the  difficult  subject  of  Kant's  conception 
of  Causality.  The  degree  of  reflection  and  research  in 
volved  in  such  work  no  doubt  benefited  us  considerably, 
but  what  I  chiefly  remember  in  connection  with  it  were 
the  professor's  elucidations.  Whatever  else  our  own 
efforts  had  failed  to  effect,  they  had  at  least  the  advan 
tage  of  putting  us  into  the  best  possible  state  for  com 
prehending  and  appreciating  at  something  like  its  full 
value  the  sure  and  illuminating  treatment  of  the  subject 
given  by  the  professor  on  the  return  of  each  essay. 

"  It  was  possible  for  Honours  students  at  St  Andrews 
in  those  days  to  be  in  quite  exceptionally  intimate 
contact  with  their  professors.  Very  few  men  thought  of 
Honours  then.  In  some  subjects,  indeed,  and  these 
standard  Arts  ones,  Moral  Philosophy  for  example,  no 
Advanced  Courses  were  held  at  all,  and  there  were  none 
in  Logic  either  till  Seth  started  them.  The  briefness  of 
his  stay  in  St  Andrews  did  not,  I  think,  give  him  time 
for  more  than  two,  the  first  of  which  was  the  one  I  had. 
In  these  courses  the  relationship  between  the  professor 
and  his  pupils  was  all  the  warmer  and  more  fruitful 
for  the  fact  that  the  classes  were  so  small.  I  think  the 
class  of  the  year  succeeding  my  own  numbered  but  three 
or  four,  the  keenest  of  whom  were  David  Irons  and 
John  Smart,  both  for  different  reasons  conspicuous 
figures  amongst  their  fellow-students.  Smart  was  known 
as  a  man  of  literary  bent,  he  was  editor  of  the  College 
Magazine  and  played  a  leading  role  in  the  Students 
Representative  Council ;  while  Irons  was  at  first  prob 
ably  better  known  as  an  athlete  than  as  a  scholar. 
Smart's  true  vocation  was  literature,  and  before  his 

E 


66  MEMOIR 

death  a  few  years  ago  he  had  acquired  with  the  dis 
criminating  scholarly  public  a  high  reputation  for  critical 
insight  and  scholarship  of  the  soundest  type.  He  first 
made  a  name  for  himself  by  a  book  on  The  Ossianic 
Question.  A  fine  study  of  Milton's  Sonnets  followed, 
and  a  posthumous  work  on  Shakespeare,  embodying  the 
results  of  much  reflection  and  original  research,  was 
widely  and  warmly  welcomed.  Smart's  deflection  from 
his  ingrained  constitutional  bent  for  letters  was  but 
temporary,  but  that  it  occurred  at  all  serves  to  show 
the  strength  of  the  attraction  exercised  by  Seth. 

"  Irons'  case  was  more  striking.  Unlike  Smart,  he 
had  a  strong  natural  affinity  for  Philosophy,  but  it  was 
an  affinity  which  but  for  Seth's  happening  to  be  in  St 
Andrews  he  might  never  have  discovered.  He  entered 
Seth's  class  and  suddenly  found  himself.  From  that 
moment  Philosophy  seemed  to  him  the  one  way  of  life 
worth  following,  and  follow  it  he  did  with  single-minded 
and  unswerving  ardour  until  his  early  death  in  America 
many  years  ago.  When  I  knew  him,  the  two  over 
mastering  interests  in  his  life  were  his  passion  for  Philo 
sophy  and  his  devotion  to  Seth,  the  two  being  almost 
indistinguishably  fused  in  his  mind. 

"  But  though  probably  none  of  his  St  Andrews  students 
felt  Seth's  influence  quite  so  much  as  Irons,  he  was  not 
the  only  one  to  feel  it  strongly.  And,  indeed,  there  was 
something  quite  out  of  the  common  about  Seth's  sheer 
effectiveness  as  a  teacher  of  Metaphysics  in  those  days. 
This  showed  itself  not  merely  in  ability  to  command 
attention  and  to  stimulate  interest  or  intellectual  curi 
osity.  Any  other  teacher  who  to  similar  knowledge 
and  talents  united  an  equal  or  nearly  equal  devotion  to 
the  subject  might  have  managed  as  much  as  that.  But 
Seth  did  more.  He  made  Metaphysics  not  merely  inter 
esting  but  exciting.  The  really  distinguishing  feature  of 
his  teaching  was  the  glowing  and  fervid  character  of 
the  interest  he  had  the  power  of  arousing  in  us  by  what 
was  nevertheless  an  appropriately  severe  and  strictly 


MEMOIR  67 

logical  treatment  of  his  subject.  I  can  recall,  for  example, 
the  state  of  tumultuous  emotion  in  which  I  found  Irons 
and  Smart  immediately  after  a  certain  lecture  on  Spinoza, 
which  in  the  tense  absorption  of  all  concerned  had  in 
sensibly  lengthened  out  from  the  regulation  period  of  one 
hour  to  two. 

"  I  once  heard  Pringle-Pattison  say  that  great  meta 
physicians  could  be  divided  into  two  classes,  according 
as  in  each  case  the  prime  motive,  the  original  impulse 
to  Speculation,  could  be  regarded  as  mainly  ethical  or 
mainly  intellectual.  His  own  place,  unless  I  am  mis 
taken,  would  be  in  the  first  group  among  thinkers  such 
as  Plato  and  Spinoza.  In  his  metaphysical  speculations 
the  ultimate  ethical  interest,  I  think,  might  always  be 
felt  as  the  essential  and  fundamental  source  of  their 
vitality.  It  was  beyond  us  then  to  discern  this  char 
acteristic  or  its  bearings  with  any  clearness  ;  but,  if  it 
was  real,  as  I  believe  it  was,  its  existence  would  have 
to  be  reckoned  with  as  perhaps  the  strongest  single 
factor  in  his  power  over  us  as  a  teacher.  It  was  a  power 
which  could  serve  in  itself  as  a  concrete  refutation  of 
that  common  view  of  Philosophy  expressed  in  the  words 
of  a  well-known  French  writer  :  '  The  great  weakness 
of  Philosophy  will  always  lie  in  its  inability  to  appeal  to 
the  feelings/  ' 


It  seems  appropriate  to  add  to  Mr  Menzies'  account 
of  the  years  during  which  Seth  taught  English  Literature 
as  well  as  Philosophy,  three  from  the  slender  sheaf  of 
poems  which  won  praise  from  Lewis  Campbell,  and 
which  their  author  printed  years  after  for  his  children. 
The  first  was  written  in  1880,  and  the  second  and  third 
date  from  the  St  Andrews  days. 


68  MEMOIR 


ST  DENIS. 

When  I  have  gazed  upon  the  storied  tombs 
Reared  o'er  the  famous  dead,  in  hallowed  crypt 
Have  seen  the  velvet  rotting  round  their  bones — 
Then  have  I  longed,  in  thinking  of  my  end, 
For  sun  and  sky,  sweet  air,  and  breeze-blown  grass. 

Lay  me  where  the  whispering  trees 

Net  the  sunlight  over  me  ; 

Green  and  gold  my  pall  shall  be 
'Neath  their  sylvan  traceries. 

Let  the  brown  bird  o'er  my  head 

Call  his  mate  among  the  leaves  ; 

When  the  reaper  binds  his  sheaves, 
His  smooth  song  shall  lull  the  dead. 


THE  DAY  AFTER. 

But  yesterday,  through  mist  and  gloom, 

We  bore  him  to  his  rest ; 
To-day  the  joyous  sunshine  floods 

The  bay  from  east  to  west. 

It  sleeps  upon  the  time-worn  towers 
And  on  the  new-made  grave, 

And  out  to  sea  the  white-winged  gull 
Flashes  along  the  wave. 

O  Life  that  cradlest  all  our  lives  ! 

We  wake  and  then  we  sleep  ; 
For  life  or  death  thou  wilt  not  break 

Thine  ancient  silence  deep. 


MEMOIR  69 


SALVE,  MAGNA  PARENS  ! 

Birthplace  of  our  immortal  years 

Dear  Earth,  upon  whose  breast  we  played, 
Whose  streams  we  strayed  by,  in  whose  lanes 

We  wandered  once  as  man  and  maid 

Dear  as  first  love  thy  fields  and  woods, 
The  flush  of  spring  and  June's  deep  green, 

And  dear  the  autumn-purpled  moor, 
The  far-off  peak  in  wintry  sheen. 

The  flying  splendours  of  the  morn, 
The  pools  that  keep  the  evening  light, 

The  silver  sickle  of  the  moon 

And  star-sown  spaces  of  the  night. 

Mother  beloved,  O  not  in  vain 

Our  spirits'  nurse,  thou  ancient  Earth  ! 

Thy  beauties  fade  not  from  our  sight, 
Where'er  our  souls  again  have  birth. 

Deep  in  our  hearts  they  mirrored  lie, 
Beyond  the  mists  of  death  they  shine  ; 

The  winds  that  blow  about  thy  hills 
Still,  still  will  stir  our  pulse  like  wine. 

Else  were  we  dead  in  very  sooth, 

Or  ghosts  within  a  ghostly  land, 
Where  the  unavailing  shadows  flit 

Cheerless  along  the  dusky  strand. 


7o 


CHAPTER  VI. 

FIRST   YEARS   IN   THE   EDINBURGH    CHAIR. 

1891-1897. 

WHEN  Professor  Campbell  Fraser  resigned  the  Chair  of 
Logic  and  Metaphysics  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh, 
Seth  at  once  became  a  candidate.  His  most  formidable 
competitor  was  Robert  Adamson,  at  this  time  Professor 
in  Owens  College,  Manchester,  and  afterwards  in  the 
University  of  Glasgow.  Adamson's  learning  and  pene 
trating  intellect  had  long  before  won  the  respect  of 
his  fellow-philosophers,  and  not  least  of  Seth  himself ; 
but  he  had  published  very  little  during  the  previous 
decade,  while  Seth's  recent  volumes  had  marked  him 
out  as  a  thinker  whose  originality  and  critical  power 
found  fitting  expression  in  a  singularly  apt  and  lucid 
literary  style.  On  July  8,  1891,  the  result  was  known, 
and  Seth  wrote  to  Professor  Laurie  :— 

"It  is  in  every  way  very  gratifying.  Be  sure  that  I 
do  not  forget  how  much  your  untiring  efforts  have  con 
tributed  to  the  result.  I  do  not  lose  sight  either  of  the 
serious  aspects  of  the  thing,  for  it  is  undoubtedly  a 
serious  matter  to  reflect  that  one  has  reached  the  goal 
of  one's  ambition.  It  remains  to  make  a  good  use  of  the 
position,  and  I  think  with  the  fresh  stimulus  and  the 
greater  leisure  in  summer,  I  may  :  I  hope  I  have  not 
yet  ceased  to  think  and  to  learn." 


MEMOIR  71 

Seth's  thirty-fifth  year  had  indeed  brought  him,  not 
only  to  the  climacteric  of  his  life — in  Dante's  phrase, 
il  mezzo  del  cammin — but  to  the  position  in  the  academic 
world  towards  which  he  had  long  looked.  For  nearly 
ten  years  he  had  been  recognised  as  a  coming  leader  of 
idealistic  thought.  For  four  years  he  had  taught  in  the 
oldest  university  of  his  native  land.  But  now  he  entered 
on  his  main  life-work,  following  that  of  the  man  to 
whom  he  owed  his  first  impulse  to  philosophy.  Campbell 
Fraser's  own  feeling  regarding  the  appointment  stands 
on  record  in  the  last  chapter  of  his  Biographia  Philoso- 
phica :  "  My  hope  for  the  Chair  of  Hamilton,  and 
through  it  for  the  university  as  well  as  for  philosophy 
in  Scotland,  was  happily  realised  in  the  appointment  of 
my  distinguished  successor,  who  fitly  represents  philo 
sophy  in  the  city  of  David  Hume,  Adam  Smith  and 
Dugald  Stewart,  Sir  William  Hamilton  and  James 
Frederick  Ferrier." 

Among  his  colleagues  in  the  Faculty  of  Arts,  Seth 
found  several  who  had  been  his  teachers  fifteen  years 
before.  Henry  Calderwood  occupied  the  Chair  of  Moral 
Philosophy,  and  in  spite  of  wide  differences  of  outlook 
and  philosophical  method,  the  two  men  worked  together 
for  six  years  harmoniously  and  with  mutual  respect.1 
Masson,  Tait  and  Blackie  also  remained ;  and  before 
long  Seth  received  from  Blackie  an  invitation  to  join  a 
circle  for  the  study  of  Greek  tragedy,  addressed  in  a 
handwriting  which  must  have  been  the  despair  of  many 
a  postman,  especially  as  the  writer  always  placed  beside 
the  address  a  short  text  or  quotation  in  Greek.  On 
July  24  Seth  wrote  to  a  Cardiff  friend  that  he  would 
now  be  free  from  the  heavy  work  as  an  external  examiner, 
which  had  hitherto  occupied  much  of  his  time  :  "  It  is 

1  Seth's  estimate  of  Calderwood  as  a  philosopher  will  be  found  in 
his  Memoir  of  James  Seth,  p.  xv,  where  he  especially  notes  Calder 
wood 's  "  fine  natural  courtesy." 


72  MEMOIR 

a  grand  thought  that  I  have  had  my  last  bout  with  exam, 
papers,  at  least  on  that  colossal  scale.  .  .  .  And  I  have 
an  assistant  too  in  the  winter !  The  letters  I  get  from 
that  assistant  are  like  precious  ointment,  and  enable 
me,  more  than  anything  else,  to  realise  my  new  dignity/' 
The  assistant  was  Mr  R.  P.  Hardie,  afterwards  Reader 
in  Ancient  Philosophy  in  the  University,  who  had 
brought  back  from  Oxford  to  his  native  city  a  deep 
interest  in  Greek  thought  and  especially  in  Aristotle, 
and  who  proved  not  only  an  invariably  helpful  colleague 
but  a  close  and  valued  friend  during  nearly  forty 
years. 

Three  months  after  Seth's  election  to  the  Edinburgh 
chair  Mr  Balfour  became  Chancellor  of  Edinburgh 
University.  So  in  the  service  of  the  University  another 
link  was  formed,  which  lasted  for  the  same  long  period. 
The  new  Chancellor  took  a  keen  interest  in  everything 
that  concerned  the  teaching  of  philosophy ;  and  a  few 
years  later,  when  Seth  launched  a  scheme  for  the  found 
ing  of  an  Honours  Philosophy  Library — now  associated 
with  the  name  of  Lord  Haldane — he  was  one  of  the  first 
contributors. 

Seth's  Inaugural  Address  in  the  chair  which  he  adorned 
for  twenty-eight  years  was  delivered  on  October  26, 
1891.  *  It  began  with  the  tribute  to  his  predecessor  and 
the  account  of  the  awakening  of  his  own  interest  in 
philosophy  which  have  been  already  quoted,  and  went 
on  to  describe  the  threefold  discipline,  in  logic,  psy 
chology  and  the  history  of  philosophy,  which  lay  before 
those  who  entered  on  the  course.  Now  that  Seth  had 
emerged  from  his  short  experience  of  the  teaching  of 
that  English  Literature  which  he  never  ceased  to  study 
with  delight,  he  was  able  to  direct  fuller  attention  than 
before  to  psychology  in  its  modern  developments ; 
though  from  the  outset  he  looked  forward  to  the  appoint  - 

1  Reprinted  in  Man's  Place  in  the  Cosmos,  p.  24  ff. 


MEMOIR  73 

ment  of  a  specialist  Lecturer  in  Psychology,  which  took 
place  fifteen  years  later. 

The  Inaugural  Address  made  it  clear  that  he  looked 
on  the  study  of  the  metaphysical  systems  of  the  past 
as  "  one  of  the  richest  parts  of  the  training  afforded  by 
a  philosophical  chair,"  and  ended  with  a  deeply  felt 
confession  of  his  own  philosophic  faith.  After  acknow 
ledging  the  grandeur  of  Hegel's  interpretation  of  the 
progress  of  life  and  mind  to  its  culmination  in  man,  he 
went  on  to  say  :  "  The  achievements  of  the  world- 
spirit  do  not  move  me  to  unqualified  admiration,  and  I 
cannot  accept  the  abstraction  of  the  race  in  place  of  the 
living  children  of  men.  Even  if  the  enormous  spiral  of 
history  is  destined  to  wind  itself  at  last  to  a  point  which 
may  be  called  achievement,  what,  I  ask,  of  the  multi 
tudes  that  perished  by  the  way  ?  '  These  all  died,  not 
having  received  the  promises/  What  if  there  are  no 
promises  to  them?  To  me  the  old  idea  of  the  world 
as  the  training-ground  of  individual  character  seems  to 
offer  a  much  more  human,  and,  I  will  add,  a  much  more 
divine,  solution  than  this  pitiless  procession  of  the  car 
of  progress."  To  many  old  students  these  words  will 
recur  as  giving  the  keynote  of  the  deeper  teaching  of 
their  old  master  in  the  well-remembered  Logic  Class 
room. 

Nor  did  they  fail  to  awaken  echoes  from  other  centres 
of  thought.  One  of  the  most  significant  came  from 
Hegel's  old  University  of  Jena,  in  a  letter  bearing  a 
signature  destined  to  become  widely  known  during  the 
two  following  decades — that  of  Rudolf  Eucken.  The 
leader  of  '  activist '  idealism  in  Germany  acknowledged 
the  pleasure  with  which  he  had  received  the  Inaugural 
Address  of  one  whom  he  greeted  as  a  fellow-worker  in 
the  cause  of  a  fundamental  refashioning  of  the  spiritual 
life  of  mankind  (cine  durchgreifende  Reform  in  dem 
Geistesleben  der  Menschheit).  He  went  on  to  congratu- 


74  MEMOIR 

late  him  on  his  transference  to  the  University  which 
was  considered  in  Germany  the  most  notable  in  the 
English-speaking  world  (die  Universitdt  die  bei  uns  in 
Deutschland  filr  die  bedeutendste  oiler  Universitdten 
englischer  Zunge  gilt)  ;  and  remarked  that  traditional 
roles  were  reversed  when  Germans  had  become  dis 
trustful  of  metaphysics  (Antimetaphysiker),  and  looked 
to  England  for  a  new  impulse  in  philosophy.  This 
impulse  Eucken  found  and  welcomed  in  the  closing 
passages  of  the  Address. 

Seth's  conscientiousness  in  preparing  for  his  class 
lectures  comes  out  in  a  letter  written  during  his  third 
winter  in  Edinburgh  to  Professor  Samuel  Alexander, 
who  had  inquired  about  the  third  series  of  Balfour 
Lectures  :  "  I  can  well  believe  you  have  been  full  of 
work  this  session.  I  find  myself  still  absurdly  occupied 
with  my  lectures  from  day  to  day,  and  have  registered 
a  solemn  vow  to  do  some  steady  work  this  summer 
towards  putting  them  into  better  shape/' 

When  Andrew  and  Eva  Seth  moved  from  St  Andrews 
in  the  autumn  of  1891,  they  settled  in  the  house  at 
16  Churchhill,  which  became  the  Edinburgh  home  of 
the  family  for  just  forty  years.  They  had  now  four 
children — Marjorie,  Norman,  Ernest  and  Elinor ;  and 
in  the  six  years  that  followed  the  two  youngest  sons, 
Siegfried  and  Ronald,  were  born.  The  new  home  was 
not  far  from  the  home  of  Seth's  student  days,  at  a  higher 
point  of  the  ridge  which  slopes  gently  westward  from 
the  base  of  Arthur's  Seat  to  the  Boroughmuir,  where  in 
old  days  was  the  rallying  point  of  Scottish  armies. 
Close  by  was  the  Bore  Stone,  where  the  King's  standard 
was  set  up,  and  but  little  farther  away  was  Merchiston 
Castle,  the  venerable  building  in  which  John  Napier 
invented  logarithms  early  in  the  seventeenth  century, 
and  which  two  hundred  and  fifty  years  later  became  a 


MEMOIR  75 

famous  school.    To  it  the  two  younger  boys  went  at  a 
later  time. 

The  garden  of  the  Seths'  new  home  sloped  to  the 
south,  and  beyond  it  were  other  large  gardens  contain 
ing  not  a  few  fine  trees.  Over  these  could  be  seen  the 
western  end  of  Blackford  Hill,  and  to  the  south-west 
the  noble  line  of  the  Pentlands  above  Swanston — the 
scarped  ridge  of  Caerketton  and  the  green  dome  of 
Allermuir.  Seth's  study  was  on  an  upper  floor,  and  the 
whole  wide  sweep  of  the  hills  was  within  view  as  he  sat 
at  his  desk. 

In  April  1892,  Seth  returned  to  St  Andrews  to  receive 
the  degree  of  Doctor  of  Laws,  and  was  heartily  wel 
comed  by  students  and  former  colleagues ;  and  a  year 
later  he  and  his  wife  carried  out  a  plan  which  had 
been  several  times  made  and  postponed — to  visit  her 
mother.  Ten  weeks  were  spent  in  Germany,  and  on 
June  17  he  wrote  to  Professor  Laurie  from  Suderode 
in  the  Harz  Mountains  :  "  It  does  one's  heart  good  to  see 
hills  again  after  the  endless  sandy  flats  of  which  North 
Germany  mainly  consists.  I  could  not  bring  myself  to 
go  near  any  of  the  Berlin  professors.  These  ceremonial 
visits  interrupt  a  holiday  frame  of  mind.  I  like  to  travel 
'  in  the  strictest  incognito  '  (as  one  reads  in  the  news 
papers),  and  keep  my  evenings  for  the  opera  and  the 
play.  Four  evenings  were  accordingly  devoted  to  the 
Wagnerian  cycle — the  Ring  der  Nibelungen." 

A  pleasant  glimpse  of  the  Seth  family  during  an 
Argyllshire  holiday  in  August  1895  is  given  in  a  letter 
from  Professor  Campbell  Fraser,  who  was  himself  re 
visiting  his  native  country  by  Loch  Etive  :  "I  must 
send  a  few  words  of  gratitude  for  the  happy  hours  I 
spent  with  you,  and  the  beautiful  picture  of  your  rural 
life  which  they  have  left  in  memory.  It  was  delightful 
to  see  the  family  bathing  procession,  and  the  youngsters 
in  the  woods  as  I  drove  back  to  Loch  Nell." 


76  MEMOIR 

In  1896  Seth  was  invited  by  Mr  Balfour  to  join  the 
'  Synthetic  Society/  which  had  been  formed  to  "  con 
tribute  towards  a  working  philosophy  of  religious  belief/' 
The  members  at  this  time  were  Balfour,  George  Wynd- 
ham,  the  Bishop  of  Rochester  (Edward  Talbot),  Charles 
Gore,  Baron  Friedrich  von  Hiigel,  R.  H.  Hutton  of  the 
Spectator,  R.  C.  Jebb  and  Wilfrid  Ward.  At  each  meeting 
a  short  paper  was  read  and  discussion  followed.  Seth 
was  often  prevented  from  attending  the  meeting  of  the 
'  Synthetic  '  by  the  work  of  his  chair,  but  when  he 
could  do  so  he  highly  appreciated  the  opportunity  of 
meeting  men  whose  interpretation  of  religion  differed 
widely  in  detail,  but  who  brought  to  these  discussions 
not  only  great  ability  but  a  common  serious  purpose. 

The  field  of  academic  ceremonial  made  little  appeal 
to  Seth,  as  is  shown  by  the  letter  to  Professor  Laurie 
lately  quoted,  though  no  man  could  carry  through  his 
part  with  greater  dignity.  But  in  1896  he  made  one 
exception.  The  '  College  of  New  Jersey/  which  was 
founded  in  1746,  was  preparing  to  celebrate  its  hundred 
and  fiftieth  anniversary  by  assuming  formally  the  title 
which  it  had  commonly  borne  for  long — that  of  the 
University  of  Princeton.  Throughout  its  earlier  history 
it  was  marked  by  a  Puritan  tradition  largely  derived 
from  Scotland.  Two  of  its  most  distinguished  Presidents 
were  John  Witherspoon,  a  Scottish  Calvinist  divine  and 
teacher,  who  was  appointed  in  1768  and  steered  the 
young  College  firmly  through  the  troubled  waters  of 
the  American  War  of  Independence  ;  and  James  M'Cosh, 
author  of  a  book  on  Scottish  Philosophy,  who  took 
office  exactly  a  hundred  years  later.  It  was  thus  natural 
that  Princeton  should  wish  to  have  a  representative 
from  a  Scots  university  among  those  who  came  to  her 
Sesquicentenary,  and  that  Seth  should  be  warmly  wel 
comed  as  representing  especially  the  Scots  tradition  in 
philosophy.  His  colleague,  Professor  Calderwood,  urged 


MEMOIR  77 

him  to  go,  and,  along  with  Mr  Hardie,  made  his  absence 
possible  by  taking  his  classes  when  the  session  of  1896-97 
opened. 

Seth  crossed  the  Atlantic  at  the  end  of  September, 
and  before  going  to  Princeton  visited  Cornell,  where 
his  brother  James  had  just  become  Sage  Professor  of 
Moral  Philosophy,  and  where  he  gave  a  public  lecture 
on  '  Optimism  and  Pessimism/  On  this  occasion  Presi 
dent  Schurman  was  able  to  introduce  his  friend  to  an 
American  audience.  By  the  middle  of  October,  Andrew 
Seth  reached  Princeton,  where  the  days  preceding  the 
actual  celebration  were  devoted  to  a  series  of  lectures 
by  distinguished  guests.  The  three  lecturers  from  Britain 
were  Professor  (now  Sir)  J.  J.  Thomson,  Professor 
Dowden,  and  Seth  himself,  whose  contribution  was  pub 
lished  under  the  title  Two  Lectures  on  Theism.  At  the 
Graduation  Ceremony  he  again  stood  as  '  one  of  three.' 
This  time  he  advanced  with  Professors  William  James 
of  Harvard  and  G.  T.  Ladd  of  Yale  to  represent  Philo 
sophy,  in  face  of  a  great  company  of  scholars  and 
scientists  who  also  received  honorary  degrees. 

There  were  other  functions — an  address  from  Presi 
dent  Cleveland,  a  procession  of  alumni  and  the  in 
evitable  torch-light  procession ;  and  in  an  account  of 
the  ceremonies  contributed  to  the  Scotsman  on  his 
return,  Seth  described  in  detail  the  Princeton  yell  at 
an  inter-collegiate  football  match.  He  was  more  seri 
ously  impressed  by  the  recital  of  an  ode  by  Dr  Henry 
Van  Dyke,  and  the  response  to  a  speech  at  the  final 
banquet,  in  which  Professor  Goldwin  Smith  of  Toronto 
pled  for  greater  mutual  trust  between  the  United  States 
and  the  British  Empire.  Only  three  years  had  passed 
since  President  Cleveland's  message  on  the  Venezuela 
dispute  had  stirred  bitter  feelings  on  both  sides  of  the 
Atlantic ;  but  so  profoundly  was  the  audience  moved 
by  Goldwin  Smith's  "  sombre  and  mournful  eloquence  " 


78  MEMOIR 

that  his  speech  ended  with  cheers  for  Old  England 
raised  in  the  body  of  the  hall.  As  the  reader  of  to-day 
looks  through  the  report  of  the  gathering  in  the  Prince- 
tonian  journal,  that  which  awakens  his  keenest  interest 
is  a  eulogy  entitled  '  Princeton  in  the  Nation's  Service  ' 
by  a  young  Professor  of  Law.  It  ends  with  a  glowing 
description  of  the  university  of  the  speaker's  dreams, 
and  with  the  question  :  "  Who  shall  show  us  the  way 
to  this  place  ?  "  The  speaker  was  Woodrow  Wilson. 

Seth  summed  up  his  impressions  in  a  letter  to  Mr 
Balfour :  "I  had  a  thoroughly  enjoyable  time  on  the 
other  side,  not  only  at  Princeton,  but  at  Harvard, 
Cornell  and  other  places,  including  Niagara.  The  kind 
ness  and  hospitality  one  received  everywhere  was  un 
bounded,  and  the  interest  of  the  visit  was  very  great." 
Towards  the  end  of  a  stormy  homeward  passage  on  the 
Lucania  he  wrote  in  a  similar  strain  to  his  brother  at 
Cornell,  and  told  how  the  discomfort  of  the  voyage  had 
been  lightened  by  the  presence  of  other  delegates  return 
ing  from  the  celebration,  and  not  less  by  the  reading  of 
Sentimental  Tommy,  then  newly  published. 

Early  in  1897  Two  Lectures  on  Theism  and  Man's 
Place  in  the  Cosmos  both  appeared.  These  volumes 
may  be  taken  as  placing  the  copestone  on  Seth's  work 
as  a  thinker  up  to  this  point,  and  both  contain  much 
of  his  most  polished  and  incisive  writing.  Although  the 
Two  Lectures  are  avowedly  only  an  outline,  they  definitely 
point  the  way  towards  an  ethical  theism  set  free  from 
the  defects  of  Pantheism  on  the  one  hand  and  Deism 
on  the  other.  The  larger  volume  in  its  original  form 
contained  the  Inaugural  Address  of  1891  and  essays 
published  during  the  five  following  years  on  Huxley's 
Romanes  Lecture,  Balfour's  Foundations  of  Belief, 
Miinsterberg's  theory  of  psychological  automatism  and 
Bradley's  Appearance  and  Reality.  In  an  enlarged 
edition  published  in  1902  there  were  added  an  apprecia- 


MEMOIR  79 

tion  of  Campbell  Eraser's  Gifford  Lectures  and  a  long 
paper  on  "The  Life  and  Opinions  of  Friedrich  Nietzsche," 
which  appeared  at  a  time  when  Nietzsche  was  still  im 
perfectly  understood  in  this  country. 

The  territory  traversed  in  these  essays  is  wide,  and 
they  show  Seth's  power  of  constructive  criticism  in  fields 
that  were  not  primarily  his  own — ethics  in  the  essay  on 
Nietzsche  and  psychology  in  that  on  Miinsterberg.  In 
the  short  essay  on  Huxley's  Evolution  and  Ethics,  with 
which  the  volume  opens,  there  is  one  of  the  compara 
tively  rare  passages  in  which  he  allows  his  latent  moral 
passion  to  appear,  as  he  dismisses  in  a  few  scornful 
sentences  the  immoralist  theory  of  the  family. 

Seth  himself  claimed  that  there  was  an  underlying 
unity  in  the  book,  for  all  the  essays  treated  at  bottom 
the  same  theme — "  man's  relation  to  the  forces  of 
nature  and  to  the  absolute  ground  of  things,  or,  in  the 
words  of  the  title,  man's  place  in  the  cosmos." — (Pref.) 
This  shows  the  movement,  already  noted,  of  his  thought 
at  this  time  from  epistemology  to  ontology  ;  yet  the  two 
lay  not  far  apart,  and  the  first  lecture  in  Theism  gave 
effective  expression  to  the  contention  which  he  always 
maintained,  that  "  the  knower  is  in  the  world  which  he 
comes  to  know,  and  the  forms  of  his  thoughts,  so  far  from 
being  an  alien  growth  or  an  imported  product,  are  them 
selves  a  function  of  the  whole  "  (p.  19).  His  criticism 
of  Mr  Bradley  also  dealt  in  part  with  the  theory  of 
knowledge.  It  called  forth  widespread  interest,  not  only 
for  its  matter  but  because  of  its  effective  form.  A 
writer  had  now  appeared  who  could  meet  that  master  of 
philosophic  wit  and  raillery  with  "  a  fine-edged  irony  " 
(to  borrow  a  phrase  of  Seth's  regarding  Berkeley)  hardly 
less  dexterous  and  penetrating  than  his  own. 

The  original  publication  of  the  articles  gathered  in 
Man's  Place  in  the  Cosmos  brought  to  the  author  several 
letters  of  more  than  passing  interest.  Mr  William 


8o  MEMOIR 

Blackwood,  the  head  of  the  famous  house  which  had 
already  published  two  of  his  books,  wrote  welcoming 
him  as  a  contributor  to  '  Maga.'  Dr  Martineau,  then 
in  his  eighty-ninth  year,  wrote  on  November  29,  1893  : 
"  I  have  read  your  essay  on  '  Man's  Place  in  Nature  ' 
with  the  keenest  interest,  and  with  all  but  unqualified 
assent  to  its  reasoning  and  its  critical  estimates  through 
out.  I  would  fain  express  to  you,  if  I  could,  the  happy 
confidence  with  which,  at  the  end  of  life,  I  anticipate 
from  you  the  much-needed  reaction  from  the  dominant 
Hegelian  form  of  Idealism.  My  hopes  in  this  respect 
used  to  rest,  as  I  often  told  him,  on  Thomas  Hill 
Green,  whose  noble  moral  nature  was  always  pressing 
him  in  that  direction.  And  now  it  is  my  fancy  that 
his  mission  has  devolved  on  you.  It  is  a  great  trust ; 
and  may  be  executed  with  full  acknowledgment  of  the 
lofty  influence,  intellectual  and  ethical,  exercised  by 
his  genius  and  Edward  Caird's  during  their  period  of 
ascendancy.  But  they  have  not  said  the  last  word  in 
philosophy,  and  would  be  the  first  to  repudiate  the 
pretension/' 

The  same  day's  post  brought  a  long  letter  from  a 
thinker  of  a  very  different  school,  Mr  Leslie  Stephen, 
to  whose  work  reference  was  made  in  the  article  which 
dealt  primarily  with  Huxley's  Romanes  Lecture.  "  I 
used  to  suppose  that  men  of  your  way  of  thinking  were 
bound  to  hold  that  men  of  my  way  of  thinking  were 
fools,  and  also  to  suppose  that  we  were  bound  to  return 
the  compliment.  I  am  very  glad  to  take  your  article 
as  an  indication  of  the  growing  tendency — and  I  hope 
growing  on  both  sides — to  greater  courtesy  and  better 
appreciation  of  each  other.  ...  I  cannot  help  believing 
for  my  own  part  that  there  is  more  agreement  between 
us  than  appears — perhaps  rather  more  than  either  of 
us  can  precisely  see  at  the  moment.  I  wish  that  I  were 
in  the  position  to  have  the  advantage  of  an  occasional 


MEMOIR  81 

talk  with  you  ;  when  I  am  sure  that  I  should  learn- 
even  though  I  am  growing  rather  too  old  and  stiff  in 
the  joints  to  change  my  habits  of  mind  or  body.  I  now 
and  then  see  your  friend  Haldane,  when  he  is  not  im 
mersed  in  briefs  or  parliamentary  warfare  ;  and  it  is 
always  a  great  pleasure  to  meet  him."  Professor 
Huxley  wrote  at  the  same  time :  "  Accept  my  cordial 
thanks  for  defending  me  and  still  more  for  understanding 
me.  I  really  have  been  unable  to  understand  what  my 
critics  have  been  dreaming  of — when  they  raise  the 
objection  that  the  ethical  process  being  part  of  the 
cosmic  process  cannot  be  opposed  to  it.  They  might 
as  well  say  that  artifice  does  not  oppose  Nature,  because 
it  is  part  of  Nature  in  the  broadest  sense." 

So  also  Mr  Balfour,  three  years  later,  when  the  article 
on  his  Foundations  of  Belief  first  appeared  :  "  You  have 
done  a  real  service,  both  to  me  and  to  any  of  my  readers 
who  were  fortunate  enough  to  see  what  you  have  written, 
by  giving  so  admirable  a  summary  of  the  general  line 
of  argument  which  I  have  endeavoured  to  set  forth. 
I  had  almost  gone  to  the  length  of  saying  that  you  are 
the  only  critic  of  any  importance  who  has  taken  the 
trouble  to  find  out  what  that  line  of  argument  really  is  ; 
the  rest  seem  chiefly  interested  in  discussing  such  frag 
mentary  portions  of  the  work  as  happen  to  be  in  collision 
with  their  own  private  views." 

But  the  essay  which  called  for  the  largest  body  of 
appreciative  comment  was  that  entitled  "A  New  Theory 
of  the  Absolute. ' '  Mr  Bradley  himself  wrote  on  November 
17,  1894  :  "  It  is  a  great  pleasure  to  see  that  you  estimate 
my  work  at  sa  high  a  value.  I  hope  my  book  will  be 
useful  as  to  some  extent  drawing  conclusions  explicitly 
which  many  were  drawing  in  private,  and  as  raising 
those  questions  which  many  were  feeling  should  be 
pressed  to  an  answer  one  way  or  the  other."  He  went 
on  to  admit  the  justice  of  some  of  Seth's  criticism,  while 

F 


82  MEMOIR 

soon  after  he  sent  an  elaborate  answer  to  a  number 
which  he  could  not  so  accept. 

Regarding  the  two  books  which  Seth  had  sent  him, 
Baron  Friedrich  von  Hugel  wrote  :  "  I  have  rarely 
indeed  seen  anything  with  which  I  have  found  myself 
in  more  constant  sympathy  and  grateful  agreement,  or 
which  seemed  to  me  as  full  of  the  most  reverent  spirit, 
combined  with  a  noble  breadth  of  knowledge  and  of 
outlook.  ...  I  was  glad  when  I  was  staying  at  Jena 
with  my  close  friend  Professor  Eucken,  to  find  how  well 
he  and  his  students  know  and  love  your  work.  .  .  . 
Scattered  about  Europe  I  have  some  nine  or  ten  philo 
sopher  friends  and  admired  writers  :  among  these  you 
count,  if  I  may  admit  it,  as  one  of  the  latter/' 

Dr  John  MacCunn's  appreciation  has  a  lighter  touch 
than  the  rest  :  "  Many  thanks  for  a  valuable  and  valued 
book.  I  have  hardly  had  a  moment's  time  to  look  into 
it.  So  that  this  is  grace  before  meat,  and  by  no  means 
meant  as  a  substitute  for  the  thanksgiving  which  I  know 
I  shall  feel  impelled  to  render  after  partaking.  Your 
treatment  of  Huxley  is  the  most  justly  appreciative  yet 
firmest  I  have  read.  And  I  welcome,  I  think,  almost 
everything  you  say  about  the  new  psychology.  I  dare 
say  it  may  come  of  psychological  ignorance  on  my  part ; 
but  I  never  meet  the  diagrams  and  the  physiological 
fluencies  about '  paths  of  discharge  '  and  suchlike  without 
the  feeling  that,  having  set  out  to  pursue  philosophy,  I 
had  fallen  helpless  into  a  natural  science  ambuscade." 

Seth's  helping  hand  was  welcomed  by  many  in  a  like 
predicament. 


83 


CHAPTER  VII. 

THE   HAINING. 

1898-1914. 

ANDREW  SETH  had  now  reached  his  forty-second  year, 
and  the  future  seemed  to  lie  clear  before  him  with  no 
prospect  of  any  sharp  deviation  from  the  path  which 
he  had  hitherto  followed.  But  at  this  point  a  change 
occurred  which,  to  his  friends  at  least,  was  sudden  and 
unlooked-for ;  and  he  and  his  wife  found  themselves 
in  possession  of  a  new  home  in  the  heart  of  the  Border 
country,  and  with  it  of  the  surname  by  which  they 
were  henceforth  known.  To  explain  this  change  of  scene 
and  of  name  we  must  go  back  for  several  generations. 

During  more  than  two  centuries  the  estate  of  Haining 
—the  original  Scots  meaning  of  the  name  is  '  enclosure/ 
part  '  hained  off ' — lying  close  to  the  ancient  burgh  of 
Selkirk,  belonged  to  a  branch  of  a  widely  known  Border 
family,  the  Pringles.  The  lairds  of  Haining  were  men 
of  note  in  the  eighteenth  century,  as  one  of  them  was 
raised  to  the  Scottish  Bench  in  1729  with  the  life  title 
of  Lord  Haining,  and  later  his  son,  a  judge  of  excep 
tional  eminence,  assumed  that  of  Lord  Alemoor.  But 
during  the  nineteenth  century  the  family  fortunes  and 
influence  declined,  and  the  male  line  died  out.  Twice 
the  estate  passed  to  a  daughter,  and  in  each  case  her 
husband  placed  the  name  Pringle  before  his  own.  Thus 


84  MEMOIR 

it  came  about  that  first  Mrs  Pringle-Douglas,  and  then 
her  daughter,  Mrs  Pringle-Pattison,  lived  at  the  Haining. 
Mrs  Pringle-Pattison  had  no  children,  and  she  bequeathed 
all  her  possessions  to  her  husband  if  he  survived  her 
without  issue.  But  it  remained  to  provide  for  the  event 
of  his  dying  before  her  ;  and  she  and  her  husband  knew 
something  of  the  Seth  family,  with  which  he  was  dis 
tantly  connected  through  the  Littles.  So,  in  view  of 
the  great  promise  shown  by  Andrew,  then  a  lad  of  about 
sixteen,  she  decided  to  insert  his  name  in  her  will. 

During  the  years  that  followed  he  heard  occasionally 
of  or  from  Mrs  Pringle-Pattison  through  his  mother  or 
one  of  her  sisters  ;  but  if  any  expectation  that  he  would 
finally  receive  The  Haining  was  aroused  in  his  own  mind, 
he  kept  it  concealed  there.  While  he  was  at  St  Andrews 
John  Pringle-Pattison  died,  and  ten  years  later  his  wife, 
whose  later  years  were  clouded  by  persistent  illness, 
died  also.  Only  then  did  the  surprising  fact  become 
known  that  she  had  bequeathed  her  whole  estate  to  her 
husband's  distant  cousin,  on  the  condition  that  he 
assumed  the  name  Pringle-Pattison.  The  terms  of  her 
will  were  clear  ;  but  its  provisions  were  so  unusual  that 
they  could  hardly  be  expected  to  pass  quite  unchallenged. 
More  than  one  counter-claim  was  raised,  but,  largely  on 
the  initiative  of  Pringle-Pattison  (as  he  had  now  become), 
these  were  settled  without  recourse  to  the  courts  ;  and 
he  agreed  as  an  act  of  grace  to  pay  annuities  to  two 
claimants  who  were  advanced  in  years. 

The  way  was  thus  clear  for  him  to  enter  upon  his 
new  domain.  Its  possession  had  both  an  attractive  and 
a  burdensome  aspect.  Its  situation  in  a  land  of  romance, 
at  the  very  gates  of  the  town  in  which  Sir  Walter  Scott 
held  office  for  a  generation  as  Sheriff  of  Ettrick  Forest, 
and  within  riding,  or  even  walking,  distance  of  Abbots- 
ford  and  Melrose,  appealed  both  to  the  poet  in  him  and 
to  his  patriotism  as  a  Borderer  by  descent.  "  On  another 


Page  Sit. 


MEMOIR  85 

side,"  Mr  Capper  has  said,  "  the  change  in  his  position 
appealed  to  his  sense  of  humour,  and  he  made  a  solemn 
expedition  to  a  distant  burial-place  of  the  Pringles,  to 
visit,  as  he  told  me,  '  the  tombs  of  his  new  ancestors/ 
His  young  family  were  of  an  age  to  profit  to  the  full  by 
their  enlarged  opportunities  of  country  life  and  to  grow 
up  familiar  with  its  society  and  pursuits;  while  they, 
in  turn,  brought  sunshine  into  a  mansion  which  had 
seen  no  children  for  a  hundred  years."  x  Nor  was  it 
only  within  The  Haining  gates  and  by  the  wood-encircled 
loch  lying  just  beyond  the  house  that  their  presence 
brought  about  a  change.  The  townsfolk  of  Selkirk,  who 
had  for  long  watched  the  slow  decay  of  an  ancient 
house,  welcomed  heartily  the  vigorous,  clean-blooded, 
young  life  \vhich  now  found  a  home  there. 

Haining  House,  like  many  Scottish  country  houses, 
was  built  at  two  different  periods,  and  in  contrasted, 
not  to  say  incongruous,  styles.  The  original  part,  prob 
ably  about  four  hundred  years  old,  was  a  fine  example 
of  the  traditional  style  of  the  country,  with  rough-cast 
walls  and  small  windows.  Part  was  demolished  in  1794, 
and  there  was  added  to  what  was  left  standing  a  new 
part  in  the  classical  style,  with  a  large  portico  at  the 
entrance,  and  high  windows  opening  on  a  lawn  which 
sloped  steeply  down  to  the  loch. 

The  main  part  of  the  estate  lay  south  of  the  Et trick 
Water,  looking  down  upon  Philiphaugh,  where  Yarrow 
and  Ettrick  meet,  and  where  the  hitherto  unbeaten 
Montrose  suffered  his  first  defeat  one  misty  morning  in 
1645.  To  the  south-east  it  extended  to  the  Water  of 
Ale,  the  perilous  crossing  of  which  figures  in  the  tale  of 
Sir  William  of  Deloraine's  ride  in  the  Lay  of  the  Last 
Minstrel.  There  were  also  three  outlying  portions.  One 
was  north  of  the  Tweed,  Fairnilee,  whose  peel  tower 
inspired  a  romantic  tale  by  Andrew  Lang.  A  second, 
1  Proceedings  of  the  British  Academy,  Vol.  xvii. 


86  MEMOIR 

Alemoor  Farm,  was  twelve  miles  to  the  south,  by  the 
moorland  loch  from  which  the  Ale  flows  ;  and  it  was 
from  this  that  Andrew  Pringle,  the  second  of  the  judges 
already  mentioned,  took  his  title,  Lord  Alemoor.  The 
third,  also  an  upland  farm,  was  named  Adders toneshiels, 
and  lay  to  the  south-east  not  far  from  the  Limekilnedge 
pass,  by  which  Dandie  Dinmont,  like  his  creator,  Sir 
Walter  himself,  used  to  ride  into  Liddesdale. 

The  management  of  this  scattered  estate  of  over  7000 
acres  would  have  made  a  heavy  call  on  the  means  and 
time  of  its  owner,  even  if  the  property  had  previously 
been  well  maintained.  But  during  the  long  period  when 
Mrs  Pringle-Pattison  was  unable  to  supervise  it,  the 
work  of  maintenance  had  been  neglected,  and  her  suc 
cessor  found  heavy  arrears  awaiting  him.  At  once  he 
set  himself  to  master  the  problems  of  estate  manage 
ment,  for  which  his  previous  academic  life  had  in  no 
way  prepared  him.  He  had  an  able  adviser  in  Mr  Curie 
of  Melrose,  one  of  a  family  distinguished  by  their 
knowledge  of  archseology  as  well  as  of  land.  But 
he  never  believed  in  delegating  tasks  which  he  could 
perform  himself,  and  he  soon  established  a  direct  contact 
with  those  who  gained  their  living  from  the  land  which 
had  so  unexpectedly  come  to  him.  Just  as  invitations 
to  stay  at  The  Haining  were  generally  written  in  his 
own  hand,  so  he  attended  in  person  to  requests  for 
repairs  and  improvements  on  the  estate.  The  public 
burdens  on  agricultural  land  were  not,  indeed,  as  heavy 
in  the  early  years  of  his  proprietorship  as  they  became 
later;  but  they  were  already  considerable,  and,  along 
with  the  other  circumstances  mentioned,  made  his  task 
far  from  easy  on  the  financial  side.  He  had  to  gain 
experience  from  the  outset  in  this  sternly  practical  school 
— one  fact  that  he  mentioned  as  having  surprised  him 
was  the  large  proportion  of  the  estate  revenue  which 
went  in  fencing  alone — but  his  friends  watched  him  as 


MEMOIR  87 

he  applied  his  clear  and  resourceful  intellect  to  a  quite 
unfamiliar  situation,  and  gradually  solved  the  problems 
which  confronted  him.  After  some  years  he  was  able 
to  sell  Fairnilee  and  Adderstoneshiels.  To  part  with 
Fairnilee  was  a  real  sacrifice  to  him  ;  but  when  this 
was  done  he  found  himself  at  last  with  a  sufficiency  of 
free  capital  to  finance  the  remaining  portions  of  the 
estate. 

As  Pringle-Pattison  gradually  and  patiently  cleared 
away  the  entanglements  which  met  him  when  he  first 
went  to  The  Haining,  the  interest  of  the  work  grew  upon 
him.  In  other  directions  he  prepared  for  his  new  station 
in  life.  He  took  riding  lessons,  though  he  did  not  follow 
up  his  new  accomplishment ;  and  in  spite  of  his  indifferent 
eyesight  he  became  a  reasonably  good  shot,  and  before 
many  summers  had  passed  his  two  elder  boys  were  able 
to  join  him  in  shooting  over  the  estate. 

Among  the  letters  which  arrived  after  the  new  owner 
ship  of  The  Haining  was  announced  was  one  dated 
March  15,  1898,  from  10  Downing  Street  :— 

"  My  dear  Seth — or  perhaps  I  ought  to  say  now,  Seth 
Pringle-Pattison,— 

I  am  delighted  to  hear  of  your  good  fortune,  which 
I  should  certainly  not  be  if  I  thought  it  would  cause 
you,  even  for  a  moment,  to  abandon  philosophy.  I 
hope,  on  the  contrary,  that  you  will  now  be  able  to  choose 
precisely  the  circumstances  most  favourable  to  original 
work. — With  every  congratulation,  Believe  me,  Yours 
very  sincerely, 

ARTHUR  JAMES  BALFOUR." 

In  August  of  the  same  year  Professor  Campbell  Fraser 
wrote  :— 

"  Let  me  thank  your  wife  and  you  very  much  for  our 
three  charming  days  at  The  Haining,  the  impression  of 


88  MEMOIR 

which  will  not  leave  us  soon.  It  was  indeed  a  satisfaction 
to  see  you  all  so  happily  settled  amidst  such  surround 
ings  ;  and  you  with  an  added  career  opened  to  you, 
not  less  responsible  than  an  academical  one,  associating 
Scottish  philosophy  with  a  romance  unprecedented  in 
its  history.  Long  may  you  all  enjoy  and  benefit  by  it 
in  every  way/' 

Next  to  welcoming  his  friends  at  The  Haining  there 
was  no  part  of  Pringle-Pattison's  life  there  which  de 
lighted  him  so  much  as  the  care  of  the  beautiful  trees 
on  the  estate  and  the  planning  of  fresh  plantations. 
Pruning  and  felling,  especially  round  the  house,  he 
carried  out  as  far  as  possible  himself,  with  the  help  of 
his  boys  and  of  any  guests  to  whom  this  occupation  might 
appeal.  In  his  first  months  at  The  Haining  he  collected 
a  formidable  outfit  of  axe,  bill  and  various  types  of 
saw,  including  a  fearsome  instrument  known  as  the  pole- 
saw  for  the  pruning  of  high  branches.  When  he  could 
form  a  small  forestry  party,  he  supplied  each  with  a 
different  tool ;  and,  when  he  was  obliged  to  go  alone, 
he  carried  a  smaller  selection  for  his  own  use. 

Other  interests  were  provided  by  the  customs  and 
traditions  of  Selkirk,  handed  down  through  several 
centuries  and  still  practised.  As  in  other  Border  burghs, 
the  great  day  is  that  of  the  Common  Riding  in  June, 
when  the  Cornet  for  the  year  rides,  suitably  attended, 
round  the  ancient  Marches  or  boundaries  of  the  town's 
land.  There  is  also  the  ancient  Forest  Club,  consisting 
largely  of  neighbouring  landowners,  of  which  Pringle- 
Pattison  was  elected  a  member.  The  members  meet 
for  dinner  twice  a  year,  clad  in  the  traditional  costume 
of  buff  waistcoat  and  evening  coat  of  archer  green.  The 
fact  that  Sir  Walter  Scott  was  a  member  of  the  Club 
appealed  strongly  to  Pringle-Pattison's  historical  sense. 

His  wife's  early  memories  of  her  home  in  a  Silesian 
manor  made  it  natural  for  her  to  take  up  the  thread  of 


MEMOIR  89 

country  life  after  long  residence  in  cities,  and  she  entered 
fully  into  her  husband's  new  interests.  Their  summer 
home  became  a  centre  of  wide  hospitality,  and  some 
times  unexpected  guests  found  their  way  there.  One 
photograph  from  the  first  years  of  the  century  shows  the 
commanding  figure  of  General  Booth  along  with  The 
Haining  family  and  guests.  He  had  come  for  a  night 
when  addressing  a  series  of  meetings  in  the  Border  towns, 
but  no  record  survives  of  any  theological  discussion 
between  himself  and  his  host.  Many  of  those  who  found 
their  way  to  The  Haining  have  already  been  named  in 
this  Memoir,  for  no  man  was  ever  more  loyal  to  old 
friends  than  Pringle-Pattison.  His  own  kinsfolk  came, 
and  his  early  companions  Mr  Capper  and  Professor 
Stalker  brought  their  families,  as  did  Dr  Schurman 
when  visiting  Europe.  The  MacCunns  came,  and,  with 
them  or  alone,  Professor  W.  P.  Ker.  Lord  Haldane 
came  when  his  official  duties  allowed,  and  his  close 
friend,  Professor  Hume  Brown,  for  long  Pringle-Pattison's 
valued  colleague  in  Edinburgh  University  where  he  held 
the  Chair  of  Scottish  History  and  Palaeography.  In 
later  years  the  Cardiff  friend,  already  named,  Mr  W.  P. 
James,  found  his  way  to  The  Haining ;  and  there  were 
many  more,  including  from  time  to  time  former  members 
of  Pringle-Pattison's  classes. 

On  first  arrival,  one  of  these  friends  has  said,  there 
was  sometimes  a  slight  passing  feeling  of  constraint,  due 
to  the  native  shyness  of  the  host ;  but  very  quickly 
this  passed,  and  in  half  an  hour  talk  would  flow  freely. 
The  circle  was  not  dominated  by  either  husband  or 
wife,  but  both  together  formed  its  centre,  her  invariable 
kindness  being  set  in  relief  by  a  shrewd  judgment  of 
people  and  things,  as  his  was  by  the  "  occasional  and 
delightful  causticity  "  of  his  remarks,  as  well  as  by  the 
"  sudden  bursts  of  hilarity  "  of  which  another  friend  has 
spoken.  His  laugh,  like  that  of  some  other  habitually 


90  MEMOIR 

serious  men,  had  an  explosive  quality,  which  made  it 
singularly  infectious. 

But  the  deepest  impression  made  on  those  who  came 
to  know  The  Haining  well  was  that  described  by  one  of 
them  as  "  its  extraordinary  atmosphere — patriarchal, 
united,  natural. ' '  The  professor's  intellectual  life  pursued 
its  own  course,  for  he  remained  the  only  member  of  the 
family  who  was  interested  in  formal  philosophy,  but 
this  formed  no  barrier  against  the  truest  sympathy 
between  the  children  and  both  their  parents.  Even 
with  friends  who  had  for  long  shared  his  own  dominating 
interests,  the  sharing  was  so  complete  that  it  could  often 
dispense  with  words.  Mrs  MacCunn  has  described  the 
"  perfect  silent  understanding  "  between  three  of  the 
circle — her  husband,  Pringle-Pattison  and  W.  P.  Ker  ; 
and  after  the  death  of  the  last-named,  Pringle-Pattison 
set  down  his  memory  of  one  occasion  when  a  large  party 
had  climbed  the  Eildon  Hills,  and  "  W.  P.  very  char 
acteristically  insisted  on  our  taking  the  three  heights  in 
their  order.  We  rested  on  the  third,  and  a  little  apart 
from  the  young  party  W.  P.  crouched  on  a  rock,  and, 
going  near,  I  heard  him  chanting  to  himself  the  '  Flowers 
laugh  before  thee  in  their  beds  '  verse  of  Wordsworth's 
Ode  to  Duty." 

With  this  we  may  join  an  account  given  by  Professor 
MacCunn  in  Our  Friend,  W.  P.:  " Perhaps  the  happiest 
social  function  at  which  I  have  ever  assisted  was  the 
Yarrow  Show  of  1908.  He  [W.  P.  Ker]  was  staying 
with  us  at  Dryhope  on  St  Mary's  Loch,  and  we  were 
amused  at  his  determination  that  we  should  all  go  to 
this  gathering.  He  was  eager  to  meet  his  friends  the 
Pringle-Pattisons — when  was  he  not  anxious  to  meet  his 
friends  ? — and  to  see  Will  Ogilvy's  noble  horsemanship. 
The  holms  of  Yarrow  on  a  clear  autumn  day  have  a  spell 
all  their  own ;  but  for  him  behind  all  these  were  memories 
of  Christ's  Kirk  on  the  Green  and  Peebles  to  the  Play." 


MEMOIR  91 

Expeditions  such  as  those  described  to  the  triple 
summit  of  the  Eildons,  or  up  Yarrow  to  Newark  Castle 
and  St  Mary's  Loch,  or  to  the  still  lonelier  recesses  of 
Ettrick,  or  eastward  as  far  as  Dryburgh  and  Smailholm 
Tower,  were  characteristic  of  summer  days  at  The 
Haining.  The  waggonette  would  convey  the  older 
members  of  the  party  with  generous  provision  for  all 
(unless  a  country  inn  formed  the  goal  of  the  expedition) , 
while  the  younger  would  walk  on  ahead  or  act  as  scouts 
and  skirmishers  on  a  generous  supply  of  bicycles.  But 
that  the  push-bicycle  had  displaced  the  ponies  of  an 
earlier  day,  Lockhart's  description  of  the  expeditions 
which  Sir  Walter  organised  and  led  from  Abbotsford  to 
the  Eildons  or  Ettrick  would  apply  almost  unchanged 
to  those  from  The  Haining  nearly  a  century  later. 

If  in  the  present  section  little  attention  has  been  paid 
to  chronology,  this  is  due  to  the  fact  that  life  at  The 
Haining  in  spring,  in  summer,  or  at  Christmas — when 
the  Christmas  tree  was  honoured  with  an  enthusiasm 
worthy  of  Mrs  Pringle-Pattison's  native  land — changed 
only  as  the  growth  of  the  sons  and  daughters  enabled 
them  to  take  a  fuller  share  in  the  activities  which  their 
parents  planned.  There  was,  however,  one  landmark, 
for  in  the  year  1909  a  double  event  took  place,  which 
called  out  the  goodwill  of  the  townsfolk  of  Selkirk  as 
well  as  those  who  lived  on  the  estate  itself — the  Silver 
Wedding  of  the  parents  and  the  Coming-of-age  of  the 
eldest  son. 

Two  years  later  history  in  the  making  knocked  sud 
denly  and  somewhat  rudely  at  the  doors  of  The  Haining, 
bringing  some  premonition  of  the  events  of  1914.  Richard 
Haldane,  who  had  shortly  before  gone  to  the  House  of 
Lords  as  Viscount  Haldane  of  Cloan,  had  arranged  to 
come  for  a  week-end  visit  in  the  latter  part  of  August. 
He  duly  arrived,  but  at  that  moment  the  Agadir  crisis, 
following  a  sudden  railway  strike,  became  acute.  The 


92  MEMOIR 

local  post-office  was  accustomed  to  take  its  Sabbath 
rest  undisturbed,  and  it  took  all  the  authority  of  the 
Minister  for  War  to  persuade  the  reluctant  officials 
that  their  day  of  rest  must  on  this  occasion  be  sacrificed, 
and  all  Sunday  a  steady  stream  of  telegrams  came  and 
went.  To  describe  the  course  or  ending  of  the  crisis  is 
no  part  of  our  purpose  here ;  but  it  is  worth  noting 
that  even  the  pressure  of  these  critical  days  did  not 
wholly  thrust  philosophy  aside,  for  Lord  Haldane  wrote 
on  August  30  from  Cloan  :  "I  have  copied  out  the 
passage  in  the  smaller  Logic  which  seems  to  me  to 
contain  the  kernel  of  Hegel  and  to  which  I  referred 
when  we  were  talking.  I  much  enjoyed  our  talk.  It  is 
rarely  one  meets  in  these  days  a  fellow  pilgrim." 


93 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

UNIVERSITY  TEACHING  AND   CORRESPONDENCE 
WITH   FRIENDS. 

1898-1914. 

IT  was  only  for  a  few  months  in  1898  that  the  title 
'  Professor  Seth  '  was  in  abeyance  in  the  philosophical 
department  of  Edinburgh  University.  We  have  seen 
how  it  came  to  be  relinquished  by  its  previous  holder, 
but  by  the  end  of  the  year  it  was  taken  up  again  by  his 
brother  James  on  his  appointment  to  the  Chair  of  Moral 
Philosophy.  The  change  may  have  been  somewhat 
confusing  to  those  who  were  members  of  the  University 
before  it  took  place ;  but  to  the  students  of  later 
years  there  was  a  certain  advantage  in  the  fact  that 
two  brothers,  teaching  closely  related  subjects,  possessed 
different  surnames.  Yet,  if  the  truth  must  be  told, 
even  those  who  most  profoundly  admired  the  elder 
seldom  troubled  to  use  in  ordinary  talk  any  designation 
longer  than  the  convenient  symbol,  SP2. 

The  appointment  of  James  Seth  as  colleague  to  his 
brother  inaugurated  a  collaboration  which  was  perhaps 
unique,  and  which  brought  great  benefits  to  the  Univer 
sity  during  the  next  twenty-one  years.  At  the  end  of 
the  previous  year  Pringle-Pattison  (as  he  shortly  after 
wards  became)  wrote  to  ask  the  advice  of  Mr  Balfour 
on  the  situation  caused  by  the  death  of  "  my  good  kind 
colleague,  Calderwood,"  and  to  find  out  how  he  would 


94  MEMOIR 

regard  the  candidature  of  his  brother,  then  at  Cornell, 
for  the  Moral  Philosophy  chair — a  step  which  was  urged 
by  the  three  veteran  philosophers  of  Edinburgh  :  Camp 
bell  Eraser,  Hutchison  Stirling  and  Laurie.  In  a  most 
judicial  reply,  Mr  Balfour  stated  his  view  that  James 
Seth  was  the  strongest  of  the  probable  candidates,  and 
so,  on  the  principle  that  the  post  should  go  to  the  best 
available  man,  was  entitled  to  receive  it.  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  he  raised  the  questions  how  the  prospect 
of  having  two  brothers  in  the  professorships  of  philosophy 
was  likely  to  impress  the  electors,  and  whether  students 
of  philosophy  might  not  be  deprived  by  this  arrange 
ment  of  the  variety  of  teaching  which  they  were  entitled 
to  expect,  even  though  each  brother  maintained  his 
originality  and  independence. 

Finally,  James  Seth  decided  to  stand,  moved  in  part 
by  the  persuasions  of  his  friends  in  Edinburgh,  and  in 
part,  as  his  brother  expressed  it,  by  "an  inextinguish 
able  yearning  to  return  to  his  native  land."  He  was 
appointed  to  the  vacant  chair  ;  and  with  the  brothers 
were  intimately  associated  in  the  philosophical  depart 
ment  for  many  years  Mr  R.  P.  Hardie  as  Lecturer  in 
Ancient  Philosophy,  and  Mr  Henry  Barker,  who  had 
recently  won  the  Shaw  Philosophical  Fellowship,  as 
Lecturer  in  Ethics  and,  till  1906,  also  in  Advanced 
Psychology. 

One  happy  result  of  James  Seth's  return  was  that  he 
could  now  rejoin  his  mother,  who  had  come  back  from 
Canada  to  Scotland  some  years  before.  "  His  return 
in  honour  to  his  native  city  gave  her  keen  satisfaction. 
She  was  a  woman  of  remarkable  force  of  character,  in 
whom  depth  of  feeling  was  happily  mated  with  a  lively 
sense  of  humour,  and  till  her  death  in  1911  at  the  age 
of  eighty  she  presided  over  her  son's  household  and 
entertained  his  guests."  1  These  words  were  written 
1  A.  S.  Pringle-Pattison,  Memoir  of  James  Seth,  p.  xxv.  f . 


MEMOIR  95 

by  her  eldest  son  fourteen  years  after  her  death ;  and 
later  still  he  wrote  acknowledging  a  friend's  description 
of  an  evening  in  her  society,  and  added  :  "  My  mother's 
laughter  (to  tears)  and  her  interested  face  as  she  followed 
the  conversation  round  the  table  are  eminently  char 
acteristic."  It  is,  perhaps,  not  out  of  place  to  add  that 
successive  generations  of  students  who  even  for  a  short 
time  met  the  venerable  mother,  alert,  dignified,  kindly, 
felt  that  they  had  discovered  one  main  secret  of  the 
distinction  of  the  sons. 

As  such  students  look  back,  they  will  be  in  almost 
complete  agreement  that  there  was  little  ground  for 
any  fear  that  the  philosophical  teaching  given  by  the 
brothers  in  Edinburgh  University  would  lack  variety. 
Both,  indeed,  held  the  same  idealistic  creed,  though  not 
in  exactly  the  same  form.  Both  were  single-minded, 
disinterested,  generous  ;  and  the  old  words  were  true 
of  them,  par  nobile  fratrum.  Yet  they  showed  their 
greatness  as  teachers  in  markedly  different  ways.  From 
the  start  there  was  a  difference  in  temperament ;  for, 
while  both  were  naturally  sensitive,  the  elder  was  at 
once  the  stronger  and  the  more  reticent.  James  Seth 
had  a  companionable  nature,  and  was  ever  eager  to 
pass  on  his  own  cherished  beliefs  and  enthusiasms  to 
younger  men.  Pringle-Pattison  expressed  his  deeper 
convictions  with  a  certain  hesitancy  ;  but  even  because 
of  this,  those  who  had  caught  anything  of  the  under 
tones  of  his  thinking  felt  his  moments  of  self-expression 
all  the  more  memorable. 

Hence  it  came  about  that  the  contrast  between 
Campbell  Eraser  and  Calderwood,  noted  in  Barrie's 
Edinburgh  Eleven  twenty  years  earlier,  was  repeated  in 
the  case  of  their  successors.  Each  had  his  own  enthusi 
astic  adherents.  As  in  the  earlier  time,  the  Moral 
Philosophy  Class  appealed  to  those  whose  philosophical 
interest  was  only  nascent  or  was  of  a  practical  type  ; 


96  MEMOIR 

for  Seth  had  an  unusual  power  of  reading  the  mind  and 
awakening  the  interest  of  the  beginner  in  philosophy, 
and  he  seldom  allowed  his  attitude  to  a  thinker  or  a 
problem  to  remain  in  doubt.  Pringle-Pattison,  while 
at  least  as  clear  in  exposition,  was  slow  to  pronounce 
final  judgments,  and  his  aim  was  rather  that  his  students 
should  themselves  seek  solutions  than  that  they  should 
accept  conclusions  because  he  held  them.  Hence  it 
was  a  commonplace  that  James  Seth  was  at  his  best 
in  the  Ordinary  Class,  while  Pringle-Pattison's  finest 
teaching  was  reserved  for  the  comparatively  small 
number  who  proceeded  to  Honours. 

In  one  respect  only  did  their  special  gifts  fail  to  find 
the  most  advantageous  exercise  ;  and  that  was  due, 
not  to  any  defect  in  either,  but  to  the  position  of  their 
respective  classes  in  the  normal  Arts  curriculum.  James 
Seth's  special  gift  was  that  of  initiating  the  new-comer 
into  philosophy,  while  Pringle-Pattison's  teaching — and 
perhaps  also  the  character  of  his  subject — called  for  a 
more  definite  philosophical  interest  and  a  more  sustained 
attention.  Yet  it  was  the  Logic  class  which  was  for 
long  the  larger,  and  which  the  majority  of  students 
took  first.  It  was  not  subject  to  the  waves  of  disorder 
which  sometimes  swept  over  other  large  classes  in  the 
Scottish  universities  of  the  day ;  yet  among  the  two 
hundred  men  and  women  who  composed  it,  there  were 
some  who  had  little  bent  for  philosophy,  and  who  at 
times  complained  of  the  lecturer's  pauses  as  he  arranged 
and  rearranged  the  large  sheets  of  manuscript  on  the 
desk  before  him.  But  a  much  larger  number  realised 
that  he  was  steadily  re-thinking,  as  he  lectured,  the 
ideas  towards  which  he  sought  to  lead  his  hearers,  and 
that  he  never  gave  less  than  his  best ;  while  there  were 
not  a  few  who  came  growingly  to  understand  the  range, 
the  fineness  and  the  balance  of  his  philosophical  outlook. 
He  did  not  use  the  Seminar  method  of  discussion,  which 


MEMOIR  97 

was  brought  from  America  and  successfully  practised 
by  his  brother  ;  but  in  a  different,  and  perhaps  a  subtler, 
way  he  made  his  abler  students  feel  that  they  were 
taken  into  a  true  partnership  in  the  quest  of  truth. 

It  was  not  his  way  to  make  the  initial  steps  too  easy, 
and  his  Ordinary  class  opened  with  a  month  of  Formal 
Logic,  which  he  believed  to  have  real  value  as  a  disci 
pline  in  exactness  of  thought.  Next  came  the  section 
of  the  course  on  Psychology.  Though  not  an  original 
worker  in  this  field,  he  knew  well  what  was  being  done 
by  others,  and  traced  its  outlines  with  his  usual  clarity 
of  phrase  and  illustration.  As  he  advanced  to  such 
topics  as  Association,  Memory  and  the  Concept,  and 
showed  how  they  were  treated  in  the  period  from 
Descartes  to  Hume,  he  led  up  to  the  transition  to  the 
Theory  of  Knowledge. 

The  last  two  months  of  the  winter  session  were  devoted 
to  a  masterly  introduction  to  the  History  of  Meta 
physics.  This  opened  with  a  discussion,  running  through 
three  or  four  lectures,  of  the  object  and  method  of 
philosophy.  It  was  differentiated,  he  held,  from  science 
as  dealing  with  the  whole  of  knowledge  and  providing 
a  "  criticism  of  categories/'  It  was  organic,  moving  as 
a  whole,  and  so  no  part  of  it  could  be  regarded  as  settled 
and  done  with.  The  course  of  speculative  thought  had 
made  it  clear  that  many  solutions  of  metaphysical 
problems,  once  accepted,  were  illusory,  since  their  con 
sequences  had  proved  untenable.  Yet  the  value  of  the 
historical  study  of  philosophy  was  not  merely  negative, 
for,  though  certain  main  types  of  thought  recurred  at 
different  epochs,  the  return  to  them  was  made  at  a  higher 
level.  From  this  introduction  Pringle-Pattison  passed 
on  to  a  clear  and  stimulating  survey  of  Greek  philosophy, 
and  then  after  a  rapid  glance  at  the  Hellenistic  and 
mediaeval  period,  to  a  treatment  of  modern  philosophy 
as  far  as  Hume.  In  the  Honours  class  he  built  on  this 

G 


98  MEMOIR 

foundation  an  exposition  of  Kant  and  post-Kantian 
idealism  and  of  Advanced  Logic,  with  special  reference 
to  the  work  of  Bradley  and  Bosanquet. 

Such  was  the  main  current  of  his  teaching  during  the 
first  fifteen  years  of  his  professorship  in  Edinburgh. 
There  were  minor  variations  from  year  to  year  ;  but  in 
1906  there  came  a  much  larger  change  with  the  institu 
tion  of  the  long-hoped-for  Lectureship  in  Psychology, 
of  which  the  late  Dr  W.  G.  Smith  was  the  first  holder. 
This  allowed  Pringle-Pattison  to  concentrate  on  the 
portions  of  his  wide  subject  in  which  he  was  most  at 
home,  and  it  also  reduced  his  Ordinary  class  to  a  more 
manageable  size  than  before.  There  followed  a  further 
change  by  which  professors  in  the  Arts  Faculty  began 
to  lecture  during  the  summer  session,  which  had  till 
then  taken  a  quite  subsidiary  place  in  the  Arts  curriculum. 
At  the  same  time  lectures  in  winter  were  reduced  from 
five  to  three  days  a  week.  This  rearrangement,  though 
desirable  on  many  grounds,  appeared  to  Pringle-Pattison 
as  a  somewhat  mixed  blessing  ;  since  he  had  always  felt 
at  home  in  the  older  Scots  system  of  a  long  summer 
vacation  for  study,  thinking  and  preparation,  in  view 
of  the  concentrated  activity  of  teaching  in  the  winter 
months. 

The  interpretation  of  Modern  Philosophy  which  he 
gave  to  his  students  may  be  gathered  in  detail  from 
his  books,  and  his  gifts  in  this  direction  were  well  known. 
Yet  his  power  of  interpreting  Greek  thought  was  not  less 
notable,  though  it  only  appeared  in  his  last  two  books, 
especially  in  the  chapter  entitled  "  Pre-existence  and 
Immortality  in  Plato/' l  The  ethical  passion  in  Plato, 
as  well  as  "  the  large  serenity  of  outlook  "  of  which 
Pringle-Pattison  there  spoke,  struck  responsive  chords 
in  his  own  mind.  But  intellectually  he  was  as  much  an 

1  The  Idea  of  Immortality,  Lecture  Hi.  ;  cf .  Studies  in  the  Philosophy 
of  Religion,  Ch.  vi.  and  vii. 


MEMOIR  99 

Aristotelian  as  a  Platonist,  for  he  had  a  profound  belief 
in  development,  while  the  study  of  history  in  its  widest 
sense  rather  than  reasoning  of  the  mathematical  order 
seemed  to  him  the  surest  path  to  philosophical  truth. 

One  memory  which  remains  clear  in  the  present  writer's 
mind,  as  he  looks  back  over  thirty  years,  is  that  of  the 
aptness  and  impressiveness  of  Pringle-Pattison's  quota 
tions,  although  in  his  Edinburgh  classes  he  naturally 
quoted  more  sparingly  from  the  poets  than  in  the 
lectures  on  Literature  of  his  St  Andrews  days.  One  such 
quotation  in  the  Honours  class  was  the  passage  from 
Lotze's  Mikrokosmos  on  the  trustworthiness  and  spiritual 
significance  of  knowledge  which  he  reproduced  in  his 
Gifford  Lectures.1  Another  well-remembered  quotation 
came  into  his  introductory  course.  He  had  reached 
the  "  incomplete  Socratics,"  and  pointed  out  that, 
opposite  as  the  theories  of  Cynic  and  Cyrenaic  appeared, 
they  had  a  certain  point  of  contact  in  an  attitude  to  the 
world  which  separated  both  from  the  uncriticised  views 
of  the  ordinary  practical  man.  Then  he  continued  in 
the  words  of  Pater :  "  The  saint,  and  the  Cyrenaic 
lover  of  beauty,  it  may  be  thought,  would  at  least  under 
stand  each  other  better  than  either  would  understand 
the  mere  man  of  the  world.  Carry  their  respective 
positions  a  point  further,  shift  the  terms  a  little,  and 
they  might  actually  touch. 

"  Perhaps  all  theories  of  practice  tend,  as  they  rise 
to  their  best,  as  understood  by  their  worthiest  repre 
sentatives,  to  identification  with  each  other.  For  the 
variety  of  men's  possible  reflections  on  their  experience, 
as  of  that  experience  itself,  is  not  really  so  great  as  it 
seems  ;  and  as  the  highest  and  most  disinterested  ethical 
formula,  filtering  down  into  men's  everyday  existence, 
reach  the  same  poor  level  of  vulgar  egotism,  so,  we  may 
fairly  suppose  that  all  the  highest  spirits,  from  whatever 

1  The  Idea  of  God,  p.  120  f. 


ioo  MEMOIR 

contrasted  points  they  have  started,  would  yet  be  found 
to  entertain,  in  the  moral  consciousness  realised  by 
themselves,  much  the  same  kind  of  mental  company."  l 

These  words  represented  a  deep  and  persistent  element 
in  Pringle-Pattison's  own  thinking.  There  was  in  it  a 
recurrent  sense  of  the  more  that  lies  beyond  and  above 
logical  formulation,  of  the  horizon  that  is  never  enclosed 
by  the  frame  of  the  picture.  If  only  this  surrounding 
territory,  as  yet  so  little  entered  upon,  could  be  patiently 
explored  by  thinkers  each  of  whom  sought  steadily  to 
appreciate  points  of  view  divergent  from  his  own,  the 
hope  of  a  large  measure  of  ultimate  agreement  indicated 
in  the  letter  quoted  from  Leslie  Stephen  (above,  p.  80  f.) 
might  at  last  be  realised. 

This  recollection  of  Pringle-Pattison's  teaching  is 
especially  associated  with  the  day,  or  days,  in  the 
Honours  class  when  he  touched  on  the  final  relation  of 
the  ethical  and  the  religious  experience — of  the  contrast 
between  the  Good  as  in  partial  and  painful  process  of 
achievement,  and  the  Good  as  already  achieved  and 
waiting  to  be  appropriated  by  the  finite  spirit.  Here 
his  teaching  had  much  in  common  with  that  of  F.  H. 
Bradley.2  He  attempted  no  formal  reconciliation  ;  but 
no  student  who  carefully  followed  his  thought  could  fail 
to  realise  how  real  and  essential  both  points  of  view 
were  to  himself,  and  how  fully  he  believed  that  they 
would  be  found  at  one  in  some  form  of  experience  wider 
in  its  span  than  ours,  and  were  indeed  implicitly  at  one 
in  the  highest  reaches  of  our  present  experience. 

Two  impressions  of  his  teaching  may  here  be  added 
which  were  placed  on  record  by  men  who  studied  under 

1  Marius  the  Epicurean,   Ch.   xvi.,   "  Second   Thoughts."     If   my 
memory  is  not  at  fault,  Pringle-Pattison  linked  with  this  Ch.  ix., 
"  New  Cyrenaicism." 

2  Cf.  the  concluding  chapter  of  Ethical  Studies,  especially  pp.  319, 
329  (2nd  ed.),  with  Seth's  early  statement  quoted  p.  32  above,  and 
with  The  Idea  of  God,  p.  396,  written  more  than  thirty  years  after. 


MEMOIR  101 

Pringle-Pattison,  one  at  the  beginning  and  the  other 
during  the  later  part  of  his  Edinburgh  professorship. 
Professor  H.  R.  Mackintosh,  writing  in  the  Scotsman  on 
the  day  after  his  death,  thus  described  his  Honours 
class  :  "  That  famous  higher  course,  some  of  us  readily 
own,  was  the  best  lecturing  we  have  ever  heard.  He 
spoke  conversationally,  at  times  with  a  hesitation  that 
added  piquancy  to  the  thing  said,  and  he  used  no  stale 
words.  His  method  was  to  develop  his  own  view  by 
way  of  exposition  and  criticism  of  the  greater  thinkers, 
the  criticism  being  of  that  higher  order  which  forces 
an  author  to  review  himself  in  the  light  of  his  own 
assumptions/' 

Professor  H.  F.  Hallett  has  thus  recorded  his  impres 
sion  of  Pringle-Pattison 's  teaching  at  a  later  time  :  "He 
possessed  in  the  highest  degree  the  power  of  going  straight 
to  the  heart  of  an  abstruse  problem.  There  was  never  a 
clearer-headed  university  professor,  yet  his  ability  was  not 
overwhelming  to  his  students.  The  slight  hesitancy  of 
his  manner,  the  complete  absence  of  the  learned  volubility 
that  often  conceals  '  learned  ignorance/  put  the  young 
student  at  ease  with  his  subject,  if  not  altogether  at 
ease  with  his  professor.  .  .  .  Further,  he  was  a  great 
teacher  of  philosophers  :  there  must  be  at  least  half  a 
dozen  professors  of  philosophy  at  present  in  the  univer 
sities  of  Great  Britain  alone  who  owe  their  first  initiation 
as  philosophers  to  Pringle-Pattison ;  but  I  should  say 
that  no  two  of  them  belong  to  the  same  school  of  thought. 
They  were  not  so  taught/' x  To  which  it  may  be  added 
that  his  pupils  have  held  chairs  of  philosophy  not  only 
in  Great  Britain,  but  in  India,  Canada,  Australia,  South 
Africa  and  the  United  States ;  and  that  many  of  those 
who  have  become  theological  teachers  have  shown  his 

1  Professor  Hallett  allows  me  to  quote,  here  and  later,  from  the 
appreciation  which  he  contributed  to  Mind,  N.S.,  No.  166  (April 
!933)>  PP-  137  ff- 


102  MEMOIR 

influence  hardly  less  than  the  philosophers.  Witness 
such  a  book  as  Professor  John  Baillie's  The  Interpretation 
of  Religion.1 

Before  we  leave  the  "  old  Logic  Classroom,"  there  is 
one  memory  which  students  of  the  years  before  1905  or 
thereabouts  will  readily  recall.  On  the  closing  day  of 
the  winter  session  Professor  Campbell  Fraser  used  to 
come  in  from  his  beautiful  home  at  Gorton,  between 
Hawthornden  and  Roslin,  to  present  the  medals  in  the 
Logic  class  and  to  wish  its  parting  members  well  as 
they  passed  on  to  another  stage  of  philosophy  or  of  life. 
He  and  Pringle-Pattison,  either  of  whom  might  have 
sat  for  the  portrait  of  the  ideal  philosopher,  were  more 
than  ordinarily  impressive  when  they  were  seen  together, 
the  one  with  snow-white,  the  other  with  silver,  hair  and 
flowing  beard.  If  there  was  more  of  command  in  the 
features  of  the  older  man,  the  younger  had  the  greater 
benignity. 

Both  before  and  after  graduation,  Pringle-Pattison's 
students  found  him,  as  they  found  his  brother,  ready  to 
take  endless  trouble  to  advise  regarding  lines  of  study 
or  research.  This  eagerness  to  help  and  unconsciousness 
of  the  dignity  of  his  own  office  found  an  outlet  in  a 
small  trait  which  many  will  remember  during  talks  in 
his  study.  When  a  book  was  mentioned,  instead  of 
merely  characterising  it  he  would  rise  from  his  chair, 
search  for  it  in  his  bookshelves  and  place  it  in  the  hands 
of  his  companion,  until  the  latter,  embarrassed  by  the 
mounting  pile  of  volumes  at  his  elbow  and  ashamed  to 
find  the  philosopher  thus  persistently  fetching  and  carry 
ing  for  a  quite  undistinguished  guest,  would  register  a  re 
solve  to  mention  no  more  books  for  that  evening  at  least. 

1  Dr  Baillie  now  holds  a  chair  in  Union  Theological  Seminary, 
New  York.  Cf.  also  an  appreciation  of  Pringle-Pattison's  life  and 
work  in  the  Australasian  Journal  of  Psychology  and  Philosophy  for 
December  1931,  by  Principal  E.  N.  Merrington  of  Knox  College, 
Dunedin,  who  was  a  post-graduate  student  of  philosophy  in  Edinburgh. 


MEMOIR  103 

Pringle-Pattison  the  man  has  been  portrayed  by 
Professor  Hallett  from  an  angle  all  the  more  significant 
that  it  would  not  so  readily  have  been  chosen  by  a 
compatriot :  "  Andrew  Seth  was  essentially  an  Edin 
burgh  man,  by  birth,  by  training,  by  residence  for  the 
greater  part  of  his  life,  and  it  may  also  be  said  by  tem 
perament  and  native  bias.  To  one  at  least  of  his  students, 
coming  to  the  Scottish  metropolis  from  over  the  Border, 
he  seemed  the  very  incarnation  of  the  spirit  of  Edinburgh. 
His  broad  and  easy  culture,  scholarly  reserve,  and  intel 
lectual  piety,  with  not  a  little  of  the  scepticism  of  mental 
attitude  and  distaste  for  enthusiasm  associated  with 
that  other  great  Edinburgh  philosopher  whose  monu 
ment  adorns  the  Calton  Hill,  found  an  ideal  setting  in  the 
austere  beauty  of  the  city  of  castle  and  college,  palace 
and  kirk/' 

University  administration  did  not  in  itself  appeal 
strongly  to  Pringle-Pattison's  temperament  or  interest, 
but,  in  this  sphere  as  in  others,  what  he  undertook  he 
carried  out  conscientiously  and  with  thoroughness.  Sir 
Richard  Lodge,  who  was  for  long  his  colleague  as  Pro 
fessor  of  History  and  Dean  of  the  Faculty  of  Arts,  has 
contributed  the  following  note  on  his  work  in  the  Senatus, 
and  also  for  several  years  in  the  University  Court : 
"  There  were  three  topics  in  which  he  took  special 
interest.  He  sought  to  maintain  for  the  philosophical 
subjects  their  time-honoured  place  in  the  Arts  curriculum. 
He  opposed,  with  what  seemed  to  me  curious  tenacity, 
all  encroachments  on  the  sanctity  of  the  vacations. 
And  he  was  a  consistent  champion  of  the  modern  lan 
guages  against  the  active  protagonist  on  the  other  side, 
Henry  Butcher.  This  was,  so  far  as  I  remember,  the 
only  matter  on  which  he  appeared  as  the  leader  of  a 
party.  His  usual  attitude  was  that  of  a  neutral  and 
rather  aloof  critic.  He  certainly  never  desired  or  claimed 
to  be  an  academic  reformer,  and  he  viewed  with  some 


104  MEMOIR 

distrust  the  excessive  loosening  of  the  curriculum. 
When  he  took  part  in  debate,  he  spoke  with  force  and 
dignity,  and  he  was  always  listened  to  with  respect." 

Regarding  the  revision  of  the  Arts  curriculum,  there 
are  many  who  now  hold  that  Pringle-Pattison's  attitude 
of  caution  was  justified,  and  that  at  this  period  its 
balance  and  its  cultural  value  were  jeopardised  by  the 
indefinite  extension  of  '  options/  many  of  which  were 
imperfectly  co-ordinated.  In  November  1908  he  wrote 
to  Professor  Alexander  :  "  We  are  kept  uncomfortably 
busy  here  working  out  the  arrangements  for  new  curricula 
under  the  far  more  elastic  conditions  of  our  new  Ordi 
nance.  Psychology,  now  in  the  hands  of  W.  G.  Smith, 
will  be  a  central  subject  for  the  teachers  who  constitute 
about  seven-tenths  of  our  total  numbers  in  Arts,  but  it 
has  yet  to  be  seen  how  the  almost  complete  freedom 
introduced  will  affect  the  study  of  philosophy  proper." 

During  the  years  covered  by  this  chapter  more  than 
one  additional  honour  came  to  Pringle-Pattison.  The 
degree  of  LL.D.,  which  St  Andrews  and  Princeton  had 
already  conferred,  was  followed  in  1902  by  that  of  D.C.L. 
from  the  University  of  Durham ;  and  two  years  later 
he  was  elected  a  Fellow  of  the  British  Academy. 

One  matter  in  which  Pringle-Pattison's  philosophical 
record  and  sound  judgment  inevitably  gave  him  a  leading 
voice  was  the  appointment  of  Gifford  Lecturers  in  the 
University.  In  the  years  covered  by  this  chapter  there 
were  four  courses  of  Gifford  Lectures  which  gave  him 
especial  satisfaction  :  those  by  William  James,  Laurie, 
Bosanquet  and  Bergson.  Of  these,  the  first  and  last 
involved  him  in  a  good  deal  of  work  and  responsibility. 
William  James*  appointment  was  made  about  two  years 
after  he  and  Seth  first  met  at  the  Princeton  celebrations 
in  1896.  But  in  the  end  of  1898  James  had  a  serious 
breakdown,  and  the  following  autumn,  when  he  was  in 
Europe  seeking  health,  a  grave  degree  of  heart  weakness 


MEMOIR  105 

showed  itself.  This  made  it  necessary  to  postpone  the 
Lectures  twice  ;  and  they  were  finally  delivered  in  the 
Summer  Terms  of  1901  and  1902,  though  even  in  the 
latter  year  the  great  psychologist  was  forced  to  lecture 
seated.  During  the  trying  period  of  uncertainty,  both 
Professor  and  Mrs  James  acknowledged  with  the  sin- 
cerest  gratitude  the  consideration  and  helpfulness  which 
their  friend  showed  in  arranging  for  these  postponements. 
In  October  1899  Mrs  James  wrote  from  Nauheim  :  "  You 
have  been  so  very  kind  that  I  find  myself  turning  grate 
fully  to  you  as  one  of  the  beneficent  influences  in  a  very 
hard  year.  A  wife's  judgment  of  her  husband's  work 
must  be  taken  sceptically,  but  I  hope  to  appeal  to  your 
own  a  few  months  hence  to  confirm  it,  for  William  has 
never  done  anything  better  than  these  lectures.  He 
has  grown  so  wise  in  all  these  weary  months  of  illness." 
Two  months  later  James  himself  wrote  :  "  I  am  applying 
for  a  second  year  of  furlough  from  Harvard,  and  between 
me  and  eternity  there  is  nothing  to  look  at  except 
Gifford  Lectures,  the  subject  of  which  fascinates  me 
more  and  more." 

When,  after  these  delays,  the  lectures  on  The  Varieties 
of  Religious  Experience  were  at  last  given  to  the  world, 
many  others  felt  the  fascination  of  the  subject ;  and 
not  least  Pringle-Pattison,  whose  range  of  sympathy 
was  wider  than  that  of  some  fellow  idealists.  He  had 
long  valued  and  used  freely  in  teaching  psychology 
William  James'  pioneer  work  in  that  field;  and  he 
welcomed  also  his  Gifford  Lectures  with  their  fresh  and 
stimulating  treatment  of  the  religious  life. 

An  attempt  was  made  with  the  co-operation  of  Dr 
Edward  Caird,  then  Master  of  Balliol,  to  secure  Mr  F.  H. 
Bradley  as  Edinburgh's  next  Gifford  Lecturer.  Mr 
Bradley 's  health  prevented  his  accepting  nomination  ; 
but  eight  or  nine  years  later  Dr  Bernard  Bosanquet 
accepted  the  appointment.  He  wrote  to  Pringle-Pattison 


io6  MEMOIR 

expressing  his  appreciation  of  the  fact  that  he  had 
been  nominated,  and  that  the  initiative  had  been  taken 
by  one  whose  views  had  often  diverged  from  his  own. 
In  spite  of  this  divergence  regarding  the  relation  of  finite 
personality  to  the  Absolute,  no  one  who  had  the  privilege 
of  seeing  them  together  at  this  time  could  fail  to  realise 
that  they  were  men  of  essentially  kindred  spirit .  Between 
them  controversy  left  no  bitterness. 

Following  Dr  Bosanquet's  tenure  of  the  Gifford 
Lectureship  came  the  appointment  which  caused  wider 
interest — one  might  truthfully  say,  excitement — than 
any  other,  that  of  M.  Bergson.  His  name  was  then  on 
all  lips,  and  his  views  were  being  expounded  in  all 
degrees  of  dilution  in  popular  no  less  than  scientific  and 
philosophical  journals.  The  invitation  to  deliver  the 
Gifford  Lectures  was  sent  towards  the  end  of  1911  ;  and 
M.  Bergson  wrote  at  once  to  the  Secretary  of  the  Univer 
sity,  Sir  Ludovic  Grant,  accepting  the  appointment,  and 
at  the  same  time  expressed  to  Pringle-Pattison  the 
pleasure  which  he  felt  in  the  prospect  of  meeting  one 
whose  works  he  had  known  for  long. 

Although  M.  Bergson  was  a  brilliant  linguist  as  well 
as  thinker,  there  were  questions  of  some  difficulty  to 
determine  regarding  the  language  in  which  the  lectures 
were  to  be  given.  The  first  suggestion  from  the  side  of 
the  University  was  that  the  majority  should  be  in 
English ;  but  this  raised  a  difficulty  for  M.  Bergson, 
whose  method  it  was  to  lecture  ex  tempore  and  after 
wards  write  what  he  had  spoken.  Finally,  it  was 
decided  that  the  lectures  should  be  in  French — save  two, 
which  were  read  by  the  lecturer  in  English.  In  these 
and  other  arrangements  Pringle-Pattison  took  an  active 
and  characteristically  helpful  part. 

In  the  summer  of  1913  he  and  his  wife  and  children 
visited  the  Rhine  and  Switzerland.  For  a  time  they 
were  a  united  party,  and  after  two  of  the  elder  children 


MEMOIR  107 

had  to  return  home,  the  others  went  on  to  the  Oberland, 
Zermatt  and  Chamonix.  When  on  his  way  home, 
Pringle-Pattison  had  the  interest  of  spending  an  evening 
in  M.  Bergson's  home  at  Auteuil.  Six  months  later 
M.  Bergson  reached  Edinburgh.  He  had  been  asked  to 
send  in  advance  a  synopsis  of  his  earlier  lectures  to  be 
translated  and  issued  at  the  opening  of  the  course  ;  and 
when  the  proof  reached  him  he  wrote  to  Pringle-Pattison  : 
"  II  est  si  parfaitement  traduit  oue  je  vous  soup£onne 
d'etre  1'auteur  de  la  traduction.  Je  serais  vraiment 
confus  de  vous  avoir  donne  cette  peine." 

The  course  was  delivered  in  the  Natural  History 
Classroom,  the  largest  in  the  University,  and  was  closely 
followed  by  the  most  varied  as  well  as  the  largest  audience 
which  had  ever  assembled  to  hear  a  series  of  philosophical 
lectures  in  Edinburgh.  The  subject  was  "  The  Problem 
of  Personality/'  and  not  only  the  material  of  the  lectures 
but  the  personality  of  the  lecturer  made  a  strong  appeal 
—the  spare  figure,  intellectual  face  with  eyes  of  unusual 
brilliance,  animation  of  manner,  lightness  of  touch,  all 
combined  with  the  marvellously  clear  French  style  to 
form  a  unique  impression.  On  one  occasion  M.  Bergson 
dined  with  Lord  Haldane  and  others  at  16  Churchhill ; 
and  on  another  he  agreed  to  meet  the  members  of  the 
University  Philosophical  Society  in  an  informal  discus 
sion  at  the  house  of  James  Seth — a  discussion  of  which 
Pringle-Pattison  left  a  short  record.1  From  every  point 
of  view  M.  Bergson's  visit  was  a  memorable  one  for 
those  interested  in  philosophy  in  Edinburgh ;  and  a 
somewhat  melancholy  interest  now  attaches  to  a  letter 
dated  from  the  University  Club  on  May  16,  in  which  he 
thanked  Pringle-Pattison  and  his  wife  for  their  friendly 
welcome,  and  provisionally  fixed  May  10,  1915,  for  the 
first  lecture  of  the  second  course.  In  this  M.  Bergson 
had  promised  to  pass  on  from  psychology,  to  which  his 
1  The  Idea  of  God,  p.  380  n. 


io8  MEMOIR 

contribution  was  well  known,  and  to  break  new  ground 
in  the  application  of  his  leading  ideas  to  the  central 
problems  of  ethics  and  religion.  But  the  strain  of  the 
war,  during  which  he  undertook  much  heavy  work  at 
the  instance  of  the  French  Government,  left  his  health 
so  impaired  that  the  first  course  was  never  published  nor 
the  second  delivered. 

This  account  of  the  sixteen  years  before  1914  may 
draw  to  a  close  with  some  account  of  Pringle-Pattison' s 
continued  friendship  with  three  men  whose  names  have 
been  often  before  us — Professor  Campbell  Fraser, 
Mr  Balfour  and  Lord  Haldane.  In  September  1899, 
when  Professor  Campbell  Fraser  reached  his  eightieth 
birthday,  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  :  "  It  is  given  to  few 
to  look  back  in  the  unimpaired  vigour  of  all  their  powers 
upon  eighty  years  of  a  life  so  full  of  honour  and  useful 
ness  as  yours  has  been.  Health  and  happiness  have  also 
been  yours.  Deep  delight  in  nature,  unfailing  interest 
in  history  and  in  the  general  movement  of  the  world 
have  contributed  to  make  life  rich  and  full.  I  have 
often  thought  within  the  last  ten  years  that,  besides 
what  we  owe  to  your  philosophical  teaching,  you  give 
in  your  own  person  a  notable  example  of -how  good  a 
thing  human  life  can  be  or  can  be  made."  The  reply 
contained  these  words  :  "I  am  too  conscious  that  the 
ideal  which  your  words  suggest  has  not  been  realised 
by  me,  but  the  fact  that  you  suppose  this  must  make 
me  more  earnest  in  the  endeavour  to  realise  it  during 
the  days  which  may  remain  for  me  in  this  passing 
world." 

Seven  years  later  it  fell  to  Pringle-Pattison  to  organise 
a  meeting  in  celebration  of  the  jubilee  of  Campbell 
Fraser's  appointment  as  successor  to  Sir  William  Hamil 
ton  ;  and  three  years  later  still  he  joined  with  Lord 
Rosebery,  Mr  Balfour  and  many  of  the  old  philosopher's 


MEMOIR  109 

former  students  in  an  address  of  congratulation  on  his 
ninetieth  birthday.  To  this  Campbell  Fraser  replied  in 
a  letter  which  ended  : — 

"  To  me  the  retrospect  awakens  a  deep  sense  of  work 
left  undone  which  ought  to  have  been  done — oppor 
tunities  lost  which  God  has  given  to  me. — With  grateful 
regard  to  all  my  too  indulgent  friends,  Ever  affectionately 
yours,  A.  CAMPBELL  FRASER." 

One  more  letter  reached  Pringle-Pattison  in  the  autumn 
of  1910,  in  which  Campbell  Fraser  said  :  "  I  have  been 
confined  to  bed  for  the  last  few  days,  but  am  now 
emerging.  This  is  due,  they  say,  to  a  week  of  (for  me) 
pretty  heavy  work  in  revising  my  '  Selections  from 
Berkeley '  for  a  sixth  edition  at  the  urgent  request  of  the 
Clarendon  Press."  Regarding  this,  the  last  philosophical 
task  of  his  long  life,  which  ended  four  years  later, 
Professor  James  Seth  told  the  writer  that,  having  gone 
over  the  proof-sheets  at  Professor  Campbell  Fraser 's 
request,  he  found  that  all  the  alterations  made  by  the 
unwearied  old  man  gave  added  clarity  and  point  to  what 
he  had  written  long  before. 

In  January  1899  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  to  Mr  Balfour  : 
"  I  have  just  been  reading  Wilfrid  Ward's  paper  for  the 
next  meeting  of  the  Synthetic.  .  .  .  The  paper  is  very 
nicely  worked  out  till  the  Church  (for  which  we  have  all 
been  waiting)  suddenly  steps  out  on  the  last  page.  I 
fear  the  analogy  between  scientific  authority  and 
authority  in  religion  will  not  hold.  We  accept  scientific 
authority  simply  to  save  ourselves  the  trouble  of  verify 
ing  the  conclusions  for  ourselves — or  the  trouble  of 
educating  ourselves  till  we  are  able  to  test  it  all.  This 
is  purely  provisional  and  a  matter  of  personal  con 
venience.  Whereas  the  religious  authority  is  supposed 
to  deal  with  matters  which  reason  is  incompetent  to 


no  MEMOIR 

settle,  and  accordingly  puts  forward  claims  to  permanent 
submission.  Again,  so  far  as  a  '  revelation  '  is  a  revela 
tion  of  spiritual  truth,  I  do  not  see  that  it  needs  any 
authority  behind  it.  Its  authority  lies  in  its  own  content. 
It  appeals  to  the  spiritual  nature  of  man,  and  the  response 
it  evokes  is  its  verification.  Spiritual  truth  is  judged  by 
the  spiritual  nature  of  man  just  as  intellectual  truth  by 
his  intellectual  nature,  and  neither  in  the  one  case  nor 
in  the  other  is  there  ultimately  a  place  for  external 
revelation  or  external  authority.  The  only  Church 
Catholic  is — 

The  human  soul  of  universal  earth 
Dreaming  on  things  to  come." 

Two  years  later  Mr  Balfour  told  Pringle-Pattison  that 
he  had  in  mind  to  write  a  new  preface  to  the  cheap 
edition  of  The  Foundations  of  Belief,  which  appeared 
that  year,  and  added  :  "I  hope  you  will  allow  me  to 
send  you  a  copy  of  this  in  proof.  Now  that  Henry 
Sidgwick  is  gone,  you  are  the  only  philosopher  to  whom 
I  should  care  to  show  it."  A  few  months  later  he  wrote 
again :  "  There  is  no  man  living  whose  opinion  in 
matters  philosophical  I  rate  so  high  as  yours,  or  whose 
spirit  in  dealing  with  them  I  more  admire." 

On  August  29,  1904,  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  from  The 
Haining  to  thank  Mr  Balfour  for  a  copy  of  his  Presi 
dential  Address  to  the  British  Association  :  "I  think 
I  may  claim  to  be  an  exception  to  the  indifferent  world 
of  whom  you  speak  on  p.  20,  for  the  idealistic  and 
teleological  argument  which  you  suggest  in  the  con 
cluding  pages  seemed  to  me  in  The  Foundations  of  Belief 
a  constructive  position  of  the  most  important  kind.  But 
I  am  afraid  it  is  the  force  with  which  you  develop  the 
sceptical  implications  of  natural  selection  and  the  rest 
of  the  evolutionary  creed  that  obscures  in  the  mind  of 


MEMOIR  in 

most  readers  the  constructive  sequel — which  so  many 
critics  of  your  book  insisted  on  taking  as  an  inconsequent 
afterthought  rather  than  an  integral  part  of  the  total 
argument." 

In  November  1902  R.  B.  Haldane  wrote  to  Pringle- 
Pattison  regarding  the  second  edition  of  Man's  Place  in 
the  Cosmos,  and  especially  the  essay  on  Bradley 's  Appear 
ance  and  Reality,  which  was  there  reprinted  :  "  I  felt 
myself  away  from  Hegelianism  and  Personality,  but 
very  close  to  your  conclusions  here.  I  think  it  is  the 
most  powerful  thing  you  have  written,  and  one  of  the 
best  essays  on  the  speculative  standpoint,  in  any  lan 
guage,  of  our  time.  I  wish  you  could  find  time  to  write 
a  book,  not  on  Hegel,  but  on  Hegelianism,  in  detail. 
No  one  alive  could  do  the  work  as  you  could.  I  refer 
specially  to  the  limits  of  the  doctrine  of  Degrees  of 
Reality — the  key,  to  my  mind,  of  the  whole  matter. 

"  I  am  glad  that  you  have  quoted  Das  Gottliche  in  the 
beginning.  It  embodies  a  power  of  wisdom." 

A  few  weeks  later  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  regarding 
the  first  series  of  Haldane 's  Gifford  Lectures  in  St 
Andrews,  entitled  The  Pathway  to  Reality  :— 

"  I  must  not  delay  any  longer  sending  you  a  few  lines 
of  thanks  for  your  Gifford  Lectures,  not  only  for  the 
gift  of  the  volume,  but  for  the  contents.  Of  the  sound 
ness  and  importance  of  the  doctrine  you  know  already 
that  I  am  well  convinced,  but  I  am  greatly  charmed 
with  your  manner  of  presenting  it.  There  is  a  personal 
flavour  all  through  the  book  which  gives  it  a  character 
of  its  own.  This,  I  think,  will  be  generally  felt,  but  to 
me  there  is  the  added  flavour  of  reminiscence  wafted 
from  its  pages  every  now  and  then.  I  think  you  have 
been  most  happily  inspired,  and  I  hope  you  will  follow 
the  same  method  of  large  free  utterance  in  your  second 
course.  .  .  . 

"  What  distressing  news  this  is  of  Ritchie's  death.    By 


H2  MEMOIR 

a  strange  coincidence  it  is  the  very  week,  and  day  of  the 
week,  when  Adamson  died  with  almost  equal  sudden 
ness  last  year/' 

Both  at  this  time  and  a  year  later,  when  the  second 
volume  of  The  Pathway  to  Reality  appeared,  Pringle- 
Pattison  reviewed  his  friend's  work  in  the  Times  ;  and 
on  the  latter  occasion  Haldane  wrote  :  "  With  the 
hand  of  a  master  you  have  set  out  the  very  pith  and 
kernel  of  these  Gifford  Lectures  in  to-day's  Times.  I 
am  more  grateful  to  you  than  I  can  easily  say,  for  what 
I  wanted  most  badly  was  to  get  before  busy  people  the 
real  point  of  what  we  have  to  say  in  common  to  them. 
There  it  is  in  two  columns — as  I  could  not  have  done  it 
myself."  During  the  same  month  (April  1904)  Pringle- 
Pattison  received  the  following,  and  pencilled  on  it, 
"  Note  this  letter  "  :- 

'  Your  letter  gave  me  very  great  pleasure.  For  there 
is  no  one  whose  judgment  I  set  alongside  of  yours,  and 
we  have  worked  side  by  side,  so  to  speak,  at  these  prob 
lems,  and  are  now  near  the  same  result.  Like  you,  I 
would  not  foreclose  the  personal  continuance,  simply 
because  to  do  so  is  to  set  up  the  other  side  of  the  antinomy. 
Despite  his  faulty  scheme,  Kant  was  not  far  from  the 
root  of  the  matter  when  he  sought  to  call  in  an  Intelligible 
World  to  redress  the  balance  of  this  empirical  world. 
But  as  you  say,  there  are  '  substantial  interests  which 
yield  a  present  satisfaction/  and  so  give  us  the  same 
thing  in  another  form. 

"  I  think  there  is  large  region,  pretty  well  untrodden, 
to  be  investigated.  It  has  to  be  shown  in  detail  how 
the  ends  which  shape  the  modes  of  thinking  in  spirit, 
which  though  free  is  finite,  determine  the  aspects  of  the 
world.  Something  towards  this  has  been  done  in  the 
sphere  of  Logic  by  Bradley  and  Bosanquet.  But  I  feel 
that  they  have  only  got  to  the  verge  of  the  ground.  I 


MEMOIR  113 

know  no  one  else  who  could  do  the  hard  thinking  the 
work  requires  as  }~ou  could,  and  I  hope  you  will.  I 
doubt  whether  there  is  very  much  more  to  be  extracted 
from  Hegel.  We  want  more  systematic  treatment  of 
detail.  However,  I  think  I  shall  read  over  again  the 
Phcenomenologie,  starting  from  this  basis :  '  Taking 
myself  as  just  the  realisation  of  this  particular  purpose, 
a  meaning  of  Absolute  Mind,  how  do  I  work  out  beyond 
it?  ' 

"  I  hope  we  may  manage  to  have  a  long  talk  before  a 
great  interval  has  passed.  With  much  gratitude,  Yours 
ever,  R.  B.  HALDANE." 

In  their  political  as  well  as  philosophical  views  the 
two  men  had  drawn  nearer.  In  the  years  after  1906 
the  Irish  question  was  for  a  time  in  abeyance,  and 
Pringle-Pattison  was  in  full  sympathy  with  the  social 
policy  of  the  Cabinet  of  which  his  friend  was  a  member. 
When  he  wrote  to  congratulate  Haldane  on  his  renewed 
return  for  East  Lothian  in  January  1910,  the  latter 
replied  :  '  The  old  and  great  Parliament  is  gone,  and 
the  task  in  this  new  one  is  a  task  which  will  be  very 
difficult  indeed.  It  is  to  me  a  very  great  satisfaction  to 
feel  that  you  are  so  keenly  with  us — I  feel  it  like  a  moral 
judgment  in  our  favour." 

On  February  3, 1913,  six  months  before  Lord  Haldane's 
'  lightning  visit '  to  Montreal  to  address  the  American 
and  Canadian  Bar  Associations,  Pringle-Pattison  wrote : — 

"  MY  DEAR  HALDANE, — Many  thanks  for  remembering, 
in  the  midst  of  all  you  have  to  do,  to  send  me  your 
Bristol  address.  It  is  extraordinarily  wise  and  sane, 
and  there  is  a  serenity  of  optimism  about  it  which  is 
very  comforting  because  one  feels  it  comes  from  breadth 
of  view  and  is  born  not  of  indolence  but  of  a  spirit  girt 
up  for  strenuous  endeavour.  I  feel  too  that  the  civic 

H 


114  MEMOIR 

university  is  one  of  the  most  encouraging  features  of 
our  time,  and  that  we  in  the  Scotch  Universities  have  to 
learn  from  the  spirit  of  these  newer  institutions. 

"I  see  your  visit  to  Canada  is  now  publicly  an 
nounced.  If  anything  comes  in  my  way  which  might 
be  of  use  in  your  address,  I  will  not  fail  to  report  it. — 
Yours  always,  A.  S.  PRINGLE-PATTISON." 


CHAPTER   IX. 

GIFFORD   LECTURES   ON   THEISM. 

1912-1917. 

FOR  twelve  years  after  Pringle-Pattison's  succession  to 
The  Haining  he  wrote  comparatively  little.  As  years 
went  on  his  eyesight  troubled  him  more,  and  at  times  of 
pressure  his  younger  daughter  used  to  read  examination 
papers  aloud  to  relieve  the  strain  on  his  eyes.  The  long 
summer  vacation,  formerly  free  for  original  work,  was 
now  largely  taken  up  by  other  and  hardly  less  absorbing 
duties.  But  in  1907  a  volume  entitled  The  Philosophical 
Radicals  appeared.  Along  with  reprints  of  earlier 
writings  it  contained  articles  based  on  Leslie  Stephen's 
English  Utilitarians,  Benjamin  Kidd's  Western  Civilisa 
tion,  Herbert  Spencer's  Autobiography  and  the  Life  of 
James  Martineau.  The  first  two  essays  showed  with 
how  firm  a  step  the  author  moved  in  the  field  of  social 
ethics  ;  and  the  essay  on  Martineau  drew  forth  a  letter 
of  warm  appreciation  from  a  distinguished  thinker  with 
whom  he  had  much  in  common,  M.  Emile  Boutroux. 
One  sentence  may  be  quoted  here,  since  a  French 
appreciation  of  style  has  a  quite  distinctive  value : 
"  D'un  bout  a  1'autre  la  clarte,  la  nettete,  la  precision 
scientifique  de  votre  exposition  rendent  la  lecture  aussi 
attachante  que  fructueuse."  Along  with  numerous 
reviews,  and  the  introduction  to  the  volume  of  Carlyle's 


n6  MEMOIR 

essays  referred  to  in  the  first  chapter  of  this  Memoir, 
The  Philosophical  Radicals  represents  the  literary  harvest 
of  the  decade  ending  in  1910. 

During  these  years  Pringle-Pattison's  pupils  and 
friends  continued  to  hope  for  a  philosophical  work  on  a 
larger  scale  than  he  had  yet  attempted ;  and  various 
friends,  including  Balfour  and  Haldane,  urged  him  to 
set  his  hand  to  the  task.  But,  as  in  the  case  of  other 
noted  thinkers,  including  the  two  philosopher-statesmen 
themselves,  it  was  his  appointment  as  Gifford  Lecturer 
which  caused  the  final  crystallisation  of  ideas  long 
present  to  his  mind  and  previously  expressed  in  less 
systematic  form.  When  Mr  Balfour  heard  of  his  friend's 
appointment  to  lecture  in  the  University  of  Aberdeen, 
he  wrote  :  "I  have  long  wished  to  see  you  Gifford 
Lecturer ;  and  am  delighted  to  hear  that  the  obstacles 
which  at  one  time  rendered  your  appointment  difficult 
have  been  swept  away.  After  all,  you  are  the  man  in  all 
Britain  most  qualified  for  the  post/* 

During  the  two  years  which  elapsed  between  the 
appointment  in  April  1910  and  the  delivery  of  the  first 
course  in  the  Summer  Term  of  1912,  Pringle-Pattison 
worked  hard  at  the  Lectures.  It  was  fortunate  that  he 
had  by  this  time  withdrawn  from  the  University  Court, 
and  that  the  changes  indicated  in  the  last  chapter  had 
somewhat  reduced  the  work  of  his  chair ;  yet  one  so 
conscientious  as  he  could  not  treat  its  duties  lightly, 
even  for  a  time,  and  his  family  were  conscious  that  he 
was  living  under  a  heavy  strain. 

But  if  the  preparation  of  the  Lectures  was  arduous, 
the  warm  welcome  which  he  received  in  Aberdeen  made 
their  delivery  pleasant.  He  was  glad  to  renew  an  old 
friendship  of  school  and  college  days  with  Principal 
Sir  George  Adam  Smith ;  and  they  shared  a  memory 
even  older  than  that  of  the  Royal  High  School.  Nearly 
fifty  years  before  the  Gifford  Lecturer  went  to  Aberdeen, 


MEMOIR  117 

four  small  boys,  George  and  Dunlop  Smith,  Andrew 
and  James  Seth,  sat  near  to  one  another  on  Sundays 
in  the  New  North  Church  in  Edinburgh,1  and  the  Smiths, 
who  suffered  from  an  excess  of  animal  spirits  which 
made  sitting  still  in  church  doubly  difficult,  looked  on 
the  Seths  as  almost  too  well-behaved  for  an  imperfect 
world.  Sir  George  Adam  Smith  had  left  his  chair  of 
Old  Testament  Language  and  Literature  in  Glasgow 
three  years  before  Pringle-Pattison  gave  his  first  course  ; 
and  he  afterwards  told  a  friend  how  great  a  refreshment 
of  spirit  it  had  been  to  escape  for  a  time  from  the  details 
of  university  business  into  the  atmosphere  of  strenuous 
thinking  and  high  idealism  which  pervaded  these  Lectures. 

Pringle-Pattison's  judgment  of  his  own  work  was 
always  stringent,  not  less  as  regards  form  than  matter  ; 
and  the  Lectures  were  not  only  revised  but  in  parts 
recast  before  publication.  This  process  occupied  many 
months,  and  was  extended  by  the  preoccupations  and 
anxieties  of  the  war.  In  June  1916  the  manuscript  was 
finally  in  the  hands  of  the  Oxford  University  Press.  In 
the  interval,  on  November  28,  1915,  Pringle-Pattison 
wrote  to  Lord  Haldane  :— 

"  I  have  read  your  paper  with  the  greatest  interest. 
You  have  swept  a  great  deal  into  your  net  besides  the 
New  Realism,  and  the  discussion  seems  to  me  throughout 
most  valuable.  What  you  say  about  Bergson  exactly 
represents  my  own  feeling  :  any  amount  of  stimulus, 
but  impossible  to  put  the  system  together,  and  useless 
to  appeal  to  intuition  unless  one  takes  intuition  as 
equivalent  to  the  larger  reason. 

"  I  agree  also  that  Idealism  must  be  broadened  suffi 
ciently  to  include  within  itself  what  is  sound  in  the 
Realist  contention,  and  as  you  say,  Bosanquet  has 
stated  the  case  about  as  well  as  it  can  be  stated  in  his 

1  The  second  in  the  quartette  was  the  late  Sir  James  Dunlop  Smith, 
K. C.S.I.,  a  distinguished  soldier  and  administrator  in  India. 


n8  MEMOIR 

criticism  of  Alexander.  I  think  the  Realists  are  right 
as  against  '  the  Berkeleian  fallacy/  or  what  they  call 
'the  ego -centric  predicament/  And  their  argument 
applies  to  Green  no  less  than  to  Berkeley.  In  both 
cases  I  think  we  only  arrive  at  a  formal  Ego,  and  really 
nothing  is  gained  by  such  a  point  of  subjectivity.  But 
however  much  of  a  Realist  one  may  be  epistemologic- 
ally,  when  it  is  a  question  of  the  individual  knower,  I 
still  hold,  ultimately  or  metaphysically,  to  what  you 
call  '  the  over-reaching  subject-object  relationship/  It 
is,  as  you  say,  simply  impossible  to  take  the  relation  of 
compresence  in  time  and  space  as  final. 

"  I  have  tried  in  one  of  my  Gifford  Lectures  x  to  dis 
engage  Idealism  from  Mentalism,  but  I  fancy  I  shall 
have  to  add  a  further  note  in  the  present  state  of  the 
controversy/' 

The  Preface  to  the  volume  was  dated  December  20, 
1916,  and  a  few  weeks  later  it  appeared  with  the  full 
title,  The  Idea  of  God  in  the  Light  of  Recent  Philosophy. 
The  last  words  indicated  that,  as  he  explicitly  stated  in 
the  Preface,  the  author  linked  his  own  thought  closely 
with  the  current  thought  of  his  time,  and  followed,  as 
he  had  always  done,  the  method  of  "  construction  through 
criticism/'  He  added  :  "  I  do  not  claim  that  it  is  the 
best  method ;  I  simply  desire  that  its  nature  be  recog 
nised/'  In  expressing  his  thanks  to  the  Senatus  of  the 
University  of  Aberdeen  for  his  appointment  to  the 
Lectureship,  he  said  :  "It  has  enabled  me  to  bring 
together  the  reflections  of  many  years,  and  I  have 
striven,  in  return,  to  give  them  of  my  best." 

Even  amid  the  stress  of  the  third  year  of  war — perhaps, 
in  the  case  of  some  readers,  all  the  more  because  of  this 
stress — the  book  received  an  immediate  welcome.  It 
was  widely  recognised  that  the  writer  had  indeed  "  given 
of  his  best."  His  own  feeling  in  regard  to  it  was  ex- 
1  Lecture  X.  :  The  Idea  of  God,  pp*  190  if. 


MEMOIR  119 

pressed  in  a  letter  to  Professor  A.  M.  Stalker  on  April  29, 
1917  :— 

"  I  just  want  to  acknowledge  the  pleasure  your  letter 
gave  me.  It  was  no  small  achievement  to  read  a  set  of 
Gifford  Lectures  through  in  these  days,  and  therefore 
also  no  small  compliment.  I  am  so  glad  you  felt  them 
'  human  '  throughout,  for  indeed  I  put  a  good  deal  of 
myself  into  them  at  places  and  I  wanted  to  state  results 
broadly. 

"It  is  a  satisfaction  to  me  to  have  brought  things 
together  to  the  extent  I  have  done,  and  I  am  content 
to  leave  the  matter  so.  I  get  some  spontaneous  letters 
which  gratify  me,  but  the  press  notices  so  far,  though 
generally  complimentary  enough,  have  been  disappoint 
ing — i.e.,  they  would  be  disappointing,  if  one  attached 
much  importance  to  them/' 

Two  months  later  he  wrote  to  Professor  J.  H.  Muir- 
head,  a  brother  of  the  companion  of  his  student  days  in 
Germany  : — 

"  It  was  a  great  pleasure  to  me,  and  a  sincere  satis 
faction,  to  receive  your  spontaneous  letter  about  my 
book.  After  taking  pains  with  a  book  there  is  a  certain 
hunger  in  an  author  to  know  what  appeal  it  makes  to 
other  minds,  and  that  hunger  is  ill  fed  by  perfunctory 
reviews  in  the  daily  and  weekly  press.  So  it  was  a  good 
deed  to  write  as  you  did. 

"  You  praise  the  volume  too  generously,  but  I  am 
so  glad  to  find  you  approve  of  the  method  I  have  fol 
lowed  and  that  you  are  in  agreement  with  my  main 
contentions.  From  some  of  your  recent  writing  I  felt 
confident  you  would  be,  as  you  say,  in  sympathy  with 
the  criticism  of  Bosanquet's  treatment  of  self-hood, 
which  is,  in  a  way,  the  centre  of  my  second  series  of 
lectures.  Bosanquet  appears  to  me  at  times  to  suffer 
from  a  negative  bias,  or  at  least  a  negative  form  of 
expression,  due,  I  think,  partly  to  revulsion  from  an 


120  MEMOIR 

orthodoxy  thrust  upon  him  in  his  youth.  I  certainly 
think  it  is  important  to  present  Idealism  in  a  more 
human-hearted  fashion,  and  you  encourage  me  to  think 
I  have  now  succeeded  in  doing  so  without  relapsing  into 
a  pluralism  of  '  impervious  '  individuals/' 

To  Lord  Haldane  he  wrote  in  March  1917  :  "  I  am 
greatly  cheered  to  know  that  you  feel  yourself  so  much 
in  sympathy  with  my  book  and  its  conclusions.  You 
would  recognise,  I  daresay,  in  some  of  the  last  pages  of 
all,  the  echo  of  some  of  our  conversations  at  Cloan  in 
the  early  days  of  1915 — the  passage  from  Hegel,  the 
reference  to  Faust,  &c."  Six  months  later  he  wrote 
further  :  '  That  you  should  go  back  to  my  book  so 
often  and  not  be  disappointed  is  indeed  high  praise,  and 
I  value  it  accordingly — though  I  am  well  aware  that 
you  must  often  piece  out  my  presentation  from  your 
own  store,  and,  of  course,  no  one  knows  so  well  as  an 
author  the  lacunce  in  his  own  treatment.  Still  you 
greatly  encourage  me,  and  I  am  grateful  for  your  good 
offices  in  bringing  the  book  to  the  notice  of  eminent 
persons.  The  Archibshop's  letter  (and  what  you  report 
of  him)  is  most  interesting,  and  I  am  glad  to  be  allowed 
to  keep  it.1 

"  I  am  glad  to  infer  from  the  Archbishop's  letter  that 
your  '  dear  and  honoured  mother/  as  he  most  truly 
calls  her,  is  still  enjoying  her  beautiful  old  age.  Please 
— as  opportunity  offers — remember  me  to  her  warmly 
and  reverentially/' 

While  it  is  needless,  and  would  perhaps  be  inappro 
priate,  to  attempt  either  a  summary  or  an  estimate 
here  of  this  book,  which  contains  Pringle-Pattison's 
fullest  treatment  of  those  problems  of  epistemology  and 
ontology  which  had  occupied  him  for  forty  years,  it 
may  be  well  to  indicate  how  his  thought  had  moved  in 

1  The  Archbishop  of  Canterbury  (Dr  Randall  Davidson)  had  been 
with  Lord  Haldane  at  Cloan  a  few  days  before. 


MEMOIR  121 

the  later  portion  of  that  time.  Those  passages,  especially 
Lectures  VI.  and  VIII. ,  in  which  he  returns  after  a  long 
interval  to  the  Theory  of  Knowledge,  show  that  he 
remained  firmly  convinced  of  the  truth  which  he  had 
all  along  emphasised,  that  knowledge  is  not  something 
interposed  between  the  mind  and  reality,  nor  does  it 
inevitably  distort  that  which  it  professes  to  transmit. 
Just  as  he  denied  in  his  first  lecture  at  Princeton  that 
the  "  knowing  subject  stands  outside  the  real  universe 
altogether,"  or  "  comes  to  inspect  it  from  afar  with 
mental  spectacles  of  a  foreign  make,"  so  he  now  denies 
that  Mind  is  "  condemned  to  circle  round  the  circum 
ference  of  the  real  world,  put  off  with  outside  shows, 
and  unable  to  penetrate  to  its  essential  core  "  (p.  132). 
The  letter  to  Lord  Haldane,  written  in  1915  and  already 
quoted,  shows  in  what  sense  he  had  been,  and  still 
remained,  a  Realist.1 

But  in  regard  to  the  great  ontological  problems, 
especially  that  of  the  relation  of  the  man's  finite  person 
ality  to  the  Whole  in  which  it  is  set,  there  was  certainly 
a  change  between  his  attitude  in  Hegelianism  and  Person 
ality  or  even  the  Two  Lectures  on  Theism  and  his  treat 
ment  of  the  same  issues  in  The  Idea  of  God.  It  was  a 
change  of  emphasis,  not  of  fundamental  principle  ;  but 
it  was  sufficiently  real  to  bring  him  back  into  contact 
with  those  early  fellow-workers  in  the  Hegelian  move 
ment  who  still  survived.  Nor  can  one  feel  sure  that,  if 
William  James  had  lived  to  read  the  Gifford  Lectures, 
he  would  have  said,  as  he  said  to  Dr  Merrington  :  "  I 
claim  Pringle-Pattison  as  on  my  side/' 2  In  what,  then, 
did  this  change  consist  ?  Not  in  any  weakening  of  his 
conviction  as  to  the  central  significance  of  human  per 
sonality,  or  the  true  witness  borne  by  the  highest  values 

1  Cf.  Professor  Hallett's  comments  in  Mind,  April  1933,  p.  144. 

2  See  the  article  already  referred  to  in  the  Australasian  Journal  of 
Psychology  and  Philosophy. 


122  MEMOIR 

in  our  experience  to  the  innermost  nature  of  Reality. 
His  view  regarding  Human  personality  was  restated  at 
length  as  against  Bosanquet's  position,  and  he  never 
wrote  with  a  graver  eloquence  than  in  such  passages  as 
that  which  ends  :  <c  Beauty  and  goodness  are  not  born 
of  the  clash  of  atoms  ;  they  are  effluences  of  something 
more  perfect  and  more  divine."  1 

But  the  distinctive  greatness  of  man's  spiritual  ex 
perience  is  now  interpreted  less  as  a  stoical  opposition 
to  the  material  forces  encompassing  him,  and  more  as 
a  relation  of  harmony  with  nature  and  a  fulfilment  of 
what  is  imperfect  in  sub-moral  life.  There  is,  indeed,  a 
striking  passage  on  the  second  last  page  of  the  book 
in  which  the  writer  speaks  of  nature  as  "an  element, 
savage  and  dangerous,  into  which  the  human  being  is 
thrown  to  show  what  stuff  he  is  made  of — an  element 
testing  with  merciless  severity  his  powers  of  courage 
and  endurance,  but  drawing  from  him  thereby  the 
utmost  of  which  he  is  capable."  But  the  main  emphasis 
is  on  man  as  the  interpreter  of  nature,  and  human  life 
as  the  consummation,  thus  far,  of  a  process  which, 
without  the  light  thrown  backwards  along  it  by  our 
spiritual  experience,  would  have  been  dark  and  mean 
ingless.  The  idea  of  "  Man  as  organic  to  the  World," 
the  title  of  the  Sixth  Lecture,  runs  through  the  book, 
and  continuity  rather  than  conflict  is  its  key-thought. 
To  express  the  change  in  different  terms,  it  is  a  move 
ment  from  the  ethicism  of  Kant  and  Fichte  to  the 
larger  humanist  view  which  represents  one  meaning  of 
the  adjective,  '  Hegelian/  In  this  later  period  Pringle- 
Pattison  would  hardly  have  repeated  his  words  at 
Princeton :  "  It  is  in  the  will,  in  purposive  action, 
and  particularly  in  our  moral  activity,  as  Fichte, 
to  my  mind,  conclusively  demonstrated,  that  we  lay 
1  P.  42 ;  cf.  pp.  236  fi. 


MEMOIR  123 

hold  upon  reality."  Or  rather,  if  he  had  repeated 
them,  it  would  have  been  with  some  addition,  softening 
their  exclusiveness  and  extending  their  range.  Thus  in 
one  of  the  later  lectures  he  speaks  of  "  the  divine  idea 
of  a  '  mind  and  life  '  "  as  "  the  very  life  itself,  experi 
enced  as  significant  because  experienced  as  a  whole, 
and  what  is  more,  as  part  of  the  meaning  of  the  all- 
inclusive  whole."  * 

The  words  last  quoted  occur  in  the  lecture  on  "  Time 
and  Eternity."  Here,  as  in  certain  other  passages,  the 
author  broke  definitely  new  ground.  He  argued  that 
"  the  eternal  view  of  a  time  process  "  is  the  view  of  its 
stages  "  as  elements  or  members  of  a  completed  pur 
pose."  In  following  this  out  he  used  the  analogy  of  a 
tragedy  or  a  symphony.  To  some  whom  he  taught  this 
may  suggest  the  regret  that  he  never  approached,  save 
incidentally,  the  problems  of  ^Esthetic.  If  he  had  dealt 
with  these  deliberately  and  on  a  large  scale,  his  apprecia 
tion  of  music,  poetry  and  natural  beauty,  and  his  finely 
developed  sense  of  form,  might  well  have  resulted  in  a 
contribution  of  unique  value  to  a  branch  of  thought 
with  which  British  philosophy  has  been  but  little 
engaged. 

But  this  crowning  volume  of  Pringle-Pattison's  career, 
together  with  the  later  Gifford  Lectures  of  which  an 
account  has  still  to  be  given,  covers  so  large  a  field  and 
contains  so  much  of  high  philosophical  and  religious  value 
that  it  savours  of  ingratitude  to  reflect  on  further  regions 
which  the  author  might  under  other  circumstances  have 
explored.  The  Idea  of  God  stands  out  with  two  other 
series  of  Gifford  Lectures  delivered  within  the  same 
years  (1907-1915)  :  Professor  James  Ward's  Realm  of 
Ends  and  Professor  Sorley's  Moral  Values  and  the  Idea 
of  God.  Though  differing  in  treatment  and  at  times  in 

1  Two  Lectures  on  Theism,  p.  46  ;  The  Idea  of  God,  p.  363. 


124  MEMOIR 

outlook,  the  three  books  have  a  solid  core  of  agreement. 
Together  they  form  an  impressive  summary  of  the 
theistic  argument,  as  it  developed  in  English  and 
Scottish  thought  in  answer  to  the  materialism  which 
sprang  from  the  triumphs  of  science  in  the  nineteenth 
century. 


125 


CHAPTER  X. 

THE   WAR  YEARS. 

1914-1918. 

THE  outbreak  of  the  Great  War,  which  brought  so  severe 
a  strain  on  numberless  British  families,  fell  inevitably 
with  an  even  greater  weight  on  the  few  homes  which 
were  as  closely  linked  with  Germany  as  that  at  The 
Haining.  For  both  husband  and  wife  there  was  a  sudden 
rending  of  old  and  intimate  bonds,  but  happily  there 
were  two  facts  which  helped  to  make  this  more  bearable 
than  it  would  otherwise  have  been.  Mrs  Pringle-Pattison 
was  an  only  surviving  child,  and  her  parents  had  passed 
away  years  before  ;  so  she  had  now  no  family  ties  with 
her  native  land.  More  important  still,  she  was  at  once 
and  completely  convinced  of  the  righteousness  of  the 
Allied  cause,  and  looked  and  hoped  throughout  for  an 
Allied  victory.  Thus  she  was  entirely  at  one  with  her 
husband  and  children  in  their  war-time  sympathies  and 
efforts. 

Even  before  the  outbreak  of  war  the  family  at  The 
Haining  had  a  twofold  military  connection.  The  eldest 
daughter,  Marjorie,  had  married  Lieutenant  (afterwards 
Major)  Webster,  R.A.M.C.,  and  the  third  son,  Siegfried, 
was  at  the  Royal  Military  College,  Sandhurst,  preparing 
for  a  commission  in  the  Cameron  Highlanders.  When 
war  broke  out  the  second  son,  Ernest,  who  had  com 
pleted  his  medical  course  a  few  months  before,  followed 


126  MEMOIR 

his  brother-in-law  into  the  Army  Medical  Corps.  How 
the  other  two  sons  and,  later,  a  second  son-in-law  took 
their  part  in  war  service  can  best  be  told  by  three  or 
four  letters  written  by  Pringle-Pattison  at  intervals 
between  1915  and  1918.  These  will  both  give  a  series, 
as  it  were,  of  cross-sections  through  the  unceasing  and 
varied  activities  of  the  sons,  and  will  also  show  the 
patient  uncomplaining  courage  of  the  father,  even  when 
the  great  blow  fell  midway  through  the  war,  and  the 
youngest,  Ronald,  fell  on  the  Somme. 

On  the  first  Sunday  of  the  war  Pringle-Pattison  wrote 
from  The  Haining  to  A.  M.  Stalker  :  ' '  Yes,  it  is  sad  to 
think  of  German  civilisation  going  down  in  a  bath  of 
blood,  as  it  seems  bound  to  do,  but,  as  you  say,  her 
spiritual  heritage  will  remain  and  perhaps  shine  out 
more  clearly.  It  is  the  German  hegemony  of  the  Prussian 
military  caste  that  must  go.  I  have  been  thinking  of 
Carlyle's  welcome  to  this  same  German  hegemony  in 
1870,  but  it  has  not  been  good  for  Europe.  The  old 
Germany  we  knew  gave  place  to  the  Bismarckian  gospel 
of  force  and  vae  victis  (as  they  have  already  begun  to 
cry  in  Germany  before  realising  who  the  conquered 
were  likely  to  be).  I  did  not  believe  in  the  inevitable- 
ness  of  this  war,  but  now  I  believe.  I  think  it  will  be  a 
changed  Europe  that  we  shall  see  when  it  is  all  over. 

"  Do  you  remember  the  constant  prophecies  and 
speculations  of  the  old  Spectator  about  what  would 
happen  when  the  Austrian  Emperor  died  ?  Will  the 
old  man  live  to  see  the  final  dismemberment  of  his 
kingdoms  ?  " 

During  the  spring  of  1915  Pringle-Pattison  watched 
with  growing  indignation  the  campaign  of  calumny 
and  innuendo  against  Lord  Haldane  which  finally  ex 
cluded  him  from  office.  Four  years  earlier  he  had 
written  when  his  friend  went  to  the  House  of  Lords  : 
"  I  have  been  much  gratified,  as  all  your  friends  must 


MEMOIR  127 

be,  to  see  how  frank  and  universal  has  been  the  tribute 
to  your  work  as  War  Minister  even  in  quarters  mostly 
given  to  carping  criticism.  It  seems  to  me  indeed  as 
if  you  were  in  danger  of  the  Biblical  woe,  when  all  men 
speak  well  of  you  !  Permit  me  to  join  in  the  chorus  of 
congratulations  and  good  wishes.  May  this  turning- 
point  in  your  career  be  only  the  starting-point  for  a 
fresh  period  of  fruitful  activity/' 

Now,  however,  the  position  was  completely  reversed, 
and  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  on  June  7,  1915  :— 

"  I  have  had  it  in  mind  to  write  you  ever  since  the 
reconstruction  of  the  Government  was  announced.  I 
have  been  very  sorry  that  stupid  and  malicious  clamour 
should  have  made  you  feel  it  right  to  resign  an  office  to 
which  destiny  had  led  you  by  a  devious  path  and  which 
you  were  so  specially  fitted  to  adorn — had,  indeed, 
already  adorned.  I  have  felt  keenly  the  injustice  of 
it,  seeing  that  it  is  precisely  to  you  that  we  owe  the 
organisation  of  the  expeditionary  force  on  the  one  hand 
and  the  territorial  army  on  the  other,  which  have  made 
the  successful  prosecution  of  the  war  possible.  Winston 
Churchill,  I  am  glad  to  see,  has  been  saying  in  Dundee 
what  all  your  friends  have  been  thinking. 

'  The  war  has  had  a  most  extraordinary  effect  in 
unsettling  people's  judgment.  I  meet  many  men  and 
women,  whom  I  should  have  thought  eminently  sober 
and  reasonable,  cherishing  almost  insane  delusions.  It 
has  been  a  very  curious  revelation. 

"  But  I  am  sure  you  feel  that  right-thinking  people 
do  you  justice,  and  meanwhile  a  period  of  rest  from  the 
intense  labours  of  so  many  years  past  may  be  well,  and 
the  O.M.  is,  I  think,  the  kind  of  honour  you  would  most 
appreciate." 

To  this  letter  Haldane  replied  that  he  counted  himself 
well  off,  as  he  was  able  to  throw  himself  into  judicial 
work,  as  well  as  philosophy  and  work  for  education. 


128  MEMOIR 

He  added  :  "  I  have  more  peace  and  time  for  meditation 
than  I  have  had  for  long." 

At  the  end  of  the  year  Pringle-Pattison  sent  this 
reply  from  Edinburgh  to  a  letter  of  Christmas  greeting 
from  W.  P.  James  at  Cardiff  :— 

"  It  was  good  to  get  your  friendly  inquiry  and  the 
good  wishes  which  the  season  brings  round.  It  is,  indeed, 
as  you  say,  with  trembling  that  one  writes  in  these  days 
to  friends  from  whom  one  had  not  heard  for  a  while. 

"  I  am  thankful  to  say  that  our  circle  is  still  intact. 
Our  third  boy  was  wounded  at  Loos  on  September  25, 
and  had  a  most  marvellous  escape.  A  bullet  passed 
through  his  throat,  just  missing  the  vital  parts.  All 
those  who  examined  the  wound  exclaimed  at  the  narrow 
ness  of  the  escape.  Having  missed,  it  left  only  a  clean 
wound  which  healed  nicely.  We  got  him  home  before 
the  middle  of  October,  and  he  had  over  six  weeks'  leave 
partly  at  The  Haining  and  partly  here,  which  was  a 
great  joy  to  us.  ...  Our  eldest  son,  Norman,  was  sent 
to  the  Dardanelles  in  August,  but  he  succumbed  to  the 
maladies  of  the  place  in  October  (enteritis  and  jaundice), 
and  was  lucky  enough  to  be  sent  home  to  convalesce.  He 
arrived  on  November  9,  and  on  the  next  day,  a  Sunday, 
we  had  the  very  extraordinary  good  fortune  of  having 
all  our  four  sons  together  again  under  one  roof. 

"  Ernest,  the  second,  who  had  spent  the  winter  in 
Rouen  in  R.A.M.C.  and  had  afterwards  been  at  the 
front  attached  to  a  regiment,  was  invalided  home  during 
the  summer,  and  after  two  months'  leave  was  put 
temporarily  on  home  duty  in  Ayrshire.  Ronald,  the 
youngest,  who  left  school  last  summer,  went  to  Sand 
hurst  in  August  for  the  four  or  five  months'  training 
they  now  give  officers." 

The  letter  goes  on  to  tell  of  the  marriage  during  the 
previous  June  of  Norman  Pringle-Pattison  to  Doris 
Tweedie,  and  the  presence  at  16  Churchhill  of  Marjorie 


MEMOIR  129 

(Mrs  Webster)  with  her  baby  boy,  and  continues  :  "  My 
younger  daughter's  fiance  has  been  fighting  with  the 
ist  Royal  Scots  near  Ypres  and  elsewhere  since  March, 
and  when  his  regiment  was  ordered  to  the  East  lately 
and  he  could  not  get  leave,  my  daughter  accompanied 
his  mother  to  Marseilles  to  see  him  before  he  went— 
rather  an  adventure  in  these  days.  They  were  rewarded 
by  seeing  him  for  two  days  and  a  half,  but  although  they 
parted  on  November  27  they  have  had  no  word  of  him 
since. 

"  Well,  well,  this  is  almost  too  much  of  a  domestic 
chronicle,  but  you  brought  it  upon  yourself.  .  .  .  When 
one  thinks  of  the  poor  Sorleys  1  and  so  many  others 
known  and  unknown,  one  feels  undeservedly  happy, 
but  as  the  war  goes  on  without  any  sign  of  ending,  one 
feels  often  strangely  old  as  if  one  belonged  to  a  bygone 
generation.  With  so  many  pledges,  one  is  afraid  to  look 
into  the  future — and  yet  one  hopes." 

During  these  months  several  letters  arrived  in  M. 
Bergson's  beautiful  handwriting,  dealing  with  the  post 
ponement  of  the  Gifford  Lectures  already  referred  to, 
telling  of  his  own  work  for  the  Allied  cause  and  his 
confidence  in  ultimate  victory,  and  containing  messages 
to  the  family  of  his  friend.  One  of  these  ran  :  "  Laissez- 
moi  vous  feliciter,  et  de  tout  cceur,  d'avour  trois  fils 
sue  le  front,  et  un  quatrieme  sur  le  point  d'y  aller. 
Laissez-moi  aussi  vous  dire  quels  vceux  je  forme  pour 
qu'ils  reviennent  sains  et  saufs." 

In  May  1916  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  to  Stalker  telling 
him  that  Norman  was  on  light  duty  near  Innerleithen ; 
Ernest  had  just  returned  to  France,  destination  unknown ; 
Siegfried  had  been  passing  through  a  strenuous  time  in 
the  trenches  near  Loos  ;  Ronald  was  guarding  the  wire- 

1  Charles  Hamilton  Sorley,  author  of  Marlborough  and  Other 
Poems,  who  fell  at  the  age  of  twenty,  was  the  son  of  Pringle-Pattioon's 
old  friends,  Professor  and  Mrs  W.  R.  Sorley. 

I 


130  MEMOIR 

less  station  at  Stoneywood,  near  Aberdeen  ;  Marjorie 
was  still  at  Malta  with  her  husband  ;  while  Clement 
Nimmo-Smith,  Elinor's  fiance,  had  been  "  cutting  down 
trees  and  scouting  on  the  mountains  near  Salonika." 

So  the  anxious  months  dragged  on,  and  the  anxiety 
became  greater  in  the  end  of  July,  when  Ronald,  aged 
just  nineteen,  went  out  to  join  his  regiment,  the  2nd 
Gordon  Highlanders,  somewhere  in  the  neighbourhood 
of  Amiens.  He  had  been  a  keen  member  of  the  O.T.C. 
at  Merchiston  Castle,  and  had  twice  shot  for  the  Ash- 
burton  Shield  at  Bisley.  He  and  his  parents  had  planned 
that  he  should  go  to  Oxford  on  leaving  Merchiston,  but, 
like  so  many  more,  he  heard  a  far  sterner  call.  His  fate 
was  strangely  different  from  that  of  his  brothers,  who 
went  through  month  after  month  of  heavy  fighting ; 
for  his  battalion  only  went  into  the  line  in  the  last  days 
of  August,  and  on  September  6  he  fell  in  a  position 
which,  according  to  the  testimony  of  a  brother  officer, 
could  only  have  been  reached  by  one  of  rare  courage. 
At  first  he  was  posted  as  missing,  but  in  a  very  few 
days  it  was  known  that  he  had  fallen.  His  brother, 
Siegfried,  returning  home  after  being  again  wounded, 
brought  the  final  news.  For  three  days  after  hearing  it 
at  Rouen  he  carried  it  with  him  silently,  until  his  parents 
met  him  in  Edinburgh,  and  he  found  that  they  also  knew. 

When  The  Idea  of  God  appeared  in  the  early  days  of 
1917  it  bore  this  dedication  : — 

TO 
MY   WIFE 

AND   THE   DEAR  MEMORY   OF 

RONALD 

OUR  YOUNGEST   SON 

WHO   GAVE   HIS   LIFE  WILLINGLY 

AT   GINCHY   ON   THE   SOMME 

6TH  SEPTEMBER  1916 


MEMOIR  131 

A  few  weeks  earlier  (October  30, 1916),  Pringle-Pattison 
wrote  to  W.  P.  James  :  "  The  enclosed  was  addressed  to 
you  a  long  time  ago,  but  I  kept  it  back  intending  to 
accompany  it  by  some  more  personal  words  of  thanks 
for  your  kind  letter  and  also  some  details  about  us. 
Unfortunately  my  eyes  have  been  more  than  usually 
weak  and  troublesome  and  have  kept  me  from  all  but 
the  unavoidable  minimum  of  writing/'  Referring  to 
Ronald,  he  went  on  :  "  His  life  was  unclouded  from 
beginning  to  end,  and  the  end  was  instantaneous.  I 
will  not  enter  into  our  grief.  It  has  been  a  comfort  to 
have  his  brother  Siegfried,  next  to  him  in  age,  with  us 
since  we  got  the  news." 

After  mentioning  a  visit  from  Marjorie,  who  had  spent 
the  summer  at  home  and  returned  to  Malta,  the  writer 
added  :  "  She  has  left  with  us  her  little  son  of  a  year 
and  a  half,  who  is  the  brightest  spot  in  the  house  and 
very  good  for  us  all,  especially  his  grandmother/' 

During  the  months  that  followed  he  wrote  for  his 
family  and  a  few  close  friends  an  account  of  Ronald's 
short  brave  life.  In  June  1917  he  wrote  to  Professor 
J.  H.  Muirhead  :- 

"  I  am  touched  by  your  feeling  reference  to  the  loss 
of  our  dear  boy.  It  still  colours  our  lives,  and  can 
never  cease  to  do  so,  and  alas  !  so  long  as  the  war  goes 
on,  we  are  constantly  in  anxiety  about  our  other  sons, 
two  of  whom  are  now  at  the  front  in  France.  I  wish 
we  met  sometimes,  but  Lewis  tells  me  you  are  rarely 
in  Scotland,  and  I  am  not  often  in  London  or  anywhere 
in  England.  My  wife  and  I  were  in  London  last  week, 
however,  as  our  third  son  was  getting  his  Military  Cross 
presented." 

This  sharp  personal  bereavement  was  not  the  only 
loss  which  fell  on  Pringle-Pattison  during  the  year  1916. 
The  Principal  of  the  University,  Sir  William  Turner, 
who  had  carried  on  his  duties  with  rare  dignity  and 


132  MEMOIR 

distinction  to  the  age  of  eighty,  passed  away  ;  and, 
among  other  losses  in  the  Senatus,  one  which  touched 
him  deeply  was  the  passing  at  a  comparatively  early 
age  of  William  Ross  Hardie,  the  Professor  of  Latin,  a 
brilliant  scholar  and  a  highly  valued  colleague. 

By  this  time  the  war  had  made  many  gaps  in  the 
ranks  of  his  former  students.  Among  these  there  was 
none  of  whose  future  work  in  philosophy  he  cherished 
higher  hopes  than  John  Handyside.  Like  himself, 
Handyside  came  up  from  the  Royal  High  School  to 
Edinburgh  University.  After  gaining  a  brilliant  First 
Class  and  the  Ferguson  Scholarship  at  the  age  of  twenty, 
he  went  on  to  Balliol,  where  his  career  was  equally  dis 
tinguished.  From  1907  he  worked  for  four  years  as 
Pringle-Pattison's  assistant  (for  the  latter  part  as 
lecturer  also),  and  a  like  period  was  spent  as  Lecturer 
in  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Liverpool.  He  then 
resigned  his  post  in  order  to  take  a  commission  in  a 
Liverpool  regiment,  and  in  October  1916  was  mortally 
wounded  "  while  gallantly  rallying  his  men  in  a  par 
ticularly  awkward  and  desperate  situation."  Handy- 
side  had  published  next  to  nothing  in  his  lifetime,  but 
soon  after  the  war  Pringle-Pattison  compiled  a  small 
volume  of  his  philosophical  papers,1  and  prefixed  to 
them  a  Biographical  Note  which  began  :  '  The  papers 
here  brought  together  are  all  that  remains  of  the  work 
of  one  of  the  acutest  and  most  thoughtful  of  the  younger 
generation  of  philosophical  teachers.  Their  author  fell 
in  the  war,  being  one  of  those  who  counted  his  life  a 
little  thing  to  give  in  so  great  a  cause." 

In  January  1918  he  wrote  again  to  W.  P.  James  :  "  I 
am  very  thankful  to  say  that  no  further  evil  has  befallen 
us  during  the  course  of  last  year.  (Did  I  write  to  you 
at  all  during  its  passing  ?)  Our  three  sons  are  alive  and 
well,  all  at  the  present  moment  in  France.  They  have 

1  The  Historical  Method  in  Ethics  and  Other  Essays  (1919). 


MEMOIR  133 

all,  including  the  medical  one,  been  in  bad  fighting  on 
the  Ypres  front  near  Paschendaele,  but  have  come 
through  safely.  Norman,  the  eldest,  was  also  in  the 
Cambrai  advance — when  it  was  an  advance — and  saw 
the  tanks  and  the  cavalry  take  Cantaing,  one  of  the 
hamlets  nearest  Cambrai  itself/' 

The  letter  then  tells  of  the  sons-in-law — for  Elinor 
Pringle-Pattison  was  now  married — one  of  whom  was 
in  France  and  the  other  on  military  duty  at  home  with 
his  arm  in  a  sling,  and  continues  :  "  My  resolution  is 
unimpaired,  but  as  regards  the  next  few  months  it 
seems  to  me  emphatically  a  case  of  '  wait  and  see/  .  .  . 

"  W.  P.  Ker  looked  in  upon  us  here  for  an  hour  about 
the  New  Year.  Otherwise  we  have  seen  few  old  friends  : 
it  is  so  difficult  for  anyone  to  get  about  now.  I  am 
selling  wood  to  the  Government  and  trying  to  prevent 
them  taking  too  much — also  ploughing  up  grass  parks  " 
— anglice,  permanent  pasture — "  for  the  nation's  food, 
which  is  a  difficult  enough  business  when  one  has  neither 
horses  nor  labour  enough  for  the  task.  Still  we  are 
doing  something. 

"  I  often  think  of  Dunster  and  Cornwall — hope  we 
may  meet  again  in  happier  times.  Brecon  would  do 
very  well :  with  time  I  daresay  I  could  still  get  to  the 
top  of  the  Beacon/' 

As  the  last  sentence  suggests,  the  writer  had  by  no 
means  lost  his  powers  of  walking.  One  day  towards 
the  end  of  the  war  he  walked  with  a  friend  from  a  point 
in  Leaderdale,  not  far  from  the  former  home  of  his 
mother's  family,  over  the  Lammermuirs  to  Humbie. 
Arriving  in  the  late  afternoon,  they  found  that  the  last 
train  had  gone,  and  they  had  to  walk  six  miles  farther 
to  Pencaitland  before  they  could  get  a  horse  and  trap 
to  take  them  to  a  point  from  which  trains  were  running 
to  Edinburgh. 

During  the  German  advance  in  April  1918  another 


134  MEMOIR 

period  of  great  anxiety  occurred,  especially  on  Siegfried's 
account.  He  had  been  sent  from  the  Camerons  to  act 
as  second-in-command  in  the  trenches  to  the  ist  Black 
Watch,  and  was  for  days  together  in  the  fierce  fighting 
near  Givenchy.  It  was  a  cause  of  profound  thankful 
ness  to  his  parents  when  a  note  came  from  him  in  hospital 
at  Camiers,  and  they  knew  that  for  the  time  he  was 
safe. 

This  war-time  chronicle  of  loss  and  anxiety  unflinch 
ingly  borne  may  end  with  extracts  from  two  letters  after 
the  Armistice.  To  Stalker,  who  had  himself  lost  a  son, 
Pringle-Pattison  wrote  on  November  16  :  "  How  sud 
denly  it  has  all  come  and  how  great  the  victory — a 
Weltgericht  indeed.  One  has  hardly  got  used  to  the  feeling 
of  relief  in  the  mornings  when  there  are  no  more  bulletins 
to  scan  and  anxiously  awaited  letters  to  look  for.  I 
trust  your  news  has  been  good  up  to  the  last  from  France 
and  Salonika  and  from  your  airman.  We  have  been 
wonderfully  spared  these  last  months,  for  Siegfried  is 
still  with  us,  doing  a  nine  weeks'  staff  course  in  Edin 
burgh,  and  Norman's  job  has  kept  him  in  this  country 
till  now,  and  Ernest  is  near  Boulogne. 

'*  The  end  of  the  long  struggle  brings  back  more  keenly 
those  who  have  died  to  secure  the  victory.  I  have  no 
doubt  you  have  been  thinking  much  of  Dan  this  week 
as  we  have  been  of  Ronald.  But  we  can  at  least  rejoice 
that  they  and  the  whole  noble  band — so  many  one 
knows — have  not  died  in  vain.  ...  I  hope  victory 
will  give  the  Allies,  and  especially  ourselves,  internal 
strength  to  resist  Bolshevism  in  all  its  varieties,  and 
make  the  necessary  transformations  of  society  in  a 
patient  and  orderly  way." 

On  December  26  he  wrote  to  W.  P.  James  :  "  The 
relief  at  the  ending  of  the  long  strain  is  indeed  great— 
so  great  indeed  that  one  has  difficulty  in  realising  that 


MEMOIR  135 

the  nightmare  is  actually  at  an  end.  How  suddenly  it 
came  too  at  the  last,  the  end  almost  as  sudden  as  the 
beginning,  and  what  a  chaos  the  world  is  and  is  likely 
to  be  for  some  good  time  to  come.  Still  I  think  we  have 
right  in  this  country  to  a  chastened  optimism.  0  passi 
graviom,  as  Virgil  encourages  us." 


136 


CHAPTER    XL 

LATER   GIFFORD   LECTURES. 

1919-1923. 

IN  the  last  months  of  the  war  the  time-table  of  Pringle- 
Pattison's  working  year  had  returned  to  the  order  with 
which  in  earlier  days  he  had  been  familiar — a  winter 
session  of  steady  lecturing,  five  days  a  week,  and  a  long 
vacation  extending  from  the  beginning  of  April  to 
October.  But  his  classes  were  in  numbers  a  mere 
shadow  of  those  in  former  days.  With  the  return  of 
peace  it  was  certain  that  there  would  be  a  rapid  increase 
in  the  number  of  students,  accompanied  by  much  heavy 
work  in  reorganising  the  department ;  so  the  question 
arose  whether  he  should  himself  enter  on  this  new 
period,  or  leave  its  responsibilities  to  a  younger  man. 
At  first  it  was  his  intention  to  resign  in  1920,  when 
forty  years  would  have  elapsed  since  he  first  taught  in 
the  University ;  but  further  thought  convinced  him 
that  it  would  be  better  to  hand  over  a  year  earlier  the 
Chair  from  which  he  had  taught  philosophy  with  the 
highest  distinction  during  twenty-eight  years.  So  his 
resignation  was  intimated  to  take  effect  in  the  summer  of 
1919.  His  feelings  as  he  sent  it  in  were  expressed  in  a 
letter  to  Professor  Stalker  on  May  13  : — 

"  If  you  look  in  the  Scotsman  to-morrow  you  will 
probably  see  in  the  Report  of  the  University  Court's 


MEMOIR  137 

proceedings  a  notice  of  the  fact  that  I  am  resigning  my 
Chair  at  the  close  of  the  present  session.  It  is  a  step 
I  have  had  in  contemplation  more  or  less  for  some  years 
(I  completed  my  thirty  years  as  a  Scotch  professor  in 
1917),  and  though  it  naturally  involves  a  wrench  and  a 
certain  amount  of  mental  and  emotional  disturbance, 
the  longing  for  freedom  has  grown  very  strong,  and  I 
think  it  is  wise  in  a  teacher  to  go  before  his  natural 
strength  is  altogether  abated. 

"  I  thought  I  should  like  you  to  hear  this  from  myself 
rather  than  come  across  it  casually  in  the  newspapers 
or  hear  it  from  others.  It  is  thirty-nine  years  this 
autumn  since  I  started  teaching  philosophy  here  as 
Eraser's  assistant/' 

When  his  successor  was  appointed,  it  was  a  great 
satisfaction  to  Pringle-Pattison  to  know  that  his  Chair 
was  to  be  filled  by  a  former  student  of  his  own  in  St 
Andrews — one  who  was  so  fully  able  to  maintain  its 
fine  traditions  as  Professor  Norman  Kemp  Smith. 

The  Edinburgh  home  at  16  Churchhill  was  still  main 
tained,  and  was  occupied  during  the  greater  part  of  the 
winter,  but  The  Haining  now  became,  even  more  than 
before,  the  focus  of  family  life.  By  the  autumn  of  1919 
the  sons  and  daughters  had  settled  down  to  their  various 
post-war  activities.  Ernest,  like  his  elder  brother-in- 
law,  retained  his  commission  in  the  Royal  Army  Medical 
Corps  ;  Siegfried,  whose  mind  had  been  set  on  a  military 
career  from  his  school-days  at  Merchiston  Castle,  re 
mained  in  the  Cameron  Highlanders  with  the  rank  of 
Captain  ;  while  Norman  Pringle-Pattison  and  Clement 
Nimmo-Smith  resumed  legal  work  as  Writers  to  the 
Signet  in  Edinburgh.  In  September  of  this  year  Pringle- 
Pattison  enjoyed  exploring  the  Roman  wall  with  his 
old  friend,  A.  M.  Stalker ;  and  a  few  days  later,  during 
the  disquiet  of  the  railway  strike,  a  walk  took  place 
from  The  Haining,  the  end  of  which  was  beautifully 


138  MEMOIR 

depicted  in  a  letter  from  W.  P.  Ker  to  his  friends  the 
MacCunns  :  "  We  ended  September  30  with  a  walk  at 
sunset,  and  later,  over  from  the  Tweed  near  Ashestiel — 
A.  S.  P. -P.  and  me.  It  was  dark  before  we  got  off  the 
hill — I  am  gloating  still — it  was  like  the  happy  days  of 
childhood  in  a  story  :  coming  down  in  darkness  and 
hearing  burns  running,  and  steering  by  the  light  thrown 
up  from  waters,  and  lights  of  Selkirk  town  on  its  hill 
across  the  water." 

Pringle-Pattison's  first  publication  after  the  war  took 
him  on  to  unwonted,  though  not  unfamiliar,  ground.  It 
was  a  pamphlet  entitled  The  Duty  of  Candour  in  Religious 
Teaching,  and  contained  an  address  delivered  in  October 
1920  as  President  of  the  Theological  Society  of  New 
College,  Edinburgh.1  He  was  not  the  first  layman  to  be 
asked  to  act  in  this  capacity,  for  Lord  Haldane  had 
done  so  some  years  earlier  ;  and  he  had  many  links  with 
the  college.  His  brother,  James,  had  studied  there,  as 
had  many  of  his  own  most  distinguished  students  ;  and 
the  Principal,  Dr  Alexander  Martin,  had  been  a  friend 
since  they  went  through  the  philosophical  classes  to 
gether  in  the  seventies.  At  the  outset  he  explained 
that  he  had  not  come  to  address  the  members  on  any 
academic  topic,  but  to  give  "  a  plain  practical  talk  on 
the  present  situation  of  the  Churches  in  regard  to  their 
inherited  creeds  and  theological  systems."  He  knew 
that  his  words  would  carry  weight  with  such  an  audience  ; 
and  he  set  out  from  the  disquieting  facts  brought  out  by 
inquiries  during  the  war  as  to  the  meagre,  and  often 
distorted,  ideas  of  Christian  teaching  held  by  most 
soldiers  in  the  citizen  armies  of  Great  Britain.  On 
these  facts  he  based  a  vigorous  appeal  to  those  who  had 
themselves  accepted  the  main  results  of  biblical  criticism 
to  practise  candour,  and  to  carry  the  sense  of  reality 

1  Then  the  Theological  College  in  Edinburgh  of  the  United  Free 
Church  of  Scotland,  and  now  of  the  Church  of  Scotland. 


MEMOIR  139 

gained  in  war  service  into  the  services  and  teaching 
of  the  Church.  "  I  believe/'  he  said,  "  that  it  is  the 
bounden  duty,  as  well  as  the  plain  interest,  of  the 
Churches  at  the  present  time  to  undertake  a  campaign  of 
instruction  in  regard  to  the  Bible,  and  primarily  in 
regard  to  the  Old  Testament.  .  .  .  The  growing  ignor 
ance  gives  you  an  excellent  opportunity  for  real  in 
struction.  You  will  be  telling  your  hearers  much  that 
is  new  to  them,  and  while  you  will  often  have  occasion 
to  emphasise  the  primitive  and  rudimentary  elements 
in  the  early  stages  of  Hebrew  religion,  the  general  effect 
of  your  instruction  ought  to  be  to  give  them  back  the 
Old  Testament  as  a  living  book  and  a  true  praeparatio 
evangelica."  In  this  short  address,  as  in  his  last  book, 
to  which  we  must  soon  refer,  Pringle-Pattison  showed 
that  he  had  not  lost  his  grasp  of  those  theological  and 
religious  questions  which  he  had  studied  and  discussed 
nearly  fifty  years  before  in  Edinburgh,  Jena  and  Got- 
tingen ;  nor  had  his  belief  diminished  in  the  value  of 
the  interpretation  which  a  liberal  theology  afforded. 

One  of  the  authors  whom  Pringle-Pattison  had  studied 
closely  from  early  days,  and  to  whose  writings  he  often 
referred,  was  John  Locke,  and  some  years  after  his 
retirement  he  prepared  an  abridged  edition  of  Locke's 
Essay  Concerning  Human  Understanding,  with  an  Intro 
duction.  But  before  this  a  train  of  events  was  in  motion 
which  led  to  the  writing  of  his  two  last  books.  He  tells 
in  the  Preface  to  The  Idea  of  Immortality  that,  in  a 
Symposium  of  the  Aristotelian  Society  held  in  1918, 
certain  statements  in  The  Idea  of  God  led  to  an  animated 
discussion  on  "  the  place  and  destiny  of  the  finite  indi 
vidual."  "  When,"  he  proceeds,  "  Principal  Jacks  con 
veyed  to  me  in  1920  an  invitation  from  the  Hibbert 
Trustees  to  deliver  a  short  course  of  lectures  in  Oxford, 
and  intimated  at  the  same  time  a  strong  desire  that  I 
should  take  Immortality  as  my  subject,  it  seemed 


140  MEMOIR 

almost  incumbent  upon  me  to  endeavour  to  meet  the 
wish  thus  expressed."  The  delivery  of  six  lectures  in 
Manchester  College  in  the  Lent  term  of  1921  proved  a 
pleasant  occasion  in  more  than  one  way,  for  Pringle- 
Pattison  found  himself  again  associated  with  the  Trust 
under  whose  auspices  he  had  studied  in  Germany  and 
produced  his  first  book  forty  years  before ;  and  it  was 
no  small  satisfaction  to  have  the  opportunity  of  lecturing 
in  Oxford  and  of  meeting  there  other  students  and 
teachers  of  philosophy. 

Meanwhile  his  former  colleagues  in  the  University  of 
Edinburgh  took  the  earliest  occasion  to  ask  him  to 
deliver  the  Gifford  Lectures  there.  The  request,  he  said, 
took  him  completely  by  surprise,  as  he  felt  that  he  had 
already  said  his  say  as  Gifford  Lecturer  in  Aberdeen. 
But  it  enabled  him  to  join  Edward  Caird  and  James 
Ward  in  the  select  company  of  those  who  have  delivered 
two  double  courses  of  Gifford  Lectures  in  different 
Scottish  universities.  It  also  gave  such  of  his  former 
students  as  were  within  reach  of  Edinburgh  the  rare  and 
unlooked-for  pleasure  of  seeing  him  again  at  his  familiar 
desk,  and  hearing  his  voice  in  the  classroom  surrounded 
by  the  names  of  former  medallists  from  the  days  of  Sir 
William  Hamilton  onward — his  own  one  of  the  greatest. 

The  Hibbert  Trustees  readily  agreed  that  Pringle- 
Pattison  should  expand  the  course  of  lectures  delivered 
in  Oxford  early  in  1921  to  form  the  Edinburgh  course 
of  the  following  winter.  So  The  Idea  of  Immortality 
took  shape,  and  appeared  in  book  form  at  the  end  of 
1922.  It  was  written  in  circumstances  of  greater  leisure 
than  the  earlier  Gifford  Lectures,  and  this  perhaps 
accounts  for  the  impression  of  unity  which  it  gives. 
The  march  of  the  argument  is  steady  and  unbroken,  and 
every  illustration,  whether  from  poetry  or  the  history 
of  thought,  makes  its  contribution  to  the  final  conclu 
sion.  The  writer's  conviction  is  patent,  yet  he  is  careful 


MEMOIR  141 

not  to  overstate  the  importance  of  Immortality  in  the 
theistic  scheme  of  things.  He  quotes  with  approval, 
as  he  had  quoted  before,  Sir  George  Adam  Smith's 
statement :  "  The  Old  Testament  is  of  use  in  reminding 
us  that  the  hope  of  immortality  is  one  of  the  secondary 
and  inferential  elements  of  religious  experience "  •; 
and  he  denies  that  we  should  "  make  it  the  centre  and 
foundation  of  our  whole  world  theory."  1  Nor  does  he 
found  his  thesis  on  any  quasi-Platonic  conception  of  the 
soul  as  an  indestructible  substance.  He  essays  the  more 
difficult  task  of  founding  it  on  the  Aristotelian  idea  of 
the  soul  as  the  "  entelechy  or  fulfilment,  the  complete 
account,  of  the  living  body  ' '  (Lecture  I V.) .  Immortality, 
he  holds,  is  only  a  belief  of  value,  if  it  harmonises  with 
our  experience  of  the  complex  unity  of  the  human 
individual.  Even  those  who  cannot  accept  the  con 
clusion  of  the  book,  or  its  final  estimate  of  human  destiny, 
may  well  feel  that  its  argument  gains  force  from  its 
very  temperateness  and  the  avoidance  of  any  philoso 
phical  short-cut  to  its  conclusion. 

A  few  months  after  its  publication  Pringle-Pattison 
restated  some  part  of  his  main  conclusions  in  a  letter  to 
an  American  correspondent 2  :— 

"  It  does  not  follow  that  we  are  to  think  of  personal 
immortality  as  an  inherent  possession  of  every  human 
soul,  or  a  talismanic  gift  conferred  indiscriminately  on 
every  being  born  in  human  shape.  A  true  self  comes 
into  being  as  the  result  of  continuous  effort,  and  the 
same  effort  is  needed  to  hold  it  together  and  ensure  its 
maintenance  ;  for  the  danger  of  disintegration  is  always 
present.  If  a  man  is  no  more  than  a  loosely  associated 
group  of  appetites  and  habits,  the  self  as  a  moral  unity 
has  either  flickered  out  or  has  never  yet  come  into 

1  The  Idea  of  Immortality,  p.  185  ;    cf.  The  Idea  of  God,  p.  43  f. 

2  Dr  Arthur  J.  Brown  of  New  York,  who  has  allowed  me  to  quote 
the  letter  here. 


142  MEMOIR 

existence.  To  the  constitution  of  such  a  real  self  there 
must  go  some  persistent  purpose,  or  rather  some  coherent 
system  of  aims  and  ideals,  and  some  glimpse  at  least, 
it  would  seem,  of  the  eternal  values.  Eternal  life,  as  a 
present  experience,  lent  no  support,  we  saw,  to  the  view 
that  such  experience  is  limited  to  the  present  life,  nor  to 
the  view  that  it  tends  in  any  way  to  bring  about  its  own 
cessation  by  dissolving  the  finite  personality.  It  does, 
however,  certainly  suggest  that  the  further  life  is  to  be  re 
garded  as  the  sequel  and  harvest  of  what  began  here.  .  .  . 

"  Where  life  is  lived  entirely  on  the  animal  level,  there 
seems  no  reason  whatever  to  suppose  that  the  life  does 
not  come  to  an  end  with  the  death  of  the  body.  But 
where  there  are  any  stirrings  of  higher  things,  such 
desires,  faint  and  flickering  as  they  may  be,  seem  to 
justify  the  admission  of  the  individual  to  further  oppor 
tunity  when  this  earthly  stage  is  ended/' 

The  Idea  of  Immortality  was  dedicated  to  the  Earl  of 
Balfour,  who  wrote  in  acknowledgment  :  '  Your  book 
has  given  me  much  pleasure  ;  pray  accept  my  warmest 
thanks.  I  am  delighted  to  have  my  name  associated 
in  any  capacity  with  a  work  of  yours."  Among  other 
friends  to  whom  Pringle-Pattison  sent  it  were  Dr  Bernard 
Bosanquet  and  Mr  F.  H.  Bradley,  and  each  acknowledged 
the  gift  in  a  closely  reasoned  letter.  That  from  Dr 
Bosanquet  expresses  his  final  thoughts  on  the  great 
subject  of  immortality,  for  it  was  written  only  a  few 
days  before  the  beginning  of  his  last  illness  and  a  month 
before  his  death  on  February  8,  1923.  It  runs  as 
follows  : — 

"  13  HEATHGATE, 

GOLDERS  GREEN,  N.W.  u. 

Jan.  8,  1923. 

"  MY  DEAR  PRINGLE-PATTISON, — I  received  your  new 
book  on  Saturday,  and  having  a  quiet  Sunday  yesterday 
read  it  through.  I  don't  mean  to  say  that  I  can  have 


MEMOIR  143 

done  it  justice  in  such  a  rapid  reading,  but  it  was  so 
interesting  that  I  could  not  lay  it  down. 

"  I  think  it  is  very  good  indeed.  On  all  the  points 
where  moral  dangers  appear  to  me  to  lurk  in  popular 
views  of  the  great  subject,  it  satisfies  me  pretty  com 
pletely.  I  welcome  it  as  sound  and  lofty  teaching,  and 
am  unfeignedly  glad  that  your  great  authority  and 
your  excellent  exposition  should  be  used  in  helping  the 
public  to  such  conceptions. 

'  You  will  not,  of  course,  expect  that  I  should  alter 
my  own  position,  or  entirely  acquiesce  in  your  repre 
sentation  of  it.  But  I  do  not  expect  that  I  shall  recur 
to  the  subject  in  public,  mainly  because  I  foresee  no 
special  occasion  for  doing  so,  and  I  am  very  content  to 
leave  the  matter  to  the  consequences  wrhich  may  emerge 
from  the  temper  of  our  times  and  the  general  influences 
at  work,  including  your  books  and  mine,  of  which  yours 
will  be  by  far  the  more  influential. 

"  If  I  did  return  to  the  subject,  there  is  one  point  I 
should  stress  more  than  I  have  done  before  ;  and  if,  as 
I  think  you  mean  to,  you  return  to  it,  it  would  be  valu 
able  if  you  would  say  an  explicit  word  on  it.  It  is  the 
influence,  on  the  general  feeling  about  a  future  life,  of 
the  change  from  the  orthodox  tradition  to  modern 
speculation,  and  also  modern  superstition.  (See  Value 
and  Destiny,  272  ff.)  When  I  think  of  the  belief  in 
which  I,  and  I  suppose  you,  were  brought  up,  as  expressed 
by  our  hymns  and  liturgy — '  Who  are  these  arrayed  in 
white/  &c. — I  feel  that  it  was  a  symbolism  of  some 
thing  splendid  and  great,  though  untenable.  Probation 
was  to  end  with  death ;  by  a  miracle,  one  was  to  be 
lifted  into  realisation  of  close  proximity  with  deity. 

"  That  idea  I  think  is  going,  and  must  go.  Both 
more  spiritual  views,  as  your  own  teaching  about '  eternal 
life/  with  the  effort  to  banish  remoteness  and  mystery 
from  the  idea  of  the  future  life,  and  more  material  views 


I44  MEMOIR 

like  those  of  the  '  spiritualists/  are  bringing  about  an 
assimilation  between  '  this  '  life  and  '  the  other/  The 
presumption  in  favour  of  conditions  of  spiritual  progress 
in  the  '  other '  life,  differing  in  principle  from  what 
obtain  '  here/  is  tending,  it  seems  to  me,  to  vanish. 
If  we  can  be  as  near  God  in  this  life  as  in  another,  it 
seems  to  follow  that  we  can  be  as  far  from  him  in  another 
as  in  this.  And  in  views  borrowed  from  the  succession 
of  lives  on  this  earth,  there  is  a  strong  presumption  (in 
spite  of  M'Taggart)  against  any  transmission  of  experi 
ence  or  character  from  one  life  to  its  successor.  And 
such  views  are  increasingly  influential. 

"  With  such  an  atmosphere  as  this,  I  do  think  our 
attitude  must  inevitably  change.  The  certainty  formerly 
offered  to  hope  is  gone .  There  is  nothing  anywhere  but  pro 
bation.  There  are,  in  a  sense,  as  you  suggest, '  elect '  souls ; 
but  who  can  be  confident  that  he  is  of  the  number  ?  I 
don't  know  if  Jones  had  dealt  anywhere  with  Browning's 
lines — '  There's  a  fancy  some  lean  to  and  others  hate '  (Old 
Pictures  in  Florence) — but  I  think  they  represent  a  point 
of  view  which  will  become  more  and  more  influential. 

"  However,  my  point  is  just  the  new  idea  of  the  future, 
which  seems  to  me  to  be  gaining  ground.  If  it  is  what 
the  world  is  really  coming  to,  so  far  as  it  holds  to  a 
future,  I  can  hardly  think  that  it  will  maintain  itself. 
I  think  that  a  view  like  Bradley 's  in  the  conclusion  of 
Truth  and  Reality  will  replace  it.  But  I  wish  very  much 
that  you  would  say  what  you  think  about  it  in  public. 
—Yours  very  truly,  B.  BOSANQUET." 

The  letter  from  Mr  Bradley  was  written  some  months 
later  : — 

MERTON  COLLEGE,  OXFORD, 
May  22-23. 

"  DEAR  PROFESSOR  PRINGLE-PATTISON, — I  have  just 
finished  reading  your  Idea  of  Immortality,  which  you 


MEMOIR  145 

so  kindly  sent  to  me  and  which  I  left  on  one  side  too 
long.  And  I  must  send  you  a  few  lines  to  congratulate 
you  on  what  seems  to  me  such  an  excellent  piece  of 
work,  and  to  thank  you  for  the  pleasure  and  profit 
which  has  come  to  me  in  reading  it.  I  have  seldom,  if 
ever,  read  any  book  on  such  a  subject  which  carried  me 
with  it  throughout  so  fully.  In  fact  I  am  not  sure 
that  I  have  to  dissent  anywhere  from  your  conclusions, 
if,  that  is,  I  have  understood  them  rightly. 

"  I  did  not  look  at  M'Taggart's  criticism  in  Mind  until 
I  had  read  your  book,  and  I  do  not  think  he  has  under 
stood  you,  but  on  the  contrary  has  very  seriously  failed 
to  do  so. 

"  But  first  let  me  notice  the  two  places  where  you 
have  criticised  myself.  In  the  first  of  these  (p.  128)  I 
accept  your  criticism  without  reserve,  and  agree  that  I 
was  wrong.  In  the  second  (pp.  156-9)  I  cannot  go  so 
far  as  that.  What  I  said  is,  I  think,  defensible,  except 
so  far  as  I  laid  an  undue  emphasis  on  one  side  of  the 
matter.  I  don't  think  that  I  denied  or  even  forgot  the 
other  side,  but  I  agree  that  what  I  wrote  was  such  as 
to  produce  in  the  mind  of  the  reader  a  one-sided  and 
incorrect  impression.  The  mood  in  which  my  book  was 
conceived  and  executed  was,  in  fact,  to  some  extent  a 
passing  one.  And,  if  this  was  regrettable  in  one  sense, 
in  another  sense  and  from  the  literary  side  it  was,  I 
suppose,  otherwise.  And  I  cannot  alter  the  book  now, 
though  I  would  not  repeat  all  of  it.  And  in  particular 
I  certainly  would  not  say  now  that  '  a  future  life  must  be 
taken  as  decidedly  improbable  '  (Appearance,  p.  506). 

"As  to  MTaggart,  he  does  not  see  that  what  we  call 
'  matter '  and  mere  material  causation  is  from  your 
point  of  view  an  abstraction  which  in  the  end  is  not 
real  or  true.  He  does  not  see  that  every  real  conse 
quence  involves  a  larger  concrete  whole  and  that  hence 
in  reality  new  consequences  come  as  '  emergents  '  from 

K 


146  MEMOIR 

that,  however  inexplicable  these  may  be  from  a  merely 
abstract  view  such  as  is  matter  and  mechanical  causa 
tion.  .  .  . 

*  The  real  question  with  you,  I  understand,  is  not  as 
to  '  survival '  but  as  to  '  survival  exactly  as  what.' 
Our  '  personality  '  even  in  life  involves  always  a  '  more/ 
and  so  again  after  death.  And  the  question  is  as  to 
whether  and  how  far  this  '  more  '  is  such  as  to  supersede 
what  we  call  our  personality,  as  such,  or  whether  this 
'  more  '  still  more  or  less  and  in  some  sense  still  pre 
serves  it.  And  the  question  of  degree  comes  in  here  as 
important,  especially  in  the  case  of  more  or  less  worth 
less  personalities. 

"  I  might  perhaps  put  the  matter  thus.  Every  self 
has  a  claim  to  complete  self-realisation,  and  this  must 
even  include  '  happiness/  Every  self  is,  in  a  sense,  so 
realised  even  in  life — but  how,  and  in  what  sense,  and 
how  much  of  what  it  calls  its  '  personality '  is  involved 
in  such  complete  self-realisation  ?  So  far  as  the  person 
ality  is  one  with  what  we  call  '  the  bad  self  ' — what  are 
we  to  say  ? 

"  And,  as  in  life,  so  after  death. 

"  Where  I  think  we  are  agreed  is  that  to  answer  these 
questions  is  not  possible.  But  for  practical  purposes 
we  may  come  nearest  to  the  truth  by  embracing  the 
idea  of  a  personal  survival  and  progress  after  death — 
continued  so  long  as  is  best  for  us  and  for  the  Whole. 
We  admit  that  this  is  not  the  entire  and  full  truth — 
which  is  in  detail  beyond  us,  and  we  don't  defend  the 
idea  of  progress  to  complete  personal  perfection  as  being 
more  than  one  aspect  of  the  whole  truth,  an  aspect 
which  we  don't  pretend  to  combine  harmoniously  with 
other  aspects — but  which  is  still  the  best  idea  compared 
with  any  other  alternative  in  our  reach,  and  is  there 
fore  defensible.  I  can  go  as  far  as  this,  and  I  think 
that  perhaps  you  will  say  that  this  is  far  enough. 


MEMOIR  147 

"  As  to  the  difficulty  with  regard  to  the  body,  I  agree 
that  the  longer  we  live,  the  less  our  bodies  as  mere 
matter  ought  to  count.  They  ought  to  be  implied  in 
our  '  personality  '  to  a  less  and  less  degree  even  as  a 
condition  of  that.  I,  however,  feel  some  difficulty  as  to 
a  wholly  bodiless  personality,  one  in  which  the  body 
has  come  to  be  only  a  past  condition.  And,  however 
much  I  dissent  in  general  from  the  idea  of  a  '  spiritual 
body/  I  am  inclined  here  to  fall  back  on  our  ignorance 
about  '  matter '  and  the  variety  of  what  may  exist 
unknown  to  us,  because  beyond  our  actual  senses.  I 
should  hence  be  willing  to  agree  to  the  possibility  of 
selves  which  after  death  would  be  perceptible  by  and 
recognizable  by  one  another,  and  would  so  far  have 
something  in  the  way  of  a  body.  I  see  that  here  we  are 
on  horribly  dangerous  ground,  but  still  total  and  absolute 
bodilessness — without  loss  of  personality  as  such — gives 
me  difficulty.  And  I  am  not  quite  sure  as  to  your 
position  here.  Of  course,  one  shrinks  from  anything 
that  looks  like  an  adoption  of  what  is  called  '  spirit 
ualism/ 

"  But  I  have  tried  your  patience,  I  fear,  too  much 
already,  and  you  will  not,  I  hope,  think  yourself  called 
on  to  answer  this  letter — which  was  meant  to  be  only  a 
message  of  congratulation  and  of  thanks. — Yours  truly, 

"F.  H.  BRADLEY/' 

This  letter  forms  a  remarkable  culmination  to  a 
friendship  between  two  thinkers  who  had  at  one  time 
occupied  standpoints  that  seemed  far  apart,  and  whom 
the  single-minded  pursuit  of  truth  had  brought  at  the 
end  to  a  large  measure  of  agreement.  In  the  year  in 
which  Pringle-Pattison  received  it,  he  gave  his  last 
course  of  Gifford  Lectures.  Its  title  was  "  Religious 
Origins  and  the  Philosophy  of  History,"  but  he  soon 
came  to  feel  that  these  topics  could  hardly  be  moulded 


148  MEMOIR 

into  an  effective  unity ;  so  he  summarised  what  he  had 
said  on  the  latter  subject  in  a  lecture  on  the  "  Philosophy 
of  History  "  published  in  the  Proceedings  of  the  British 
Academy  for  1924,  and  spent  the  following  five  years 
working  over  the  earlier  part  of  the  course,  adding  to  it 
a  treatment  of  the  development  of  ethical  religion  in 
Judaism  and  Christianity.  Finally,  after  this  long 
process  of  revision,  the  book  appeared  in  the  summer 
of  1930,  with  the  full  title,  "  Studies  in  the  Philosophy 
of  Religion,  partly  based  on  the  Gifford  Lectures  delivered 
in  the  University  of  Edinburgh  in  the  year  1923."  The 
somewhat  unusual  phrase  "  partly  based  on  "  indicates 
the  extent  to  which  the  original  lectures  had  been  altered 
and  extended  before  publication,  as  does  the  division  of 
the  book  into  seventeen  chaptefs  instead  of  the  familiar 
ten  lectures.  Throughout,  the  treatment  is  historical. 
Especially  in  the  first  six  chapters,  which  deal  with 
primitive  and  early  religion,  the  ground  covered  was 
new  to  the  writer,  but  his  own  interest  in  exploring  it, 
and  the  power  of  exposition  which  never  deserted  him, 
lend  vividness  to  his  survey.  At  intervals  the  argument 
is  lit  up  by  a  flash  of  insight  focussed  in  a  terse  phrase, 
as  when  he  says  that,  even  for  the  poly t heist,  "  there  is  a 
kind  of  implicit  monotheism  in  the  very  act  and  attitude 
of  worship  "  ;  or  that  Jesus  "  did  not  merely  teach 
the  fatherhood ;  he  lived  the  sonship  "  (pp.  86,  168). 
The  last  six  chapters  deal  with  the  New  Testament 
and  early  Christianity,  and  the  last,  entitled  "  The 
Christ  of  the  Creeds,"  takes  the  writer  into  a  theological 
region  which  he  had  hardly  entered  before.  Yet  this 
return,  from  the  historical  point  of  view,  to  the  Philosophy 
of  Religion,  which  he  had  treated  in  his  first  book  from 
the  standpoint  of  the  great  modern  idealist  systems, 
makes  manifest  the  underlying  unity  of  his  thinking 
during  fifty  years. 


149 


CHAPTER  XII. 

CLOSING   YEARS. 

1923-1931. 

IN  the  summer  of  1923  Professor  W.  P.  Ker  died  suddenly 
while  on  a  walking  tour  in  Switzerland.  This  was  a 
blow  which  Pringle-Pattison  felt  keenly,  and  on  July  22 
he  wrote  from  The  Haining  to  Mr  W.  P.  James  :  "I 
feel  I  must  write  to  you  in  our  common  sorrow,  for  I 
know  Ker's  death  must  touch  you  very  closely.  For 
myself  I  can  think  of  nothing  else  since  I  saw  the  fact, 
so  terrible  in  its  total  unexpectedness,  in  Thursday's 
paper.  Somehow  one  took  it  for  granted  that  he  would 
go  on  to  a  serene  old  age  like  his  father's  between  eighty 
and  ninety.  One  saw  others  growing  older  and  felt  the 
advance  of  years  oneself,  but  he  seemed  ewig  Jung,  so 
full  of  the  zest  of  life  and  the  love  of  all  beautiful  things, 
that  one  had  no  fears  or  anxieties  for  him  and  never 
dreamt  of  outliving  him.  And  now  the  curtain  is  drawn 
through  a  little  over-exertion  on  the  mountains.  It  is 
indeed  a  lamentable  calamity  to  all  his  friends.  ...  I 
saw  him  for  the  last  time  on  February  5,  when  we  parted 
in  the  Oxford  railway  station  after  a  most  happy  week 
end  when  he  entertained  me  at  All  Souls.  .  .  . 

"  We  were  in  hopes  of  inducing  him  to  spend  some 
time  here  later  in  the  autumn,  and  I  had  been  thinking 
how  pleasant  it  would  be  to  have  you  here  at  the  same 


150  MEMOIR 

time  after  so  long  an  interval.  I  have  not  seen  you 
since  we  parted  after  that  Cornish  expedition  in  the 
spring  of  1914.  You  remember  how  Ker  walked  round 
every  point  of  rock,  while  most  of  us  were  contented  to 
take  the  base  line  of  the  triangle  ?  Alas  !  alas  !  for  all 
that  has  happened  'twixt  then  and  now,  and  especially 
for  this  last  impoverishment.  But  will  you  not,  perhaps 
all  the  more,  try  to  come  to  us  for  a  week  and  inter 
change  thoughts  and  renew  old  memories  ?  .  .  .  Do 
think  of  it  :  I  cannot  say  whether  we  may  be  here  next 
summer ;  we  might  find  it  desirable  to  let  the  place. 
But  this  year  at  any  rate  we  are  here,  and  the  children 
and  grandchildren  are  coming  to  us  in  relays.  In  the 
end  of  September  we  hope  to  see  our  soldier  son  back 
from  Chanak.  '  W.  P.'  was  a  household  word  with  all 
the  children,  and  they  understand  what  we  have  lost 
in  him/' 

Just  a  year  later,  when  Professor  James  Seth,  who  had 
resigned  the  Chair  of  Moral  Philosophy  a  few  weeks 
before,  was  calling  to  inquire  for  an  invalid  friend  in 
Edinburgh,  he  suddenly  passed  away.  His  heart  was 
known  to  be  gravely  affected,  but  the  shock  to  mem 
bers  of  his  family  was  none  the  less  great.  Not  only 
had  he  been  a  close  comrade  of  his  elder  brother  in  their 
activity  as  thinkers  and  teachers,  but  he  had  never 
married,  was  a  frequent  visitor  to  The  Haining,  and  had 
been  with  the  family  there  or  at  Churchhill  during  many 
of  the  tense  and  sorrowful  moments  of  the  war.  The 
short  Memoir  which  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  the  following 
year  as  an  Introduction  to  the  volume,  Essays  in  Ethics 
and  Religion,  shows,  even  through  its  characteristic 
restraint,  in  how  close  a  unity  the  two  brothers  lived  and 
worked. 

Although  such  empty  places  were  multiplying  in  the 
circle  of  Pringle-Pattison's  contemporaries  and  fellow- 
workers,  there  were  many  others  of  his  own  time  and 


MEMOIR  151 

among  his  pupils  who  were  eager  to  acknowledge  their 
debt  to  him.  So,  during  the  following  winter,  he  was 
asked  to  give  sittings  to  Mr  A.  E.  Borthwick,  A.R.S.A., 
who  painted  a  portrait  of  much  dignity  and  expressive 
ness,  in  which  he  is  represented  standing  in  his  robes 
as  a  Doctor  of  Laws.  The  portrait  was  presented  in  the 
Senate  Hall  of  the  University  on  March  7,  1925.  Pro 
fessor  W.  P.  Paterson,  Dean  of  the  Faculty  of  Divinity, 
who  had  known  Andrew  Seth  at  the  High  School  and 
had  in  later  years  been  for  long  his  colleague  and  friend, 
presided  over  the  gathering.  He  said  that  the  portrait 
was  that  of  one  "  known  throughout  the  English- 
speaking  world  as  the  most  distinguished  theologian  of 
Edinburgh  University — a  philosophical  theologian. ' '  The 
presentation  was  made  by  an  Honours  student  of  thirty 
years  before — Mr  H.  P.  Macmillan,  K.C.,  now  Lord 
Macmillan — who  emphasised,  as  the  Chairman  had  already 
done,  the  fact  that  his  career  was  a  distinctively  Scottish 
one.  Mr  Macmillan  also  said  that  no  teacher  could  make 
the  science  miscalled  "  crabbed  metaphysics "  more 
human  and  inspiring  than  could  he,  while  his  written 
studies  never  failed  to  sound  the  note  of  optimism. 

Pringle-Pattison's  reply  was  in  part  reminiscent,  in 
part  a  defence  of  the  place  of  philosophy  as  an  integral 
part  of  a  university  curriculum.  After  summarising  the 
view  of  life  which  he  had  always  tried  to  set  before  his 
students,  he  said  that  he  had  always  considered  the  life 
of  a  university  teacher  as  "  one  of  the  happiest  and  most 
memorable  that  could  fall  to  any  man's  lot.  His  re 
sponsibilities  w^ere  great,  but  his  reward  was  also  great. 
If  he  loved  his  subject — and  it  was  presumably  the 
subject  of  his  choice — he  would  be  in  no  danger  of  finding 
it  grow  stale  ;  it  would  always  be  showing  new  sides  of 
itself  and  opening  up  new  vistas  of  delight."  l  The 
simple  ceremony  will  live  in  the  memories  of  Pringle- 
1  Scotsman,  March  9,  1925* 


152  MEMOIR 

Pattison's  old  students  who  were  fortunate  enough  to 
form  part  of  the  little  company  as  a  very  fitting 
consummation  of  his  long  service  to  the  University, 
and  especially  they  will  treasure  the  words  of  his 
reply. 

A  year  before  this  presentation  Professor  and  Mrs 
Pringle-Pattison  paid  a  long-planned  visit  to  Italy,  and 
a  year  later  they  revisited  Germany — an  experience 
which,  he  said,  he  had  hardly  hoped  again  to  enjoy.  But 
Dr  Schurman  was  now  Ambassador  of  the  United  States 
in  Berlin,  and  an  invitation  to  spend  ten  days  at  the 
Embassy  in  the  city  which  they  seen  together  as  students 
nearly  half  a  century  before  was  an  opportunity  too 
good  to  miss.  The  resulting  visit  was  described  in  a 
letter  to  Lord  Haldane  on  May  27,  1926  :— 

"  We  had  a  delightful  fortnight  with  the  Ambassador 
in  Berlin,  the  second  half  of  April,  and  enjoyed  summer- 
like  warmth,  while,  according  to  reports,  you  were 
shivering  with  cold  both  in  Scotland  and  England.  We 
met  a  number  of  interesting  people  at  the  Embassy, 
including  Luther,  the  Chancellor,  Einstein,  Professor 
Liebeck  (President  of  the  Kant  Gesellschaft) ,  Ludwig 
Stein  (editor  of  the  Archiv  fur  GescMchte  d.  Philosophic], 
who  sent  you  his  warm  regards,  and  many  others.  Schur 
man  had  a  very  high  opinion  of  Luther's  wisdom  and 
honesty  and  also  of  Zimmerman's  ability.  He  main 
tains  cordial  relations  with  them  and  others,  and  is,  I 
think,  a  persona  grata  all  round. 

"  The  amazing  differences  between  the  Germany  of 
to-day  and  Germany  as  we  used  to  know  it  is,  of  course, 
the  total  disappearance  (submergence  at  all  events)  of 
the  military  class.  You  remember  the  tall  arrogant 
officers  with  their  flowing  cloaks  and  clanking  spurs 
monopolising  the  pavement  in  Unter  den  Linden.  Now 
not  a  uniform,  other  than  a  policeman's,  to  be  seen  in 
Germany  except  the  British  khaki  in  Wiesbaden  (where 


MEMOIR  153 

we  wound  up  our  stay)  and  the  scarlet  mess-jackets  of 
the  officers  dancing  in  the  evenings  in  the  hotels  there. 
If  this  state  of  things  is  allowed  to  go  on  for  any  length 
of  time,  it  cannot  but  profoundly  affect  the  spirit  of 
the  people,  and  I  should  doubt  whether  it  would  ever 
be  possible  to  reimpose  conscription  upon  the  nation 
when  the  mass  of  the  people  have  tasted  freedom. 

"  We  had  a  short  but  pleasant  visit  to  Gottingen 
towards  the  end  of  April — '  we  '  in  this  case  meaning 
Schurman,  the  Rev.  Lewis  Muirhead  and  myself. 
Schurman  had  notified  the  '  Curator '  of  the  University 
of  our  intended  visit,  and  we  were  met  at  the  station 
by  him  and  his  '  Magnificanz/  the  Rector  and  an  Ameri 
can  professor  on  the  staff — all  in  tall  hats,  who  whisked 
us  off  to  a  meeting  of  the  Akademie  der  Wissenschaften, 
which  happened  to  take  place  that  afternoon,  thence 
to  supper  and  then  to  a  '  Bier-abend  '  of  the  professors 
in  residence,  where  a  speech  of  welcome  by  the  Chairman, 
to  which  Schurman  replied,  was  followed  by  informal 
conversation  washed  down  by  beer.  Next  morning  they 
brought  two  cars  and  showed  us  all  the  chief  sights  of 
the  University,  including  our  own  signatures  in  the 
Matriculation  Album  of  1880  ! — and  after  they  had 
entertained  us  to  a  most  friendly  lunch  (at  the  Curator's 
house)  we  left  the  same  afternoon.  ...  It  is  a  busy 
hive  of  learning,  and  the  University,  with  its  many 
institutes,  has  grown  out  of  knowledge  since  1880.  The 
very  face  of  the  rather  dull  country  round  has  been 
changed  by  judicious  planting. 

"  From  Berlin  my  wife  and  I  went  to  Weimar  for 
part  of  three  days,  on  one  of  which  we  went  along  to 
Jena  and  lunched  in  the  Bar,  where  John  [Dr  J.  S. 
Haldane]  and  I  lunched  together  for  a  whole  Semester 
in  1879.  From  Weimar  we  went  on  to  Eisenach,  but 
just  as  May  came  in  the  weather  changed  to  dull  and 
cool,  and  we  were  obliged  to  give  up  the  idea  of  further 


154  MEMOIR 

exploration  in  Thuringen.  So  we  did  not  penetrate  to 
Ilmenau  ;  in  fact  we  only  got  up  to  the  Wartburg  in  a 
closed  motor  an  hour  or  so  before  we  left  Eisenach. 

"  We  went  on  to  Wiesbaden  hoping  for  the  warmth 
and  sunshine  one  usually  gets  there,  but  the  same  type 
of  weather  continued,  and  the  Strike  also  came  to 
unsettle  our  plans,  so  we  simply  remained  in  a  comfort 
able  hotel  there  till  the  way  was  clear  for  return. 

"  The  good  temper  of  the  nation  during  the  [General] 
Strike  and  the  way  in  which  it  was  terminated  greatly 
increased  our  prestige  on  the  Continent.  If  only  some 
thing  similar  could  be  achieved  in  the  Coal  Strike  !  " 

The  loyalty  of  Pringle-Pattison  to  old  friends  has 
already  been  noted.  One  characteristic  instance  occurred 
when  Professor  MacCunn's  eyesight  had  seriously  failed, 
and  his  wife  was  suffering  from  a  throat  affection  which 
for  the  time  prevented  her  reading  to  him.  Hearing  of 
this,  Pringle-Pattison,  though  in  poor  health  himself, 
crossed  Scotland  in  mid- winter  to  visit  and  cheer  them. 

In  these  years  at  The  Haining  the  grandchildren 
more  and  more  played  the  part  which  had  been  played 
by  the  sons  and  daughters  when  Pringle-Pattison  and 
his  wife  first  made  their  home  there.  He  had  lost  none 
of  his  interest  in  his  trees,  and  when  any  required  pruning 
round  the  house  or  beside  the  loch  he  was  wont  to  do 
the  work  himself.  Sometimes  his  venerable  figure  might 
be  seen  disappearing  into  the  woods  with  a  small  grand 
son,  immensely  proud  of  his  dignity  and  looking  forward 
to  a  lesson  in  woodcraft,  marching  on  either  side,  all 
three  being  armed  with  hatchet,  bill  or  saw.  The  eldest 
grandson,  Harry  Webster,  lived  regularly  for  some 
years  with  his  grandparents  in  order  to  attend  Mer- 
chiston  School.  There  were  also  the  two  families  in 
Edinburgh ;  and  shortly  before  the  end  of  1925  the 
second  son,  Ernest,  who  had  married  in  India,  came 
home  with  his  wife  and  child.  So  the  circle  enlarged ; 


MEMOIR  155 

and,  even  in  the  last  months,  when  Pringle-Pattison's 
physical  strength  began  to  ebb,  no  one  could  see  him 
in  its  midst  without  feeling  how  much  he  remained  its 
active  centre. 

The  spring  of  1928  brought  grave  anxiety.  His  wife's 
health,  on  which  the  anxiety  of  the  war  years  had  un 
doubtedly  placed  a  severe  strain,  broke  down  in  May, 
and  after  several  months  of  illness  she  passed  away  at 
The  Haining  on  October  25.  In  the  words  of  Mr  Capper  : 
"  It  was  a  blow  of  extreme  severity,  and  although  her 
husband  bore  it  with  his  customary  patience  he  never 
recovered  from  the  shock/'  A  few  weeks  would  have 
brought  them  to  the  fiftieth  anniversary  of  their  first 
meeting  and  the  beginning  of  their  love  for  one  another  ; 
and  for  forty-four  years  they  had  shared  all  life's  ex 
periences  as  man  and  wife.  After  so  long  and  perfect 
a  union  the  parting  could  not  but  leave  him  who  sur 
vived  weary  and  lonely,  though  ever  courageous.  Even 
in  regard  to  his  physical  strength,  those  who  were 
nearest  noticed  that  the  heart  trouble  which  had  been 
apparent  earlier  now  grew  markedly  worse. 

The  severance  of  a  friendship  of  more  than  fifty  years 
came  in  the  same  year,  for  on  August  19,  1928,  Richard 
Burdon  Haldane  passed  away  at  Cloan.  A  few  months 
later  Pringle-Pattison  wrote  a  long  biographical  article 
for  the  Proceedings  of  the  British  Academy.  This 
appreciation  of  Lord  Haldane 's  work,  public  and  philo 
sophical,  showed  his  gifts  as  an  author  still  unimpaired 
—his  admirably  balanced  judgment,  and  his  power  of 
describing  men  and  events  in  rapid  summary  without 
baldness  and  of  expressing  heartfelt  admiration  with  no 
forced  or  exaggerated  note. 

The  death  of  Lord  Haldane  was  followed  after  eighteen 
months  by  that  of  Lord  Balfour.  Again  Pringle-Pattison 
was  asked  to  write  an  account  of  the  philosophical  work 
of  one  whom  he  had  known  for  so  long  and  whose  friend- 


156  MEMOIR 

ship  he  so  highly  valued.  He  felt  the  importance  of  the 
task — his  last,  as  it  proved — and  it  occupied  him  closely 
through  the  early  months  of  1931.  When  his  last  illness 
began,  it  was  complete,  save  for  the  final  revision  of  the 
closing  portion,  and  at  the  date  when  this  Memoir  is 
written  it  awaits  publication. 

In  the  last  three  lonely  years  his  children  and  grand 
children  were  able  to  do  much  to  fill  his  days  with 
varied  interest.  He  enjoyed  runs  by  motor  to  many  of 
the  beautiful  and  historic  places  round  Edinburgh  with 
one  or  other  of  his  children,  including  his  son  Siegfried, 
who  spent  part  of  this  time  with  his  regiment  at  Redford, 
just  outside  the  city.  In  March  1929  Norman  Pringle- 
Pattison  snatched  a  few  weeks  from  the  claims  of  busi 
ness  and  started  with  his  father  for  Naples.  Pringle- 
Pattison  had  long  wished  to  see  that  region,  and  entered 
with  zest  into  the  exploration  of  the  enchanted  country 
surrounding  the  Bay  of  Naples — Paestum,  Pompeii, 
Amalfi,  Sorrento,  Capri.  Then  they  turned  north,  to 
wards  Rapallo,  and  had  one  day  in  Rome.  Here  he  was 
able  to  act  as  guide  to  his  son  (he  had  visited  Rome  some 
years  earlier  with  his  wife),  and  showed  the  same  enthu 
siasm  in  taking  him  round  the  Forum,  the  Palatine 
and  St  Peter's.  From  Rapallo  Norman  Pringle-Pattison 
returned  home,  but  his  father  remained  on  the  Italian 
Riviera  with  a  party  which  included  three  old  friends- 
Professor  and  Mrs  Sorley  and  Mrs  Ross,  whose  husband, 
Dr  David  M.  Ross,  had  been  a  senior  friend  in  the 
philosophical  classes  in  the  seventies.  Unfortunately 
influenza  descended  upon  the  party,  and  although  Pringle- 
Pattison  escaped,  his  return  had  to  be  made  alone  by  sea 
from  Genoa. 

The  following  year,  as  has  been  noted,  saw  the  pub 
lication  of  his  last  book.  Of  the  philosophers  of  his  own 
generation  few  now  survived.  But  when  the  name 
of  one,  Professor  Alexander,  appeared  in  the  King's 


MEMOIR  157 

Birthday  Honours  List  as  receiving  the  Order  of  Merit, 
he  at  once  wrote  :  "  Very  hearty  congratulations  on 
the  much  coveted  and  well  bestowed  honour  just  con 
ferred  on  you.  I  am  glad  both  for  your  own  sake  and 
the  sake  of  philosophy." 

In  the  early  summer  of  1931  Pringle-Pattison  embarked 
on  his  last  foreign  journey,  a  cruise  to  the  Northern 
Capitals  with  his  youngest  and  only  surviving  brother. 
For  Mr  John  Seth  it  was  a  time  of  very  real  anxiety ; 
for  the  bodily  strength  of  his  elder  brother  proved  less 
than  had  been  anticipated,  and  very  much  less  than  the 
determination  of  his  will.  With  his  gentleness  had  always 
gone  an  unusual  tenacity  of  purpose  ;  and  even  now  he 
was  unwilling  to  miss  any  opportunity  of  seeing  the 
historic  cities  at  which  the  steamer  successively  called. 
At  Copenhagen  he  collapsed  on  the  quay  after  landing, 
and  had  to  be  assisted  up  the  companionway  to  his 
cabin.  Finally,  the  care  and  watchfulness  of  his  brother 
brought  him  safe  home  ;  but  on  his  return  to  The 
Haining  his  strength  began  slowly  to  ebb.  One  of  his 
last  messages,  written  in  pencil,  was  sent  as  a  birthday 
greeting  to  his  oldest  friend,  Mr  Capper,  and  included 
the  two  words,  "  No  pain."  The  end  came  peacefully 
in  the  early  morning  of  September  i  in  the  library  at 
his  beloved  Haining,  and  three  days  later  his  body  was 
laid  to  rest  in  the  city  which  he  also  loved,  and  in 
which  his  greatest  work  as  a  teacher  was  accomplished. 

It  is  too  soon,  even  if  this  were  the  appropriate 
place,  to  assess  the  rank  which  the  books  of  Pringle- 
Pattison  may  finally  hold  among  the  philosophical 
writings  of  his  time.  He  himself  assuredly  made  no 
claim  to  rank  among  the  di  majores  of  philosophy.  He 
was  content,  as  the  title  of  his  chief  book  shows,  to 
identify  his  thinking  closely  with  that  of  his  time,  and 
to  answer  its  questions  in  the  form  which  his  contem- 


158  MEMOIR 

poraries  gave  to  them.  At  times  he  even  seemed  to 
spend  his  strength  in  the  discussion  of  views  set  forth 
by  men  less  in  intellectual  stature  than  himself ;  and 
these  portions  of  his  work  may  be  compared  to  the  vine 
whose  branches  bear  a  nobler  fruit  than  that  of  the 
trees  by  which  they  are  supported,  and  from  which  they 
take  their  direction.  Essentially  he  was  of  those  who, 
in  words  which  he  would  not  have  disowned,  "  serve 
their  own  generation  by  the  will  of  God." 

Yet  the  value  of  his  work  will  assuredly  extend  beyond 
his  own  generation,  and  even  that  of  those  who  learned 
from  him.  It  summarised,  and  in  some  sense  brought 
to  a  close,  a  development  of  two  centuries  in  Scottish 
philosophy  ;  and  it  may  well  prove  to  have  a  vitality 
and  an  interest  for  thinkers  of  generations  still  distant, 
so  that  future  searchers  for  a  sure  basis  of  theistic  belief 
may  turn  to  it  for  light  on  the  problems  of  their  own  day. 

But  one  thing  admits  of  no  dispute — the  service  which 
this  great  teacher  accomplished  by  what  he  was,  not  less 
than  by  what  he  taught.  In  the  words  of  Professor 
Hallett  :  "  His  personal  dignity  was  a  discipline,  his 
interest  a  sufficient  reward,  his  commendation  an  inspira 
tion  to  new  effort,  and  to  those  who  were  fortunate  enough 
to  win  his  friendship — a  gift  not  lightly  bestowed — he 
was  an  unfailing  support  in  illness  and  in  effort,  in  the 
more  dignified  forms  of  social  intercourse  and  in  the 
studious  adventures  of  the  intellectual  life.  As  a  philo 
sopher  his  intellectual  humility  was  only  matched  by 
his  native  acumen  and  scholarly  industry.  Nothing 
would  have  been  easier  than  for  him  to  set  up  for  a  great 
philosopher  ;  for  there  was  nothing  of  the  eclectic  about 
him,  in  spite  of  a  method  of  exposition  suggesting 
eclecticism  to  the  unwary.  He  thought  through  all  his 
convictions,  yielding  nothing  to  their  peremptoriness 
that  was  not  supported  by  their  intellectual  trans 
parency,  and  laboured  to  place  them  in  due  order  in  a 


MEMOIR  159 

consistent  system,  keeping  ever  in  mind  the  necessary 
limitations  of  human  thought  and  the  high  responsi 
bilities  of  his  chosen  vocation." 

He  himself  expressed  the  governing  principles  of  his 
own  work  as  a  teacher  on  the  occasion  already  described 
in  March  1925,  by  saying  that  his  effort  had  not  been  to 
impose  on  his  pupils  dogmatic  solutions  of  his  own  ; 
rather  he  taught  them  first  to  appreciate  the  difficulties 
and  complexities  of  the  questions  raised,  yet  suggested 
in  the  end  that  "  to  think  the  worst  of  the  universe  and 
its  Author  was  not  necessarily  to  come  nearest  the 
truth."  '  Truth,  goodness,  beauty,  love/'  he  concluded, 
"  are  realities  as  well  as  values  ;  and  how  can  we  explain 
their  existence  save  in  a  world  which  is  fundamentally 
spiritual  ?  " 

Sixteen  years  earlier  he  wrote  lines  regarding  his 
friend,  Simon  Somerville  Laurie,  which,  along  with  the 
sentences  just  quoted,  may  well  stand  as  his  final 
message  : — 

We  lay  in  earth  the  weary  heart, 

The  massive  labouring  brain, 
Mindful  how  firm  and  clear  his  faith, 

The  spirit  lives  again. 

Within  some  higher  sphere,  he  taught, 

New  truth  shall  greet  our  view  ; 
If  God  is  God  and  worth  our  trust, 

Death  shall  our  life  renew. 

And  shall  we  say  his  faith  was  vain, 
Friends  round  his  grave  here  met  ? 

For  us  he  lives,  a  Presence  still, 
How  then  should  God  forget  ? 


THE 
BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

Delivered  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh  in  1891 

BY 

A.   SETH  PRINGLE-PATTISON 


[Throughout  the  Lectures,  the  footnotes  in  square  brackets  are  taken 
from  the  Author's  annotated  copy  except  where  otherwise  marked. — ED.] 


LECTURE   I. 

PSYCHOLOGY,    EPISTEMOLOGY    AND    METAPHYSICS. 

IN  what  is  called  in  the  widest  sense  '  philosophical '  dis 
cussion  it  is  tolerably  well  known  by  this  time  that  a 
fruitful  source  of  confusion  and  controversy  has  been 
the  mixing  up  of  psychological  with  strictly  philosophical 
or  metaphysical  questions.  This  is  one  of  the  current 
criticisms  upon  the  English  school  of  thinkers  as  repre 
sented  by  Locke,  Berkeley  and  Hume,  and  their  suc 
cessors  in  the  present  century  like  the  Mills.  It  is  said 
that  when  we  ask  them  for  a  philosophical  theory  of 
knowledge  and  existence,  they  reply  with  an  account  of 
the  growth  of  consciousness  in  the  individual  sentient 
organism.  There  is  a  great  measure  of  truth  in  this 
criticism.  The  fault  of  these  philosophers  lies,  however, 
not  in  their  exclusively  psychological  attitude — for  in 
that  case  their  theories  would  stand  as  psychology,  and 
we  should  look  for  our  philosophy  elsewhere — but  in 
their  unconscious  shifting  from  one  point  of  view  to  the 
other.  They  are  far  from  being  pure  psychologists  ; 
there  is  a  great  deal  of  philosophy  or  theory  of  know 
ledge  in  Locke,  Berkeley  and  Hume.  But  they  speak 
sometimes  from  one  point  of  view,  sometimes  from  the 
other,  without  being  aware  that  the  two  points  of  view 
are  different.  This  criticism,  however — though  it  is 
specially  true  of  English  philosophy — applies  more  or 
less  to  philosophical  writers  in  general,  and  hence  it  is 
encouraging  to  note  that  within  quite  recent  times  a 


164      BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

sense  of  the  need  of  greater  precision  has  shown  itself 
in  the  most  varied  quarters,  English  as  well  as  conti 
nental,  among  empiricists  as  well  as  transcendentalists. 
Strenuous  attempts  have  been  made  to  differentiate  the 
various  questions  embraced  under  the  general  term 
'  philosophy/  and  assign  each  as  a  subject  of  inquiry  to 
a  separate  science  or  discipline. 

In  this  way  there  has  been  constituted  what,  so  far  as 
the  name  goes,  is  a  new  science,  though  the  inquiries 
grouped  under  it  have  formed  part  of  philosophical 
investigation  since  a  very  early  time.  This  is  the  science 
which,  for  the  last  thirty  years  or  so,  the  Germans  have 
come  to  call  distinctively  Erkenntnisstheorie,  or  theory 
of  knowledge.  Theory  of  Knowledge  has  been  the  cir 
cumlocution  largely  adopted  by  English  writers  who 
have  wished  to  enforce  the  distinction  between  these 
inquiries  and  the  investigations  of  psychological  science. 
But  as  the  distinction  has  come  more  to  the  front,  the 
need  of  a  single  word  has  been  felt — were  it  only,  as 
Hamilton  pointed  out  in  the  case  of  psychology,  that 
we  may  be  able  to  form  an  adjective  from  it — and 
accordingly  just  as  psychology  supplanted  the  more 
cumbrous  designations  such  as  science  or  philosophy  of 
mind,  so  the  excellent  and  in  every  way  unobjectionable 
title  of  epistemology  will,  in  all  probability,  permanently 
take  the  place  of  the  less  convenient  designation  "  theory 
of  knowledge." 

But  it  will  be  asked  what  is  the  subject  of  this  new 
science,  or  rather  what  particular  philosophical  inquiries 
are  to  be  isolated  and  grouped  under  it  ?  To  this  it 
may  be  answered  generally  that  epistemology  is  an 
investigation  of  knowledge  as  knowledge,  or,  in  other 
words,  of  the  relation  of  knowledge  to  reality,  of  the 
validity  of  knowledge.  This,  at  least,  is  the  fundamental 
question  to  which  other  epistemological  discussions  are 
subsidiary.  The  precise  bearing  of  this  definition  is 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM       165 

best  seen  by  a  contrast  between  epistemology  and  psy 
chology  in  their  mode  of  dealing  with  the  same  subject- 
matter  ;  for,  in  a  sense,  the  fact  of  knowledge  belongs 
to  psychology  as  much  as  to  epistemology.  This  contrast 
has  been  lucidly  expounded  within  the  last  few  years  by 
several  writers.  But  the  difference  in  point  of  view  is 
very  fairly  stated  by  Locke,  though  he  was  one  of  the 
worst  sinners  in  practically  confounding  what  he  had 
theoretically  distinguished.  The  distinction  between 
psychology  and  epistemology,  indeed,  is  the  distinction 
between  the  Second  Book  of  the  Essay  and  the  Fourth, 
and  this  Locke  explains  in  his  Introduction  as  follows  : 
"  First,  I  shall  inquire  into  the  original  of  those  ideas, 
notions,  or  whatever  else  you  please  to  call  them,  which 
a  man  observes,  and  is  conscious  to  himself  he  has  in 
his  mind ;  and  the  ways  whereby  the  understanding 
comes  to  be  furnished  with  them."  This  is  pure  psy 
chology — what,  he  asks,  are  the  mental  states  which 
constitute  the  individual  mind,  and  into  what  elementary 
facts  may  they  be  analysed — of  what  primitive  facts 
may  the  more  complex  be  the  result  ?  "  Secondly  [he 
proceeds],  I  shall  endeavour  to  show  what  knowledge 
the  understanding  hath  by  those  ideas,  and  the  certainty, 
evidence  and  extent  of  it."  This  is  the  question  of 
epistemology :  What  knowledge  can  I  have  of  the 
world  of  men  and  things,  by  means  of  my  mental 
states  ? 

Psychology,  according  to  Locke's  way  of  putting  it, 
deals  with  '  ideas/  which  he  defines  as  "  the  immediate 
objects  of  the  mind  in  thinking  "  ; l  it  treats  ideas  as 
mental  facts  which  have  an  existence  of  their  own  in 
consciousness.  Epistemology  deals  with  the  '  knowledge  ' 
which  we  reach  by  means  of  these  ideas  or  immediate 

1  Second  Letter  to  the  Bishop  of  Worcester.  So,  again,  Essay, 
Bk.  II.,  c.  8,  8  :  "  Whatsoever  the  mind  perceives  in  itself,  or  is  the 
immediate  object  of  perception,  thought,  or  understanding." 


i66      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

mental  facts.  It  takes  the  ideas  not  as  themselves  bits 
of  fact,  but  as  signs  or  symbols  of  some  further  reality  ; 
it  takes  them,  in  short,  as  ideas  of  things.  Hence  the 
word  '  idea/  taken  even  in  the  wide  sense  in  which  it 
is  used  by  Locke,  is  not  a  good  one  to  employ  in  a 
psychological  reference ;  for  it  inevitably  contains  this 
epistemological  implication,  this  reference  of  the  mental 
state  to  something  beyond  itself.  "  States  of  conscious 
ness/'  as  Mr  Ward  suggests,  would  be  a  more  appro 
priate  and  colourless  designation  for  the  objects  of 
psychological  science.  The  psychologist  deals  with 
psychical  events  merely  as  such ;  the  world  of  conscious 
states  is  the  reality  with  which  alone  he  is  concerned, 
and  each  state  of  consciousness  is  a  real  fact  in  that 
world — a  fact  occurring  at  a  definite  time  and  in  a  definite 
set  of  connections  with  other  psychical  facts.  The  inter 
connections  of  this  factual  world,  the  laws  of  the  happen 
ing  of  psychical  events,  are  what  the  psychologist  has 
to  investigate. 

It  is  only  for  the  psychologist,  however,  that  mental 
states  are  interesting  on  their  own  account,  as  subjective 
realities  or  facts.  To  everyone  else  they  are  interesting 
only  for  what  they  mean,  for  the  knowledge  they  give  us 
of  a  world  beyond  themselves.  Viewed  in  themselves, 
the  mental  states  are,  as  it  were,  only  instrumental ;  by 
them,  as  Locke  says,  the  understanding  hath  knowledge. 
They  are  merely  a  mechanism  by  which  a  world  of  men 
and  things  is  somehow  revealed  to  me.  It  is  only  for 
the  psychologist,  I  say,  that  the  investigation  of  this 
mechanism,  as  a  mechanism,  has  an  interest.  To  all 
the  rest  of  mankind  ideas  or  presentations  are  interesting 
only  for  the  knowledge  they  give  us  of  a  reality  beyond 
themselves.  In  point  of  fact,  we  never  pause  to  con 
sider  them  as  what  they  are  in  themselves — we  treat 
them  consistently  as  significant,  as  ideas  of  something, 
as  representative  or  symbolic  of  a  world  of  facts.  Now 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       167 

it  is  from  this  latter  point  of  view  that  epistemology 
considers  ideas. 

Of  course  this  distinction,  even  the  manner  of  stating 
it,  is  far  from  being  new.  Not  to  go  farther  back,  it  is 
drawn  with  great  clearness  in  the  writings  of  Descartes 
and  his  followers.  In  fact,  considerable  emphasis  is 
laid  upon  it  in  the  Cartesian  philosophy,  and  a  special 
terminology  is  employed  to  designate  it.  "  Ideas,"  says 
Descartes  himself,1  "  may  be  taken  in  so  far  only  as 
they  are  certain  modes  of  consciousness,"  and  so  regarded, 
"  they  all  seem  in  the  same  manner  to  proceed  from 
myself."  That  is  to  say,  they  are  all  subjective  functions 
or  psychical  events.  But  they  may  also  be  considered 
"  as  images,  of  which  one  represents  one  thing  and 
another  a  different."  So  far  as  the  idea  is  taken  simply 
as  an  act  or  function  of  the  mind,  a  subjective  fact, 
it  is  said  by  the  Cartesians  to  have  "  esse  formate  seu 
proprium  "  ;  so  far  as  it  is  taken  in  its  representative 
capacity,  as  standing  for  some  object  thought,  it  is  said 
to  have  an  objective  or  vicarious  being — esse  objectivum 
sive  vicarium.  There  is  a  tendency  in  the  Cartesian 
school  to  appropriate  the  term  '  idea  '  in  the  first  or 
psychological  sense,  and  to  use  '  perception '  in  the 
epistemological  reference.  Perception  is  certainly  a 
term  which  should  be  the  exclusive  property  of  the 
epistemologist ;  and  it  is  satisfactory,  therefore,  to  note 
that  the  most  recent  psychologists  seem  inclined  to 
substitute  for  it  the  term  '  presentation/  But  the  term 
'  idea  '  also,  as  we  have  seen,  belongs  more  appropriately 
to  epistemology,  and  so  pre-eminently,  of  course,  do 
such  terms  as  '  knowledge  '  and  '  cognition/  As  already 
indicated,  the  best  general  psychological  equivalent  is 
states  of  consciousness,  mental  states,  psychical  functions. 

In  accordance  with  what  has  been  said,  Epistemology 
may  be  intelligibly  described  as  dealing  with  the  relation 

1  Third  Meditation. 


168       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

of  knowledge  to  reality.  Of  course,  if  we  take  reality 
in  the  widest  sense,  our  cognitive  states  are  also  part 
of  reality  ;  they  also  are.  The  wildest  fancy  that  flits 
through  the  mind  exists  in  its  own  way,  fills  out  its  own 
moment  of  time  and  takes  its  individual  place  in  the 
fact-continuum  which  constitutes  the  universe.  But,  as 
we  have  seen,  this  aspect  of  mental  facts  may  be  con 
veniently  neglected,  and  hence  reality  in  the  above 
phrase  comes  to  be  used  in  a  narrower  sense.  It  means 
not  necessarily  physical  or  material  realities,  but  realities 
which  have  a  different  fashion  of  existence  from  the 
fleeting  and  evanescent  mode  of  psychical  states — beings 
or  things  which  are  in  some  sense  permanent  and  inde 
pendent,  which  at  all  events  have  a  reality  different  in 
kind  from  that  of  mental  states.  This  reference  of  ideas 
to  a  world  of  reality  beyond  themselves  is  what  is  meant 
when  knowledge  is  contrasted  with  reality,  and  when 
question  is  made  of  the  relation  of  the  one  to  the  other. 
This  way  of  putting  the  epistemological  problem  may 
be  said  to  beg  the  question  at  issue  between  Idealism 
and  Realism — inasmuch  as  the  terminology  is  incom 
patible  with  those  idealistic  theories  which  deny,  or 
seem  to  deny,  the  existence  of  any  such  extra-conscious 
reality  as  is  here  spoken  of.  In  truth,  however,  this  is 
not  so  ;  for  in  any  case  this  dualism  seems  to  exist, 
and  so,  if  not  justified,  it  has  to  be  explained  away. 
Subjective  idealism,  accordingly,  must  have  an  episte- 
mology  of  its  own,  even  if  it  be  only  of  a  negatively 
critical  character.  For  indeed  no  theory  can  deny  the 
contrast  between  the  present  content  of  consciousness 
and  that  which  it  symbolises  or  stands  for.  No  theorist 
takes  the  particular  mental  state  as  independent  and 
self-sufficient ;  he  cannot  avoid  referring  it  beyond 
itself.  But  if  he  is  a  subjective  idealist,  say  like  Mill, 
he  'will  try  to  avoid  the  acknowledgment  that  this 
reference  of  present  consciousness  beyond  itself  carries 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   169 

us  beyond  consciousness  altogether.  He  will  explain  it 
as  a  reference  of  a  particular  mental  state  to  a  permanent 
law  of  connection  between  mental  states,  and  thus 
convey  the  impression  that  the  reality  to  which  the 
subjective  consciousness  refers  is  still  in  a  manner 
within  that  consciousness.  This  does  not  appear  to  me 
to  be  an  adequate  account  of  the  facts,  but  what  I  am 
concerned  to  show  just  now  is  only  that  the  episte- 
mological  question  is  not  determined  out  of  hand  by  the 
way  in  which  it  has  been  defined.  The  essential  episte- 
mological  contrast  is  as  fully  recognised  by  Mill  as  any 
Realist  could  wish  to  see  it.  Take  his  own  words  in 
evidence  :  "  The  conception  I  form  of  the  world  existing 
at  any  moment,  comprises,  along  with  the  sensations  I 
am  feeling,  a  countless  variety  of  possibilities  of  sensa 
tion.  .  .  .  These  various  possibilities  are  the  important 
thing  to  me  in  the  world.  My  present  sensations  are 
generally  of  little  importance,  and  are,  moreover,  fugi 
tive  ;  the  possibilities,  on  the  contrary,  are  permanent, 
which  is  the  character  that  mainly  distinguishes  our 
idea  of  Substance  or  Matter  from  our  notion  of  sensation." 
This  reference  of  the  '  fugitive  '  content  of  consciousness 
to  a  '  permanent/  which  is  somehow  beyond  it  (a  refer 
ence  which  Mill  admits  and  emphasises),  is  just  what 
we  ordinarily  mean  by  knowledge,  and  as  such  it  con 
stitutes  the  problem  of  epistemology.  But  the  unavoid 
able  acknowledgment  of  this  contrast,  of  this  reference, 
does  not  imply  any  decision  as  to  the  nature  of  the 
'  permanent/  or  the  precise  sense  in  which  the  '  beyond  ' 
is  to  be  understood.  It  may  be  Mill's  permanent  possi 
bilities  of  sensation,  it  may  be  the  unconscious  matter 
of  popular  philosophy,  it  may  be  an  infinite  number  of 
monadic  consciousnesses,  or  it  may  be  a  system  of 
divine  or  objective  thought.  These  are  further  questions, 
to  be  determined  partly  by  epistemology,  partly  by 
metaphysics,  but  they  all  equally  presuppose  that 


170   BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

epistemological  dualism  which  can  be  denied  only  by 
a  theory  which  would  be  content  with  the  momentary 
presentations  of  sense,  as  they  come  and  go  in  hopeless 
entanglement  and  disarray.* 

To  recapitulate,  then.  Psychology,  assuming  the  ex 
istence  of  a  subject  or  medium  of  consciousness,  seeks 
to  explain,  mainly  by  the  help  of  association  or  processes 
practically  similar,  how  out  of  the  come-and-go  of  con 
scious  states,  there  are  evolved  such  subjective  facts  as 
perceptions,  the  belief  in  an  independent  real  world  and 
the  idea  of  the  Ego  or  subject  himself.  It  investigates 
how  such  ideas  and  beliefs  come  to  pass,  but  it  does  not 
touch  the  further  question  whether  they  are  well-founded 
or  no.  They  may  be  a  correct  account  of  the  real  state  of 
things,  or  they  may  be  illusions  ;  but  anyway  they  are 
beliefs,  subjective  facts  which  may  be  shown  with 
probability  to  have  arisen  in  a  certain  way.  And  that 
is  enough  for  psychology  which,  so  far  as  it  sticks  to  its 
own  last,  does  not  seek  to  go  beyond  the  inner  world 
of  the  subject.  The  external  world,  so  far  as  psychology 
treats  it,  is  simply  a  complex  presentation  in  conscious 
ness,  a  subjective  object  :  with  the  extraconscious  or 
trans-subjective  psychology  ex  vi  termini  can  have  no 
concern.  Belief  in  a  trans-subjective  world  may,  indeed 
—must,  in  fact — be  treated  by  the  psychologist.  But 
that  belief,  again,  he  treats  simply  as  a  subjective  fact ; 
he  analyses  its  constituents  and  tells  us  the  complex 
elements  of  which  it  is  built  up  ;  he  tells  us  with  great 
precision  what  we  do  believe,  but  so  far  as  he  is  a  pure 
psychologist  he  does  not  attempt  to  tell  us  whether  our 
belief  is  true,  whether  we  have  real  warrant  for  it.  On 
that  point  he  is  dumb. 

If  it  is  objected  that  this  view  of  psychology,  as 
limited  to  the  subjective  world,  is  insufficient,  seeing 
that  in  great  part  of  his  work  the  psychologist  is  bound 
to  assume  the  correlation  of  mind  and  body,  and  the 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   171 

existence  of  an  external  cause  of  impressions,  I  reply 
that,  on  its  physiological  or  experimental  side,  psy 
chology  simply  places  itself  at  the  point  of  view  of  the 
other  sciences.  It  is  now  as  purely  objective  as  it  was 
before  purely  subjective.  It  takes  up  its  position  in 
the  object  from  the  outset,  and  treats  subjective  facts 
themselves  as  objective,  i.e.,  as  mere  appendages  or 
accompaniments  of  the  objective  facts  of  nerve  and 
brain.  Psychology  is  thus  either  purely  subjective  or 
purely  objective x  in  its  standpoint,  according  as  we 
look  at  it.  What  it  does  not  deal  with  is  the  nature  of 
the  relation  between  the  subject  and  the  object,  which 
is  exemplified  in  every  act  of  knowledge. 

Now  it  is  the  essential  function  of  epistemology  to 
deal  with  this  very  relation,  to  investigate  it  on  the  side 
of  its  validity,  its  truth.  With  what  right  do  we  pass 
beyond  our  subjective  states  ?  What  is  the  ground  of 
our  belief  in  an  independent  world  ?  Our  cognitive 
states  appear  to  refer  themselves  to  a  reality  which  we 
know  by  their  means.  Epistemology  does  not,  like 
psychology,  rest  in  the  appearance.  It  seeks  to  deter 
mine  whether  the  appearance  is  true,  and,  if  true,  in  what 
sense  precisely  it  is  to  be  understood.  The  point  on 
which  psychology  is  dumb,  forms  the  central  problem 
of  epistemological  science.  What  is  reality,  the  episte- 
mologist  asks.2  Is  there  any  reality  beyond  the  conscious 
states  themselves  and  their  connections  ?  If  there  is, 
in  what  sense  can  we  be  said  to  know  it  ?  Is  knowledge, 
inference,  or  belief,  the  most  appropriate  word  to  use  in 
the  circumstances  ?  The  fundamental  question  of  ex 
ternal  perception  thus  broadens  out  into  a  general  con 
sideration  of  the  foundations  of  belief.  And,  accordingly, 
the  whole  inquiry  might  be  fitly  enough  so  described  in  a 

1  [But  this  objective  or  natural  science  psychology  neglects  the 
implication  of  a  subject.] 

a  [Rather  the  metaphysician.] 


172      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

more  generalised  fashion — namely,  as  an  inquiry  into 
"  the  foundations  of  belief."  So  it  is  described  by  Mr 
Arthur  Balfour  in  the  sub-title  of  his  Defence  of  Philo 
sophic  Doubt,  a  book  which  may  be  regarded  as  one  of 
the  most  brilliant  of  recent  English  contributions  to 
wards  an  epistemology  or  theory  of  knowledge  in  the 
strict  sense  of  these  terms.  Mr  Balfour  expressly  defines 
his  subject-matter  as  "a.  systematic  account  of  the 
grounds  of  belief  and  disbelief,"  and  he  is  at  pains  in 
his  introductory  chapter  to  distinguish  the  inquiry  most 
carefully  from  psychology,  on  the  one  hand,  so  far  as  that 
investigates  merely  the  growth  and  causes  of  a  belief, 
and  on  the  other  hand  from  metaphysics  or  ontology.1 

1  As  regards  a  name  for  the  inquiry  thus  isolated  and  denned, 
Mr  Balfour  proposes  the  term  Philosophy,  acknowledging  at  the 
same  time  that  this  application  is  not  exactly  sanctioned  by  usage. 
If  it  were  at  all  possible  to  appropriate  the  general  term,  Philosophy, 
in  a  specific  sense,  there  might  be  much  to  say  for  this  innovation. 
Many  arguments  in  its  favour  might  be  drawn  even  from  the  vague 
sense  which  the  term  bears  in  current  usage.  In  modern  times,  and 
within  the  present  century  in  particular,  Philosophy  is  very  frequently 
used  in  the  schools  as  equivalent  to  Epistemology  or  Theory  of 
Knowledge.  But  in  spite  of  this,  it  seems  to  me  hopeless  (and  un 
desirable)  to  cut  ourselves  loose  from  the  tradition  of  more  than  two 
thousand  years,  which  associates  the  term  irrevocably  with  meta 
physical  or  ontological  speculation.  By  metaphysics  or  ontology  I 
mean  some  kind  of  theory  or  no-theory  of  the  ultimate  nature  of 
things.  Such  a  metaphysical  theory  is  that  to  which  all  other  philoso 
phical  inquiries  lead  up — that  in  which  they  culminate — and  it  seems 
to  me  undesirable  to  define  philosophy  in  such  a  way  as  to  exclude 
from  its  scope  what  has  hitherto  been  considered  its  heart  and  soul. 
I  confess,  indeed,  that  if  we  are  to  narrow  the  term  at  all,  I  should 
be  inclined  to  identify  philosophy  rather  with  metaphysics  or  ontology. 
The  claim  on  behalf  of  epistemology,  as  I  take  it,  is  that  it  lays  the 
substructure  ;  it  is  the  necessary  preliminary  alike  of  science  and  of 
metaphysics.  But  it  may  as  fairly  be  argued  on  the  other  side  that 
the  ultimate  or  culminating  science  has  the  best  claim  to  the  time- 
honoured  title.  Happily,  however,  we  are  not  reduced  to  an  aimless 
wrangle  of  this  description,  for  Epistemology  is  just  the  single  term 
we  want.  Philosophy  will  doubtless  remain  in  its  indefmiteness  as  a 
generic  title,  associated  now  more  closely  with  theory  of  knowledge, 
now  more  closely  with  metaphysics ;  while  epistemology  (overlapping 
into  logic),  metaphysics  or  ontology,  and  ethics  (which  as  metaphysic 
of  ethics  is  connected  in  the  most  intimate  way  with  any  ultimate 
theory  of  things) — while  these  three  at  least,  to  mention  no  more  at 
present,  are  covered  by  her  ample  aegis. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       173 

For  on  this  side  also  the  line  requires  to  be  drawn.  If 
epistemology  is  not  to  be  confounded  with  psychology 
on  the  one  hand,  neither  is  it  to  be  identified  with  meta 
physics  on  the  other.  The  prevalent  confusion  in  English 
philosophy  between  the  two  first  has  been  well  exposed 
by  Kantian  and  Hegelian  writers,  but  some  of  them 
have  themselves  fallen  into  a  new  confusion  between 
epistemology  and  metaphysics.  A  considerable  section 
of  my  last  course  of  Balfour  Lectures  l  was  devoted, 
indeed,  to  showing  that  English  Neo-Kantianism,  as  it 
has  come  to  be  called,  seeks  to  establish  metaphysical 
positions  by  arguments  which  are  purely  epistemological, 
and  therefore  unconvincing  when  stretched  beyond  their 
proper  application.  And  in  this  respect  I  have  seen  no 
reason,  during  the  years  that  have  elapsed,  to  change 
the  views  I  then  expressed.  For  it  must  not  be  for 
gotten  that  the  question  which  epistemology  finds 
before  it  is  the  relation  of  the  individual  knower  to  a 
world  of  reality — a  world  whose  very  existence  it  is 
bound  to  treat  at  the  outset  as  problematical.  How, 
or  in  what  sense,  does  the  individual  knower  transcend 
his  own  individual  existence  and  become  aware  of  other 
men  and  things  ?  It  is  this  relatively  simple  and  mani 
festly  preliminary  question  which  epistemology  has  to 
take  up.  Subjective  states  are  plainly  our  data  ;  it  is 
there  we  have  our  foothold,  our  pied  a  terre  ;  but  unless 
we  can  step  beyond  them,  metaphysics  in  any  con 
structive  sense  can  hardly  make  a  beginning.  Episte 
mology,  if  its  results  are  negative,  necessarily  leads  to  a 
thorough-going  scepticism  ;  but  if  its  results  are  positive, 
it  only  clears  the  way  for  metaphysical  construction  or 
hypothesis.  The  mere  fact  that  we  believe  ourselves 
to  have  successfully  made  the  leap  from  the  subjective 
to  a  real  which  is  independent  of  our  subjectivity,  does 
not  reveal  to  us  offhand  the  ultimate  ground  or  essence 

1  Hegelianism  and  Personality. 


174      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

of  that  real.  Epistemology,  in  short,  has  to  do  entirely 
with  the  relation  of  the  subjective  consciousness  to  a 
trans-subjective  world  which  it  knows  or  seems  to 
know.  Metaphysics  has  to  do  with  the  ultimate  nature 
of  the  reality  which  reveals  itself  alike  in  the  conscious 
ness  which  knows  and  the  world  which  is  known.  The 
categories  of  the  one  are  subjective  and  trans-subjective 
(conscious  state  and  real  being)  ;  the  categories  of  the 
other  are  pre-eminently  essence  and  appearance. 

It  is  true  we  use  some  categories  in  both  connections  ; 
but  if  we  look  more  carefully  we  shall  find  that  they 
bear  a  totally  different  sense  in  the  two  cases,  and 
grievous  is  the  damage  that  has  ensued  to  philosophy 
from  the  failure  to  keep  the  two  senses  separate.  The 
much-abused  term  '  phenomenon  '  is  one  of  those  double- 
faced  words  ;  phenomenon  in  a  metaphysical  reference 
is  the  manifestation  or  revelation  of  an  essence  or  in 
dwelling  reality.  When  the  poet  speaks  of  "  a  Presence 
which  disturbs  him  with  the  joy  of  elevated  thoughts, 
a  motion  and  a  spirit  which  impels  all  thinking  things, 
all  objects  of  all  thought,"  he  is  metaphysically  con 
trasting  the  essential  Spirit  with  the  universe  of  intelli 
gences  and  intelligibilia,  which  are  its  manifestation  or 
phenomenon.  Natura  natumta,  in  the  old  phrase,  is  the 
phenomenon  of  natura  natumns.  If,  with  Goethe,  we 
say  that  nature  is  the  garment  of  God  by  which  we  see 
Him,  we  make  nature  the  phenomenon  of  a  divine 
essence.  If  we  take  atoms  and  the  void  as  our  meta 
physical  principia,  then  the  human  consciousness  and 
the  variegated  face  of  nature  as  it  appears  to  that 
consciousness  are  phenomena  of  what  Berkeley  calls  the 
materialist's  "  stupid  thoughtless  somewhat."  If  we  say 
with  the  Hegelians  that  Thought  is  the  ultimate  reality 
which  manifests  itself  alike  in  nature  and  man,  we  are 
engaged  with  the  same  metaphysical  contrast ;  if  we 
say  Will  with  Schopenhauer  or  the  Unconscious  with 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   175 

Hartman,  it  is  still  the  same  —  it  is  a  metaphysical  con 
trast,  a  metaphysical  problem,  which  engages  us.  But 
phenomenon  has  also  come  to  be  used  in  an  epistemolo- 
gical  reference,  and  then  it  means,  and  ought  to  be 
restricted  to  mean,  the  subjective  state  as  contrasted 
with  the  trans-subjective  reality  known  by  means  of 
that  state.  In  that  sense,  familiar  to  us  from  Kant,  to 
say  that  we  know  only  phenomena  means  that  we  know 
only  our  own  conscious  states  and  cannot  know  '  things- 
in-themselves/  that  is  to  say,  the  trans-subjective 
realities  of  which  our  states  are  the  evidence.  Here  it 
is  obvious  the  use  of  the  term  '  phenomenon  '  is  quite  a 
new  one.  Nor  is  the  epistemological  thing-in-itself  to 
be  identified  with  the  metaphysical  essence.  For  even 
if  we  possessed  that  knowledge  of  trans-subjective 
realities  which  Kantianism  denies,  we  should  still  be 
dealing  only  with  phenomena  in  the  metaphysical  sense 
—  with  the  particular  existences  of  the  universe,  not 
with  the  essence  or  universal  of  which  they  are  the 
expression.  When  such  a  serious  ambiguity  is  dis 
covered  lurking  in  a  term  which  is  so  freely  bandied 
about  as  '  phenomena/  it  may  well  be  doubted  whether 
the  controversialists  are  always  clear  as  to  the  sense  in 
which  they  mean  it  to  be  taken.1 

But,  indeed,  the  time-honoured  title  of  Idealism  itself 
covers  a  double  entendre  of  a  similar  description,  accord 
ing  as  it  is  used  metaphysically  or  epistemologically. 
Metaphysically,  Idealism  is  opposed  most  ordinarily 
to  Materialism  ;  in  the  widest  sense  it  is  the  opposite 
of  what  may  be  called  the  mechanical  and  atheistic 
view  of  the  universe,  whatever  special  form  that 


1  A  fuller  analysis  of  the  use  of  the  term  '  phenomena  '  in  Kantian 
and  positivistic  thought  would  bring  some  of  these  inconsistencies 
instructively  to  light.  For  the  plausibility  of  the  quasi-scientific 
agnosticism  which  is  so  widely  spread  in  our  periodicals  and  popular 
philosophy  depends  in  great  part  on  a  systematic  confusion  between 
the  two  different  senses  of  the  word. 


176      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

take.  Is  self-conscious  thought  with  its  ideal  ends — the 
True,  the  Beautiful  and  the  Good — the  self-realising 
End  that  works  in  changes  and  makes  it  Evolution  ?  or 
are  these  but  the  casual  outcome  of  a  mechanical  system 
—a  system  in  its  ultimate  essence  indifferent  to  the 
results  which  in  its  gyrations  it  has  unwittingly  created 
and  will  as  unwittingly  destroy  ?  Is  thought  or  matter 
the  prius  ?  Is  the  ultimate  essence  and  cause  of  all 
things  only  "  dust  that  rises  up,  and  is  lightly  laid  again  " ; 
or  is  it  the  Eternal  Love  of  Dante's  Vision— "  the  love 
that  moves  the  sun  and  the  other  stars  "  ?  That  is  the 
fundamental  metaphysical  antithesis.  If  we  embrace 
the  one  alternative,  however  we  may  clothe  it  in  detail, 
we  recognise  the  universe  as  our  home,  and  we  may 
have  a  religion  ;  if  we  embrace  the  other,  then  the 
spirit  of  man  is  indeed  homeless  in  an  alien  world.  In 
the  plain,  impressive  words  of  Marcus  Aurelius — "the 
universe  is  either  a  confusion  and  a  dispersion,  or  it  is 
unity  and  order  and  providence.  If  it  is  the  former, 
why  do  I  care  about  anything  else  than  how  I  shall  at 
last  become  earth  ?  But  if  the  other  supposition  is 
true,  I  venerate,  and  I  am  firm  and  I  trust  in  Him  who 
governs."  Marcus  Aurelius  expresses  the  difference  from 
the  religious  or  practical  side  ;  from  the  speculative 
side  the  difference  is,  as  I  have  said,  a  metaphysical 
one,  and  all  the  theories  which  support  the  latter  alter 
native  may  be  embraced  under  the  generic  name  of 
Idealism. 

Quite  distinct  from  this  metaphysical  Idealism,  how 
ever,  is  the  epistemological  Idealism  which  is  opposed, 
not  to  Materialism,  but  to  Realism.  Here  the  question 
at  issue  is  not  the  problem  of  the  ultimate  constitution 
of  the  universe  ;  it  is  the  question  of  the  theory  of 
knowledge — in  its  most  obvious  and  easy  form — the 
question  of  the  external  world  and  the  nature  of  the 
existence  we  are  prepared  to  assign  to  it.  Has  it  any 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       177 

existence  beyond  the  minds  of  the  conscious  beings  who 
perceive  it,  or  is  per  dpi  its  whole  esse  ?  Does  the  actual 
and  possible  experience  of  conscious  beings  constitute 
an  exhaustive  account  of  its  modus  essendi  ?  Is  it  a 
mere  phenomenon,  a  mental  appearance,  or  does  it 
possess  in  some  sense  an  extra-conscious  reality  of  its 
own  ?  The  question  might  be  more  exactly  formulated, 
for  as  soon  as  we  essay  a  solution  we  find  that  it  involves 
not  only  the  existence  of  what  we  usually  call  the 
external  world,  but  all  existence  whatever  beyond  my 
conscious  states.  It  includes,  therefore,  the  validity  of 
my  belief  in  the  existence  of  other  conscious  beings. 
But  the  question  itself  and  its  details  are  not  at  present 
before  us  :  we  are  not  called  upon  at  this  stage  to  do 
more  than  indicate  its  general  nature.  It  is  obvious 
that  we  are  here  in  the  presence  of  a  set  of  problems  of  a 
widely  different  range  and  import  from  the  metaphysical 
problem  indicated  a  minute  or  two  ago.  We  are  dealing 
with  the  preliminary  question  of  the  extent  and  validity 
of  knowledge — in  a  word,  with  epistemology,  not  with 
metaphysics  or  ontology.  It  is  equally  obvious  that 
epistemological  Idealism  does  not  coincide  with  the 
metaphysical  Idealism  sketched  above.  Berkeley  is 
usually  classed  as  a  subjective  Idealist  in  the  epistemolo 
gical  sense ;  and  if  we  accept  this  classification,  we 
might  say  that  in  his  case  the  two  senses  of  Idealism 
happen  to  fit  the  same  person.  But  Berkeley  is  NOT  a 
consistent  subjective  idealist :  he  is  only  an  imma- 
terialist.  He  believes  in  the  real  trans-subjective  ex 
istence  of  other  finite  spirits,  and  of  God  the  infinite 
Spirit,  and  it  is  his  epistemological  Realism  in  these 
respects  that  enables  him  to  reach  his  metaphysical 
Idealism — his  conviction  of  order  and  reason  at  the 
heart  of  things.  Consistent  epistemological  idealism 
must  be  Solipsism  at  the  best ;  indeed,  it  is  Hume, 
not  Berkeley,  that  is  in  this  sense  an  idealist  of  the 

M 


178       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

purest  water,  and  Hume  is  not  so  much  as  a  Solipsist. 
It  might  easily  be  shown  that  epistemological  Idealism 
inevitably  conducts  us  in  consistency  to  scepticism  of 
the  Humian  or  an  essentially  similar  type.  Where  a 
so-called  Idealism  fails  to  reach  this  goal,  it  is  in  virtue 
of  the  realistic  elements  which  it  inconsistently  adopts 
into  its  system.  Such  a  line  of  argument  would  form  a 
convincing  proof  from  history  of  the  distinction  on  which 
I  am  insisting  between  epistemology  and  metaphysics. 
For  scepticism  is,  of  course,  so  far  from  being  allied  to 
metaphysical  Idealism  that  it  would  rather  require  to 
be  bracketed  with  materialism.  Though,  of  course,  not 
dogmatic  like  the  latter,  it  ranks  with  it  as  a  philos 
ophy  of  despair.  If  epistemological  Idealism  is  thus 
twin  brother  of  Scepticism,  it  is  plain,  on  the  other 
hand,  from  what  I  have  said,  that  a  thinker  may  be, 
epistemologically,  a  strenuous  Realist,  and  at  the  same 
time  an  Idealist  in  the  broad  metaphysical  sense  of  the 
term.  He  is  such  an  Idealist  if  he  recognises  that  all 
the  real  individuals  whose  trans-subjective  existence  he 
maintains  are  "  moments  in  the  being  "  of  an  intelli 
gently  directed  Life.  Indeed,  as  has  been  hinted,  it  is 
only  in  virtue  of  epistemological  Realism  that  we  can 
avoid  Scepticism  and  so  much  as  begin  our  journey 
towards  metaphysical  Idealism. 

It  follows,  therefore,  that  nothing  can  be  more  essential 
to  clear  thinking  than  to  keep  these  two  sets  of  questions 
apart ;  yet  I  am  afraid  that  they  are  constantly  inter 
changed.  In  particular  it  seems  to  me  that  this  is  the 
case  with  many  of  the  English  thinkers,  who  profess  a 
general  allegiance  to  Kant  or  Hegel.  The  English  neo- 
Hegelians  convey  the  impression  that  in  order  to  reach 
a  metaphysical,  or,  as  they  call  it,  a  spiritual,  Idealism, 
it  is  at  least  necessary  to  deny  the  reality  of  '  things-in- 
themselves/  Metaphysically  they  mean  by  this,  as  I 
perfectly  well  understand,  that  the  external  world  is 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       179 

not  to  be  taken  as  an  independent  fact,  existing,  so  to 
speak,  on  its  own  account,  and  having  only  accidental 
relations  with  the  rest  of  the  universe.    The  universe  is 
once  for  all  a  whole,  and  the  external  world,  as  the 
Hegelians  put  it,  is  essentially  related  to  intelligence  ; 
in  other  words,  it  is  not  a  brute  fact  existing  outside 
the  sweep  of  the  divine  life  and  its  intelligent  ends.    In 
all  this  I  most  heartily  agree  with  the  neo-Hegelians. 
Whether  we  can  absolutely  prove  so  much  or  no,  it  is 
certain  that  so  much  is  involved  in  every  constructive 
system  of  metaphysics  ;   and  certainly  we  cannot  believe 
less  without  lapsing  into  scepticism.     If  we  put  this 
metaphysical  sense  upon  the  words,  then  I  most  cer 
tainly  believe,  in  Berkeley's  phrase,  that  "  the  absolute 
existence   of  unthinking   things   are   words   without   a 
meaning."    There  is  no  metaphysical  thing-in-itself,  no 
res  completa,  except  the  universe  regarded  as  a  self- 
existent    whole.      The    thinker    who    leaves    anything 
outside  in  this  way  makes  confession  of  speculative  bank 
ruptcy.     But  though  the  unrelated  thing-in-itself  can 
have   no   place   in   metaphysics,   it   is   quite   otherwise 
with  the  epistemological  thing-in-itself,   if  we  are  to 
designate   trans-subjective    reality   by   this   ill-omened 
phrase.     The  existence  of  the  latter  must  be  asserted 
as  strenuously  as  that  of  the  former  must  be  denied. 
All  my  fellow-men  are  things-in-themselves  to  me  in  the 
epistemological  sense — extra-conscious  realities — and  I 
fail  to  see  how  we  can  draw  any  hard  and  fast  line  at 
them. 

Hence,  as  I  have  argued  on  a  previous  occasion,  any 
thing  which  tends  to  confuse  the  two  questions  is  to  be 
deprecated  :  we  cannot  deal  with  the  two  in  the  same 
breath  without  confusing  the  issues.  Our  epistemological 
premises  will  not  bear  our  metaphysical  conclusion. 
Epistemology  starts,  and  must  start,  from  the  individual 
human  consciousness — the  only  consciousness  known  to 


i8o       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

us.  If,  however,  it  be  pointed  out  to  a  neo-Hegelian 
that  the  epistemological  assertions  which  he  makes  as 
to  the  relation  of  knower  and  known  are  plainly  unten 
able  as  applied  to  this  consciousness,  we  are  met  by  the 
rejoinder  that  they  are  not  meant  to  be  understood  of 
any  subjective  or  individual  consciousness,  but  of  a 
so-called  universal  or  divine  consciousness.  It  is  not 
my  purpose  at  this  stage  to  discuss  the  satisfactoriness 
of  this  hypothetical  divine  epistemology  as  a  metaphysic 
of  existence,  but  I  would  point  out  that  by  this  procedure, 
illegitimate  as  I  consider  it,  the  real  question  of  episte 
mology  is  burked.  That  question  is  very  fairly  put  by 
Professor  Huxley  in  a  page  of  his  little  book  on  Hume. 
In  pursuance  of  a  favourite  line  of  thought,  he  is  skil 
fully  balancing  Idealism  and  Materialism  against  one 
another  in  such  a  way  as  to  leave  both  problematical, 
and  in  stating  the  case  in  favour  of  what  he  calls  Idealism, 
he  uses  the  following  expression  :  "  For  any  demon 
stration  that  can  be  given  to  the  contrary  effect,  the 
'  collection  of  perceptions  '  which  makes  up  my  con 
sciousness  may  be  an  orderly  phantasmagoria  generated 
by  the  Ego,  unfolding  its  successive  scenes  on  the  back 
ground  of  the  abyss  of  nothingness."  l  With  Professor 
Huxley's  own  view  we  have  nothing  to  do  here,  but 
simply  with  the  statement  quoted,  namely,  that  there 
is  no  logically  coercive  proof  of  any  real  existence 
beyond  the  subjective  consciousness.  Idealism  is  used 
by  Professor  Huxley  in  its  epistemological  sense,  and  is 
equivalent  with  him  to  Solipsism.  His  position  amounts 
to  this  :  that  reason  does  not  force  us  to  go  beyond  the 
circle  of  our  own  consciousness  :  all  that  is  may  be  a 
skilfully  woven  system  of  my  individual  presentations 
and  representations.  This  is  the  true  question  of  episte 
mology  ;  that,  at  least,  which  it  has  first  to  settle.  But 
to  judge  from  the  writings  of  the  neo-Kantians  and 

1  Hume  (English  Men  of  Letters),  pp.  80-8 1. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   181 

Hegelians,  one  would  hardly  gather  that  individual 
knowers  existed  at  all.  The  subjective  consciousness 
seems  suppressed ;  they  often  speak  as  if  knowledge 
were  not  a  subjective  process  at  all.  In  Hegel  himself, 
just  for  this  reason,  there  is  no  epistemology ;  we  hear 
nothing  of  individuals,  but  only  of  the  universal  process 
in  which  objective  thought  comes  to  consciousness  of 
itself. 

Hegelianism,  in  fact,  offers  an  eminent  example  of  the 
confusion  between  Epistemology  and  Metaphysics  on 
which  I  am  dwelling.  With  Hegel  the  essence  of  the 
universe  is  thought  here  in  the  subject  and  thought 
there  in  the  object ;  and  there  is  some  temptation 
therefore  to  think  that  this  metaphysical  identity 
absolves  us  from  the  epistemological  inquiry.  But 
that  is  not  the  case.  However  much  the  objective  world 
and  the  individual  knower  may  be  identical  in  essence, 
the  objective  thought  which  he  recognises  is  still  trans- 
subjective  to  the  individual  knower,  just  as  much 
beyond  his  individual  consciousness,  as  if  it  were  the 
crass  matter  of  the  Natural  Dualist ;  and  the  question 
how  we  reach  this  trans-subjective,  how  we  transcend 
the  individual  consciousness,  has  still  to  be  faced.  The 
epistemological  dualism,  in  other  words,  remains  in  full 
force,  and  only  if  that  is  satisfactorily  surmounted,  can 
we  have  any  guarantee  for  our  metaphysical  monism, 
for  the  asserted  identity  of  thought  and  being.  Far  be 
it  from  me  to  say,  however,  that  Hegel  and  the  neo- 
Hegelians  are  the  only  sinners  in  this  respect.  If  Hegel 
swamps  Epistemology  in  Metaphysics,  the  Realism  of 
Scottish  philosophy  often  errs  as  much  in  an  opposite 
direction.  In  answer  to  Hume  it  insists  (most  rightly, 
as  I  think,  in  principle,  though  not  always  happily  in 
point  of  expression)  upon  an  epistemological  dualism 
of  subject  and  object  as  the  fundamental  fact  of  know 
ledge.  But  when  it  proceeds  forthwith  to  treat  this 


182       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

epistemological  dualism  of  knowledge  and  reality  as  a 
metaphysical  dualism  between  mind  and  matter,  between 
two  generically  different  substances,  it  falls  at  once  into 
most  unphilosophical  crudities.  Dualism  in  knowledge 
is  no  more  a  proof  of  metaphysical  heterogeneity  than 
identity  of  metaphysical  essence  in  Hegel's  sense  can  be 
taken  as  eliminating  the  epistemological  problem. 

The  problem  of  knowledge  and  the  Real,  then,  is  the 
question  which  Epistemology  has  to  face.  As  stated  by 
Professor  Huxley,  and  indeed  as  stated  in  any  form,  it  is 
apt  to  appear  fantastical  and  frivolous  to  the  common- 
sense  mind ;  but  if  it  were  so,  it  would  hardly  have 
formed  the  central  problem  of  modern  philosophy.  I 
am  convinced  at  least  that  unless  it  is  probed  to  the 
bottom,  we  can  have  no  clearness  as  to  the  foundations 
of  knowledge  and  belief ;  and  without  such  clearness  we 
can  hardly  expect  to  make  satisfactory  progress  in 
philosophy. 


LECTURE   II. 

THE   PROBLEM   OF   EPISTEMOLOGY. 

THE  problem  of  epistemology  arises  from  the  very 
nature  of  knowledge.  Knowledge  implies  a  reference 
to  that  which  is  known,  and  which  is  therefore  to  be 
distinguished  from  the  knowledge  itself  considered  sub 
jectively  as  an  act  or  process  of  the  being  who  knows. 
What  is  known,  the  object  of  knowledge,  may  be  styled 
most  generally  Reality.  Knowledge  bears  in  its  heart, 
in  its  very  notion,  this  reference  to  a  reality  distinct 
from  itself.  No  idealist  will  deny,  at  all  events,  that 
knowledge  seems  to  us  to  carry  this  reference  with  it. 
Hume  himself  speaks  of  it  as  "  the  universal  and  primary 
opinion  of  all  men/'  it  is  "a  natural  instinct  or  pre 
supposition,"  1  so  that  if  its  validity  is  not  accepted, 
the  illusion  will  at  least  require  explanation.  Know 
ledge  as  knowledge  points  beyond  itself  to  a  reality 
whose  representation  or  symbol  it  is.  This  holds  true, 
as  a  careful  analysis  would  show,  even  in  what  is  called 
self-knowledge,  the  reflective  knowledge  of  one's  own 
states,  in  which  the  act  of  knowledge  and  the  object 
known  might  seem  to  fall  together.  But,  without  in 
sisting  at  the  outset  on  this  refinement,  let  us  take  the 
general  or  typical  case,  in  which  the  knowledge  is  know 
ledge  of  beings  other  than  ourselves,  a  knowledge  of  the 
facts  of  the  world  around  us.  Here  the  very  function  of 
knowledge,  as  ordinarily  understood,  is  to  disclose  to 

1  Enquiry,  section  12. 


184      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

one  being  the  nature  of  beings  and  things  with  which  he 
is  in  relation,  but  which  are  different  ;  i.e.,  numerically 
and  existentially  distinct  from  himself.  One  being  or 
individual  cannot  go  out  of  himself,  so  far  as  his  being 
or  existence  is  concerned.  He  is  and  remains  himself  so 
long  as  he  exists  at  all.  But  though  every  individual, 
qua  existent,  remains  thus  anchored  upon  himself— 
rooted  to  his  own  centre,  to  the  locus,  as  it  were,  assigned 
him  in  the  process  of  the  universal  life — yet  by  the 
influence  of  other  realities  upon  him  and  the  response 
of  his  own  being  to  these  influences — in  other  words, 
by  means  of  his  own  subjective  states,  and  without 
therefore  performing  the  impossible  feat  of  stepping  out 
of  himself — he  becomes  aware  of  other  existences,  or, 
as  we  say,  he  comes  to  know  that  other  beings  or  things 
exist  besides  himself,  and  also  what  their  nature  is. 
This  knowledge,  as  knowledge,  is  necessarily  subjective,'1 
for  no  being  can  be  present  in  existence  within  another 
being.  In  existence  things  necessarily  remain  apart  or 
distinct :  we  can  know  things,  therefore,  only  by  report, 
only  by  their  effect  upon  us. 

That,  then,  is  the  problem  or  crux  of  knowledge  which 
has  vexed  philosophers.  Knowledge  is  necessarily  sub 
jective,  so  far  as  it  is  state  or  process  of  the  knowing 
being ;  but  it  as  necessarily  involves  an  objective  refer 
ence.  If  it  is  not  an  illusion  altogether,  it  is  a  knowledge 
of  realities  which  are  trans-subjective  or  extra-conscious  ; 
i.e.,  which  exist  beyond  and  independently  of  the  con 
sciousness  of  the  individual  knowing  them.  But  all 
through  the  modern  period  philosophers  have  been 
turning  the  subjectivity  of  knowledge  against  its  objec 
tivity,  and  in  the  last  resort  converting  the  very  notion 
of  knowledge  into  an  argument  against  the  possibility 
of  knowledge.  If  they  have  not  gone  to  this  extreme 
length,  the  possibility  of  real  knowledge  has  been  an 

1  [Italics  in  the  author's  annotated  copy.] 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       185 

ever  present  difficulty  to  modern  thought — a  difficulty 
that  has  seemed  to  grow  greater  instead  of  less  in  the 
hands  of  successive  thinkers,  till  it  may  be  said  since 
the  time  of  Hume  and  Kant  to  have  been  the  main 
subject  of  philosophical  debate.  Now,  it  can  scarcely 
be  doubted  that  in  this  respect  philosophy  has  largely 
created  the  difficulties  which  it  finds  so  hard  to  surmount, 
but  at  the  same  time  we  cannot  wonder  at  or  regret  the 
time  and  labour  expended  on  this  question  ;  for  it  is 
the  business  of  philosophy  to  doubt  wherever  doubt  is 
possible,  and  to  probe  its  own  doubts  to  the  bottom, 
in  order  to  discover  whether  they  are  really  fatal  to  the 
faith  we  repose  in  the  act  of  knowledge.  A  theory  of 
knowledge  or  a  philosophy  of  belief  is  a  necessary  pre 
liminary  of  all  scientific  and  metaphysical  inquiry. 

In  endeavouring  to  establish  such  a  theory,  we  must 
start  from  the  ordinary  consciousness.  What  does  the 
plain  man  believe  about  perception  and  the  real  world 
of  physical  things  ?  He  believes  that  his  senses,  especially 
sight  and  touch,  put  him  in  immediate  relation  with 
real  things.  He  has  only  to  open  his  eyes  or  to  stretch 
out  his  hand,  and  he  is  face  to  face  or  in  actual  contact 
with  the  realities  themselves.  The  objects  which  he 
perceives  are  not  dependent  upon  his  perceiving  them, 
which  is  a  purely  accidental  fact  both  in  their  life- 
history  and  in  his.  Just  as  he  himself  existed  as  a  real 
being  before  the  act  of  perception,  so  they  existed  inde 
pendently  before  he  turned  his  eyes  upon  them,  and 
they  continue  to  exist  after  his  vision  is  averted.  He 
believes,  in  short,  that  he  sees  and  touches  the  real 
thing  as  that  exists  in  itself  independent  of  perception. 
He  draws  no  distinction  between  the  existence  of  the 
thing  in  itself  and  its  existence  for  him  in  the  moment 
of  perception.  The  appearance  is  the  reality.  '  The 
vulgar,"  as  Hume  says,  "  confound  perceptions  and 
objects,  and  attribute  a  distinct  continued  existence  to 


i86      BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

the  very  things  they  feel  or  see."  1  Tis  certain,"  he 
says  again,  "  that  almost  all  mankind,  and  even  philo 
sophers  themselves,  for  the  greatest  part  of  their  lives, 
take  their  perceptions  to  be  their  only  objects,  and 
suppose  that  the  very  being,  which  is  intimately  present 
to  the  mind,  is  the  real  body  or  material  existence.  'Tis 
also  certain  that  this  very  perception  or  object  is  sup 
posed  to  have  a  continued  uninterrupted  being,  and 
neither  to  be  annihilated  by  our  absence  nor  to  be 
brought  into  existence  by  our  presence."  2 

No  doubt  this  is,  as  Hume  says,  the  belief  of  "  the 
vulgar  "  ;  it  is  what  Mr  Spencer  calls  Crude,  and  what 
other  writers  call  naive  or  uncritical,  Realism.  As  such, 
it  contains  much  that  is  untenable,  and  much  that 
requires  more  careful  sifting  and  definition.  But  what 
we  have  to  note  is  that  it  is  a  primary,  instinctive  and 
irresistible  belief  of  all  mankind,  nay  of  the  whole  animal 
creation.  Hume  himself  characterises  Realism  as  "  a 
natural  instinct  or  prepossession  "  which  operates  "  with 
out  any  reasoning  or  even  almost  before  the  use  of 
reason." 3  Even  the  sceptic,  he  says  again,  "  must 
assent  to  the  principle  concerning  the  existence  of 
body,  though  he  cannot  pretend  by  any  arguments  of 
philosophy  to  maintain  its  veracity.  Nature  has  not 
left  this  to  his  choice,  and  has  doubtless  esteemed  it 
an  affair  of  too  great  importance  to  be  trusted  to  our 
uncertain  reasons  and  speculations." 4  It  may  be 
matter  for  consideration  at  a  later  stage  whether  the 
mere  fact  of  this  universal,  primary  and  ineradicable 
belief  is  not  itself  an  element  in  the  problem ;  except 
on  the  hypothesis  of  universal  irrationality  may  it  not 
be  argued  that  the  provision  of  nature  in  this  respect 
is  hardly  likely  to  be  a  carefully  organised  deception  ? 

1  Treatise,  Part  IV.  section  2. 

2  Ibid. 

3  Enquiry,  section  12. 

4  Treatise,  Part  IV.  section  2. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       187 

But  here  we  are  merely  concerned  with  the  fact  of  what 
Mr  Spencer  calls  the  priority  of  Realism.  It  cannot  be 
too  strongly  insisted  that  in  this  respect  Realism  holds 
the  field.  As  Mr  Spencer  puts  it,  "I  see  no  alternative 
but  to  affirm  that  the  thing  primarily  known,  is  not 
that  a  sensation  has  been  experienced,  but  that  there 
exists  an  outer  object/' 1  Mr  Spencer's  position  here  is 
not  essentially  different  from  that  of  Reid  when  he 
insists  in  opposition  to  Hume  that  we  do  not  start 
with  ideas  or,  as  Hume  calls  them,  perceptions — unre 
lated  mental  states — but  with  judgments.  Judgment, 
he  argues,  is  the  primitive  act  of  mind  and  a  knowledge 
of  sensations  per  se  is  only  reached  at  a  much  later  stage 
"  by  resolving  and  analysing  a  natural  and  original 
judgment."  As  I  put  it  on  a  previous  occasion,  "  we 
do  not  begin  by  studying  the  contents  of  our  own  minds 
and  afterwards  proceed  by  inference  to  realities  beyond. 
We  are  never  restricted  to  our  own  ideas,  as  ideas  ; 
from  the  first  dawn  of  knowledge  we  treat  the  subjective 
excitation  as  the  symbol  or  revealer  to  us  of  a  real 
world."2 

Mr  Spencer,  in  the  chapter  from  which  I  have  quoted,3 
gives  an  admirable  exposure  of  the  fallacy  which  under 
lies  the  opposite  view.  "  The  error  has  been  in  con 
founding  two  quite  distinct  things — having  a  sensation, 
and  being  conscious  of  having  a  sensation."  Certainly, 
sensations  must  be  given  as  the  conditions  of  perception 
or  knowledge ;  they  are  unquestionably  the  immediate 
data  upon  which  the  perceptive  judgment  reposes.  Mr 
Spencer,  it  is  true,  guided  by  his  idea  of  evolution, 
projects  his  imagination  into  "  the  dark  backward  and 
abysm  of  time  "  and  seems  to  teach  that  "  the  simple 
consciousness  of  sensation,  uncomplicated  by  any  con- 

1  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  ii.  p.  369. 

2  Scottish  Philosophy,  p.  103  (2nd  ed.).     [In  the  4th  ed.  (p.  102), 
the  phrase  "  as  ideas  "  is  altered  to  "  as  mental  states." — ED.] 

3  Principles  of  Psychology,  Part  VII.  Ch.  6. 


188      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

sciousness  of  subject  or  object,  is  primordial/'  and  that, 
as  he  puts  it,  "  through  immeasurably  long  and  complex 
differentiations  and  integrations  of  such  primordial 
sensations  and  derived  ideas,  there  develops  a  con 
sciousness  of  self  and  a  correlative  not-self."  But,  as 
he  adds,  "it  is  one  thing  to  say  that  in  such  a  creature 
the  sensations  are  the  things  originally  given,  and  it  is 
quite  another  thing  to  say  these  sensations  can  be  known 
as  sensations  by  such  a  creature."  Such  an  argument 
"  identifies  two  things  which  are  at  the  very  opposite 
extremes  of  the  process  of  mental  evolution."  It  is,  in 
fact,  only  the  psychologist  who  in  his  reflective  analysis 
is  conscious  of  sensations  as  sensations  distinguished 
from  and  referred  to  their  external  causes.  And  we 
have  here  an  example  of  what  Professor  James  has 
dubbed  "  the  psychologist's  fallacy  par  excellence  " — 
the  confusion  by  the  psychologist  of  his  own  standpoint 
with  that  of  the  mental  fact  about  which  he  is  making 
his  report.  Mr  Spencer  lays  his  finger  most  effectively 
upon  the  fallacy  in  the  present  case.  But  for  myself, 
I  question  whether  he  does  not  go  too  far  in  admitting 
an  undifferentiated  sensuous  consciousness  as  the  prim 
ordial  fact  in  the  evolutionary  process.  It  is  in  vain 
that  we  project  our  imaginations  towards  such  a  hypo 
thetical  beginning  :  it  has  nothing  in  common  with  what 
we  understand  by  knowledge,  and  is  therefore  perfectly 
unrealisable  by  us.  Being  thus  totally  heterogeneous, 
it  cannot  form  a  step  on  the  road  to  knowledge  :  I  mean 
that  it  does  not  in  any  sense  pave  the  way  for  it  or 
render  the  emergence  of  cognition  easier  to  conceive. 
Whether  we  interpolate  this  hypothetical  sensuous  con 
sciousness  as  a  time-prius  or  not,  the  appearance  of 
perception  or  cognitive  consciousness — the  conscious 
ness  we  know — remains  equally  an  unexplained  begin 
ning,  an  absolute  fjLtrdftaa-LS  et9  dXXo  76^09. 

It  is  not  an  essential  point  in  our  present  argument, 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       189 

but  I  am  disposed  to  question  whether  any  animal  con 
sciousness  can  be  fairly  described  as  a  "  simple  con 
sciousness  of  sensation  "  — that  is  to  say,  a  state  of  pure 
internality,  of  diffused  inward  feeling,  without  a  ger 
minal  consciousness  of  distinction  between  the  feeling 
self  and  its  surroundings.  There  is  no  question  here  of 
the  developed  or  reflective1  consciousness  of  Ego  and 
non-Ego,  but  only  of  that  animal  awareness  of  objective 
facts  which  is  seen  in  reaction  upon  stimuli  and  in 
purposive  adaptation  of  act  to  circumstance.  It  is  in 
action  that  we  have  the  surest  clue  to  the  early  stages 
of  the  animal  and  the  human  consciousness.  Knowledge 
in  such  creatures  exists  simply  in  a  practical  reference. 
Consciousness  would  be  a  useless  luxury  unless  as  put 
ting  them  in  relation  to  the  surrounding  world  and 
enabling  them  to  adapt  their  actions  to  its  varying 
stimuli.  In  point  of  fact,  this  practical  consciousness, 
so  far  as  we  can  judge,  accompanies  animal  life  from 
the  outset.  At  least  we  cannot  even  imagine  a  con 
sciousness  without  the  objective  reference — i.e.,  without 
a  felt  distinction  between  the  feeling  subject  and  an 
object  which  it  feels — something  different,  of  whose 
presence  to  it  it  is  aware.  Once  more  let  it  be  repeated, 
we  are  not  speaking  of  the  reflective  realisation  of  those 
distinctions  which  comes  so  much  later — which  comes 
to  the  non-human  animal  not  at  all,  and  to  human 
beings  only  intermittently ;  we  are  speaking  of  the 
instinctive  or  direct  consciousness  which  all  living 
creatures  possess  (in  greater  or  less  degree)  for  the 
practical  ends  of  living,  to  enable  them  to  respond  to 
external  stimulus  and  to  adapt  themselves  to  their 
surroundings.  Put  on  this  broad  ground,  it  may  be 
said  that  the  reaction  of  the  sensitive  organism  is  the 
practical  recognition  of  an  independent  object — it  is 
the  first  or  earliest  form  which  that  recognition  takes. 

1  ["reflected"  in  the  original. — ED.] 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

Further,  there  seems  no  reason  to  doubt  that  it  is  the 
contrast  of  activity  and  passivity — of  resistance  en 
countered  and  instinctive  effort  put  forth  against  the 
resistance,  to  which  may  be  added  the  contrast  of  want 
and  satisfaction,  of  restless  craving  and  the  stilling  of 
appetite  by  its  appropriate  gratification — it  is  these 
contrasts  which  awaken  and  intensify  the  distinction 
between  the  sensitive  subject  and  objects  independent 
of  itself.  The  infant  whose  pains  of  deprivation  are 
ended  by  the  presentation  of  the  mother's  breast,  the 
snail  which  puts  forth  its  horns  and  comes  in  contact 
with  an  object  in  its  path,1  are  alike  in  a  fair  way  towards 
realising  the  existence  of  independent  objects.  It  may 
be  taken  as  pretty  generally  acknowledged  that  the 
consciousness  of  independent  externality  is  given  chiefly 
in  the  sense  of  effort  and  the  phenomena  of  resisted 
energy.  Here  we  see  the  category  of  causality,  as  it 
were,  alive  before  us  in  instinctive  action.  Hence,  as 
Mr  Spencer  says,  "  the  root-conception  of  existence 
beyond  consciousness  becomes  that  of  resistance  plus 
some  force  which  the  resistance  measures/' 2  Of  such 
a  simple  quasi-reflex  character  are  the  experiences  which 
"  yield  subject  and  object  as  independent  existences."  3 
We  do  not  require  to  go  for  them  to  the  rational  con 
sciousness  of  man.  In  reacting  upon  a  stimulus,  the 
sensitive  subject  projects  or  reflects  its  feeling  out, 
interprets  it  as  the  sign  of  an  independent  somewhat. 
In  this  sense  we  may  agree  with  Mr  Spencer  that  "  the 
Realistic  interpretation  of  our  states  of  consciousness  " 
is  "  deep  as  the  very  structure  of  the  nervous  system, 
and  cannot  for  an  instant  be  actually  expelled "  ; 4 
or,  as  Professor  Laurie  puts  it,  the  affirmation  of  inde 
pendent  externality  is  a  necessary  reflex  movement  of 

1  An  example  of  Professor  Laurie's. 

2  Principles  of  Psychology,  Part  VII.  Ch.  18. 

3  Ibid.,  Ch.  13. 

4  Ibid.,  Ch.  14. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       191 

sense.  "  By  a  reflex  action  of  consciousness  things  are 
constituted  objects  and  external.  This  movement, 
moreover,  lies  in  the  heart  of  consciousness  ;  and  through 
it  alone  is  consciousness  possible."1 

This  being  so,  then — Realism  being  incontestably  prior 
—philosophical  reflection  supervenes,  and  subjects  this 
primitive  and  instinctive  consciousness  to  a  sceptical 
criticism,  which  aims  either  at  establishing  some  form 
of  Idealism  or  at  reducing  us  to  complete  Scepticism. 
This  criticism,  as  already  remarked,  is  both  salutary 
and  necessary  ;  for  if  Realism  is  to  justify  itself  it  must 
do  so  at  the  bar  of  Reason  :  it  cannot  save  itself  by  a 
mere  appeal  to  instinctive  or  unreasoned  belief,  especially 
when  that  belief  may  be  seen  at  a  glance  to  involve  a 
number  of  unscientific  and  untenable  assertions.  Reflec 
tive  criticism  brings  to  light  important  and  undeniable 
distinctions  which  are  ignored  in  the  primitive  realistic 
beliefs  of  the  race.  The  philosophical  thinker  will  avail 
himself  gladly  of  these  distinctions  to  purge  the  crude 
or  instinctive  doctrine  of  the  unscientific  elements 
which  bring  it  into  discredit,  while  at  the  same  time  he 
endeavours,  in  view  of  this  idealistic  criticism,  to  state 
in  an  unexceptionable  form  the  indestructible  elements 
of  truth  which  he  believes  the  original  belief  to  contain. 
In  regard  to  this  indestructible  basis  of  truth  he  must 
meet  the  criticisms  of  the  idealist  by  showing  that 
Idealism  as  an  epistemological  doctrine  only  exists  as  a 
criticism  of  Realism,  and  derives  any  plausibility  it 
possesses  from  the  surreptitious  or  unobserved  importa 
tion  into  its  statement  of  our  ineradicable  realistic 
assumptions.  Were  it  not  for  these  assumptions  the 
idealistic  theory  could  not  be  stated  in  words.  Idealism 
is  really  an  attempt  to  obliterate  the  distinction  between 
knowing  and  being,  which  it  finds  established  in  common 
belief  and  in  the  realistic  theories.  The  gist  of  episte- 

1  Metaphysica  Nova  et  Vetusta,  p.  74  (2nd  ed.). 


192   BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

mological  Idealism  is  that  the  knowing1  is  the  thing 
known  ;  that  being  known  to  different  consciousnesses 
is  the  only  being  or  existence  of  the  object ;  that 
cognitive  states  of  a  number  of  conscious  beings  exist, 
but  that  the  'it/  the  object  which  we  ordinarily  suppose 
these  cognitive  states  to  refer  to — which  we  suppose  to 
be  known  by  means  of  these  cognitive  states — is  nothing 
beyond  the  cognitive  states  themselves.2  Now  on  such 
a  theory  it  is  pretty  evident  that  the  distinction  of 
Knowing  and  Being,  of  independent  subject  and  object, 
would  never  have  arisen,  and  would  not  have  required 
therefore  to  be  explained  away.  Hence,  it  may  be 
repeated,  Idealism  exists  only  as  a  criticism  of  Realism. 
When  developed  itself  as  a  substantive  theory,  it  leads 
to  a  view  of  existence  which  is  a  redmtio  ad  absurdum 
of  the  doctrine  in  question.  By  such  a  line  of  argument 
Realism  is  left  in  possession  of  the  field,  and  a  critical 
or  carefully  guarded  Realism  is  established  as  the  only 
satisfactory,  indeed  the  only  sane,  theory  of  knowledge. 
The  considerations  on  which  a  sceptical  idealism,  or  an 
idealistic  scepticism,  founds  are  sufficiently  obvious,  and 
by  no  means  profound.  As  Hume  puts  it,  the  "  universal 
and  primary  opinion  of  all  men  is  soon  destroyed  by  the 
slightest  philosophy." 3  Possibly,  therefore  (to  adapt 
Bacon's  maxim),  if  a  little  philosophy  inclines  men's 
minds  to  idealism,  depth  in  philosophy  may  bring  them 
back  to  Realism.  "  The  slightest  philosophy  teaches  us," 
Hume  proceeds,  "  that  nothing  can  ever  be  present  to 
the  mind  but  an  image  or  perception,  and  that  the 
senses  are  only  the  inlets  through  which  these  images 
are  conveyed,  without  being  able  to  produce  any  im 
mediate  intercourse  between  the  mind  and  the  object." 

1  [state  of  knowing.] 

2  Obviously    on   such    a    hypothesis    the    designation    '  cognitive  ' 
applied  to  the  states  is  no  longer  appropriate,  since  they  have  ceased 
to  be  the  instruments  of  knowledge. 

3  Enquiry,  section  12. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       193 

In  other  words,  and  to  put  it  more  modernly,  the  special 
arguments  by  which  idealism  is  enforced  are  drawn  from 
the  physiology  of  the  sense-organs.  The  general  position 
on  which  it  rests  is  that,  physiologically,  knowledge  has 
for  its  immediate  conditions  certain  processes  in  every 
organism,  and,  psychologically,  knowledge  consists  of 
certain  subjective  experiences  in  me  (whatever  that  may 
precisely  mean,  some  denying  the  me  and  asserting 
simply  the  subjective  experiences  as  such).  As  Hume 
says,  we  never  get  "  any  immediate  intercourse  between 
the  mind  and  the  object."  Consciousness,  as  such,  is 
shut  up  to  its  own  contents  or  constituents.  What 
transcends  consciousness — i.e.,  any  existence  which  is 
other  than  consciousness  cannot  be  in  consciousness  ; 
albeit  the  ordinary  naive  idea  seems  to  be  that  conscious 
ness,  as  it  were,  goes  out  of  itself,  and  actually  lays  hold 
of  things,  or  throws  its  net  over  them.  In  literal  fact, 
however,  this  is  not  so.  The  psychical  experiences 
which  constitute  knowledge  are  one  thing,  and,  accord 
ing  to  the  doctrine  of  a  Realism  that  understands  itself, 
the  thing  known  is  another.  Their  distinction  is  unde 
niable,  though  an  ill-advised  Realism  and  an  ill-advised 
Idealism  alike  try  to  undermine  it  or  to  explain  it  away. 
In  fact,  as  we  saw  at  the  outset  of  this  paper,  the  distinc 
tion  may  be  said  to  be  involved  in  the  very  nature  or 
notion  of  knowledge.  Knowledge  means  nothing  if  it 
does  not  mean  the  relation  of  two  factors,  knowledge 
of  an  object  by  a  subject.  But  knowledge  is  not  an 
entity  stretching  across,  as  it  were,  from  subject  to 
object,  and  uniting  them  ;  still  less  is  knowledge  the 
one  reality  of  which  subject  and  object  are  two  sides 
or  aspects.  Knowledge  is  an  activity,  an  activo-passive 
experience  of  the  subject,  whereby  it  becomes  aware  of 
what  is  not  itself.  The  cognitive  state  is  thus  related 
psychologically  to  the  subject  whose  state  it  is,  and 
epistemologically  to  the  object  of  which  it  is  the  know- 

N 


194      BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

ledge.  Epistemologically  there  is  a  union  of  subject  and 
object :  the  knower  and  what  he  knows  are  in  a  sense,  as 
Aristotle  says,  one.  But  ontologically,  or  as  a  matter 
of  existence,  they  remain  distinct — the  one  here  and  the 
other  there — and  nothing  avails  to  bridge  this  chasm. 
The  chasm,  it  is  true,  is  not  an  absolute  one,  otherwise 
knowledge  would  be  forever  impossible.  Across  the 
inane  there  is  no  bridge.  Both  subject  and  object  are 
members  of  one  world.  That  may  be  taken  as  the 
ultimate  and  unavoidable  presupposition.  But  separa 
tion  and  difference  are  the  very  conditions  of  knowledge  ; 
if  it  were  not  for  the  difference  where  would  be  the 
need  of  knowledge  ?  Each  thing  would  actually  be 
everything  else,  or  rather  '  each  '  would  be  an  impossible 
conception.  The  O/JLOV  iravra  of  Anaxagoras  would  be 
realised  in  a  more  intimate  and  literal  sense  than  its 
author  ever  imagined  ;  all  things  would  be  together,  an 
indistinguishable  conglomerate  of  mutual  interpenetration. 
It  is  individuation,  distinctness  in  existence,  that  calls 
for  knowledge  and  gives  it  scope.  Feelings,  images, 
ideas,  beliefs,  volitions — these  are  the  components  of 
consciousness,  they  have  an  existence  of  their  own, 
but  it  is  a  mode  of  existence  generically  distinct  from 
that  we  attribute  to  things  as  real  beings,  whether 
material  or  spiritual.  By  means  of  certain  of  these 
conscious  facts — those  called  cognitive — the  being  in 
whom  they  occur  believes  that  he  is  made  aware  of  the 
existence,  nature  and  actions  of  existences  other  than 
himself.  But  he  cannot  by  any  possibility  step  out  of 
himself  and  pass  over  into  these  other  existences,  or  draw 
them  into  himself.  In  this  respect  Matthew  Arnold's 
lines  are  as  true  as  they  are  poignantly  beautiful  :— 

Yes  !  in  the  sea  of  life  enisled, 

With  echoing  straits  between  us  thrown, 

Dotting  the  shoreless  watery  wild, 
We  mortal  millions  live  alone. 

The  islands  feel  the  enclasping  flow, 

And  then  their  endless  bounds  they  know. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       195 

But,  as  I  have  said,  to  wish  to  overpass  these  limits  is 
to  rebel  against  the  very  nature  of  selfhood,  and  episte- 
mologically  to  kick  against  the  very  notion  of  knowledge. 
That  very  self  which  is  a  principle  of  isolation  in  exist 
ence  is  the  principle  on  which  all  communion,  all  fellow 
ship  rests,  alike  in  knowing  and  in  feeling.  But  know 
ledge  is  not  a  fusion  of  knower  and  known,  nor  is  it  all 
explained  by  being  regarded  as  a  kind  of  physical  con 
tinuity  or  immediate  contact  between  the  knowing 
subject  and  the  object  known.  Though  science  may 
prove  all  perception  to  be  dependent  on  the  existence 
of  a  physical  medium  between  the  object  perceived  and 
the  sense-organs,  thus  reducing  all  the  senses  to  varieties 
of  touch,  the  psychical  facts  which  result  are  yet  totally 
different,  and  as  it  were  apart  from  the  series  of  physical 
movements  from  which  they  result.  Physical  nearness 
or  remoteness  does  not  affect  the  epistemological  ques 
tion.  The  table  which  is  in  immediate  contact  with  my 
organism  is  as  completely  and  inexorably  outside  the 
world  of  my  consciousness  as  the  most  distant  '  star  and 
system  '  visible  upon  the  bosom  of  the  night.  Though 
I  press  my  hand  against  it,  it  is  no  more  present  in  con 
sciousness  than  is  the  friend  on  the  other  side  of  the 
globe  whose  image  rises  at  the  moment  in  my  mind. 
There  are  in  fact  two  worlds,  and  to  that  fundamental 
antithesis  we  return.  To  the  one  world  belong,  in 
Berkeley's  language  though  not  in  Berkeley's  sense,  all 
the  choir  of  heaven  and  furniture  of  the  earth,  to  the 
other  the  thoughts  and  feelings  of  the  individual  who  is 
consciously  aware  of  this  system  of  things  in  which  he 
himself  draws  his  breath  and  has  his  place.  To  use 
the  well-worn  words,  there  is  the  macrocosm  and  there 
is  the  microcosm.  Ontologically  or  metaphysically,  the 
microcosm  must  necessarily  be  viewed  as  a  dependent 
part  or  function  of  the  mighty  whole  ;  but  epistemologic- 
ally  the  microcosm  rounds  itself  off  within  itself,  and 
constitutes  in  perfect  strictness  a  little  world  of  its  own. 


196       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

The  world  of  consciousness,  on  the  one  hand,  and  the 
(so  far  hypothetical)  world  of  real  things,  on  the  other, 
are  two  mutually  exclusive  spheres.  No  member  of 
the  real  sphere  can  intrude  itself  into  the  conscious 
sphere,  nor  can  consciousness  go  out  into  the  real  sphere 
and  as  it  were  lay  hold  with  hands  upon  a  real  object. 
The  two  worlds  are,  to  this  extent  and  in  this  sense, 
totally  disparate. 

As  soon  as  this  is  clearly  recognised — and  as  Hume 
says,  no  very  profound  philosophical  reflection  is  needed 
to  reach  this  stage — it  becomes  evident  that  Realism 
cannot  be  maintained  as  a  philosophical  hypothesis  in 
the  uncritical  form  which  it  assumes  in  the  mind  of  the 
plain  man.  And  so  far  as  the  Realism  of  Scottish 
philosophy  is  merely  an  uncritical  reassertion  of  our 
primitive  beliefs,  it  is  not  to  be  wondered  at  that  succeed 
ing  philosophers  have  so  frequently  treated  their  specula 
tions  as  a  negligible  quantity.  Immediacy  must  be  given 
up  before  any  tenable  theory  of  perception  and  any 
philosophical  doctrine  of  Realism  can  be  established. 
The  truth  of  the  idealistic  contentions  must  be  acknow 
ledged.  It  must  be  granted  that  in  passing  from  the 
real  to  the  ideal  there  is  a  solution  of  continuity,  a  leap, 
a  passage  from  one  world  to  another.  The  world  of 
real  things  is  transcendent  with  reference  to  the  world 
of  consciousness  ;  the  world  of  objects  (as  we  customarily, 
though  ambiguously,  speak  of  it)  is  trans-subjective  or 
extra-conscious.  In  other  words,  it  falls  absolutely 
outside  of,  or  beyond,  the  little  world  of  consciousness, 
and  the  conscious  being  cannot  in  the  nature  of  things 
overleap  or  transcend  itself.  The  knowledge  which  we 
call  most  immediate  or  direct  is  only  relatively  so  ;  so 
far  as  it  is  knowledge,  it  is  mediate,  or  the  result  of  a 
process.  Knowledge  puts  a  man  in  relation  with  things 
through  the  medium  of  his  perceptions,  but  his  percep 
tions  are  not  the  things  ;  he  does  not  pass  over  into  the 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       197 

things,  nor  do  the  things  pass  over  into  him.  At  no 
point  can  the  real  world,  as  it  were,  force  an  entrance 
into  the  closed  sphere  of  the  ideal ;  nor  does  that  sphere 
open  at  any  point  to  receive  into  itself  the  smallest 
atom  of  the  real  world,  qua  real,  though  it  has  room 
within  itself  ideally  for  the  whole  universe  of  God. 

A  critical  Realism  must  start  then  with  the  acknow 
ledgment  of  this  fact.  This  is  the  truth  which  both  Locke 
and  Kant  had  got  firm  hold  of.  It  is  the  basis  of  Locke's 
hypothetical  Dualism,  and,  so  far  as  our  present  argu 
ment  is  concerned,  Kant's  relativistic  phenomenalism 
with  its  inferential  background  of  things-in-themselves 
is  substantially  a  similar  theory  with  the  sceptical 
suggestions  of  Lockianism  unfortunately  emphasised. 
From  Locke  and  Kant  as  centres  the  epistemological 
speculations  of  modern  philosophy  may  be  conveniently 
viewed.  Now,  unquestionably,  the  transcendence  of 
the  real  does  give  scepticism  its  opportunity.  Scepticism 
takes  up  its  position  in  the  gap  thus  apparently  made 
between  the  ideal  and  the  real,  and  asks  how  we  know 
that  we  know  the  real  things,  what  assurance  have  we 
that  the  world  of  real  things  is  as  it  appears  to  us  to  be, 
nay,  in  the  last  resort,  what  assurance  have  we  that 
there  is  a  world  of  real  things  at  all.  This  sceptical 
insinuation  requires  to  be  fairly  met,  for,  however  little 
it  avails  to  shake  our  practical  certainty,  the  theoretic 
possibility  of  such  a  doubt  lies  in  the  very  nature  of 
the  case.  So  long  as  the  knower  and  that  which  he 
knows  are  not  identical,  so  long  is  it  possible  that  his 
knowledge  may  not  be  true — i.e.,  may  not  correctly 
render  the  nature  of  what  is.  Hence  a  succession  of 
attempts  to  dispense  with  the  otherness  or  transcend 
ency  of  the  object  known.  Thus  we  find  Berkeley 
inveighing  against  this  "  groundless  and  absurd  notion  " 
as  " the  very  root  of  scepticism."  1  The  arguments  used 
1  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge,  section  86. 


ig8       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

by  sceptics  in  all  ages,  he  says,  depend  on  the  sup 
position  of  external  objects.1  The  temptation  accord 
ingly  is  to  abolish  the  independent  world  of  real  exist 
ences  altogether,  and  to  manipulate  our  perceptions  or 
ideas  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  them  stand  in  its  place. 
This  is  the  plan  we  find  adopted  by  Berkeley  partially, 
and  in  more  thorough-going  fashion  by  Hume.  Berkeley 
and  Hume  have  been  modernised  by  Mill.  It  was  this 
sceptical  development  of  Locke's  "  way  of  ideas  "  that 
drove  some  Scotch  philosophers  to  seek  refuge  in  the 
theory  or  no  theory  of  Immediate  Perception.  By 
thus  putting  the  mind  with  its  nose  up  against  things 
(to  use  a  homely  but  graphic  phrase  of  Von  Hartmann's) 
they  sought  to  cut  off  the  very  possibility  of  doubt. 
But  this  is  to  cut  the  Gordian  knot  in  an  inadmissible 
way.  The  doubt  has  been  raised  and  is  plainly  possible. 
This  is  fully  admitted  and  stated  with  admirable  clear 
ness  by  Hamilton,  even  while  insisting  most  strenuously 
upon  the  testimony  of  consciousness  to  a  duality  of 
existence.  "  The  facts  of  consciousness,"  he  says,  "  are 
to  be  considered  in  two  points  of  view,  either  as  evi 
dencing  their  own  ideal  or  phenomenal  existence,  or  as 
evidencing  the  objective  existence  of  something  else 
beyond  them.  A  belief  in  the  former  is  not  identical 
with  a  belief  in  the  latter.  The  one  cannot,  the  other 
may  possibly  be  refused.  In  the  case  of  a  common 
witness  we  cannot  doubt  the  fact  of  his  testimony  as 
emitted,  but  we  can  always  doubt  the  truth  of  that 
which  his  testimony  avers.  So  it  is  with  consciousness."  2 
Hence  to  shout  Immediate  Perception  is  no  reply.  It 
is  to  seek  an  imaginary  security  by  shutting  one's  eyes 
to  the  danger,  instead  of  boldly  facing  it.  A  more  legiti 
mate  method  is  to  show  the  inadequacy  of  the  idealistic 
substitutes  for  a  trans-subjective  real  world,  to  show, 

1  Principles  of  Hitman  Knowledge,  section  87. 

2  Lectures  on  Metaphysics,  I.  p.  271. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       199 

as  I  said  before,  that  it  is  only  in  virtue  of  their  borrow 
ings  from  Realism  that  they  can  be  stated  and  discussed. 
This  indirect  proof,  proceeding  by  the  exclusion  of  other 
possible  theories,  is  declared  by  Hartmann *•  to  be  the 
only  way  in  which  a  critical  Realism  can  be  firmly  estab 
lished  ;  or,  to  put  it  otherwise,  the  doubt  must  be 
redargued  by  showing  its  ultimate  scope.  This  is  to  a 
certain  extent  what  Reid  does,  and  it  is  in  his  criticisms 
of  the  ideal  theory  conceived  in  this  spirit,  and  not  in 
his  dogmatic  assertion  of  immediate  perception,  that  we 
must  recognise  his  philosophical  merit  and  his  philoso 
phical  importance. 

1  See  his  Kritische  Gvundlegung  des  transcendentalen  Realismus,  and 
his  Grundproblem  der  Erkenntnisstheorie,  passim. 


LECTURE   III. 

EPISTEMOLOGY   IN   LOCKE   AND   KANT. 

LOCKE'S  hypothetical  Realism  or  problematical  Dualism 
is,  as  such,  a  sounder  theory  than  the  vastly  more  acute 
and  subtle  theories  of  his  critics.  But  in  Locke's  hands 
the  theory  is  stated  in  such  a  way  that  Berkeley  and 
Hume  become  logical  necessities ;  if  they  had  not 
existed,  it  would  have  been  necessary  to  invent  them. 
Locke's  rudimentary  psychology,  his  inextricable  com 
mingling  of  psychological,  epistemological  and  meta 
physical  questions,  are  mainly  to  blame  for  this.  Above 
all  must  be  signalised  the  atomic  sensationalism  which 
he  places  in  the  forefront  of  his  theory,  though  he  him 
self  is  the  last  man  to  abide  consistently  by  it.  Readers 
of  Green's  massive  Introduction  to  Hume  will  remember 
the  constantly  reiterated  criticism  that  Locke  habitually 
uses  idea  or  simple  idea  as  equivalent  to  "  idea  of  a  thing." 
The  simple  idea,  says  Green,  is  thus  represented  as 
involving  a  theory  of  its  own  cause  ;  it  is  not  a  mere 
sensation,  but  the  idea  of  a  quality  of  a  thing  ;  it  is 
referred  to  a  permanent  real  world  of  which  it  is  repre 
sentative  or  symbolic.  Beyond  doubt  this  is  precisely 
what  Locke  does.  One  has  only  to  open  the  Essay  to 
find  Locke  continually  passing  from  the  one  order  of 
phrases  to  the  other.  "  The  senses/'  he  says,  "  let  in 
particular  ideas  "  and  furnish  the  yet  empty  cabinet ;  but 
Locke  says  with  equal  readiness  they  "  convey  into  the 


202       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

mind,  several  distinct  perceptions  of  things."  The 
particular  ideas  bare  of  all  reference,  a  drip,  drip  of  dis 
continuous  sensations,  so  many  present  existences  in 
consciousness,  each  testifying  to  itself  alone,  are  trans 
formed  without  a  qualm  into  "  ideas  of  things  without." 
Locke  apparently  does  not  see  the  difference  between 
the  two  sets  of  statements.  But  if  the  difference  is 
ignored  in  Locke,  we  find  it  explicitly  denied  by  Hume 
that  there  is  any  difference  :  'To  form  the  idea  of  an 
object  and  to  form  an  idea  simply  is  the  same  thing  ; 
the  reference  of  the  idea  to  the  object  being  an  ex 
traneous  denomination,  of  which  in  itself  it  bears  no 
mark  or  character."1  Green,  I  take  it,  does  not  mean 
that  Locke  was  wrong  in  taking  up  this  second  position, 
and  in  beginning  his  theory  of  knowledge,  not  with  a 
simple  idea  of  sensation — a  mere  sensation — but  with 
a  judgment  in  which  a  causal  reference  and  the  dis 
tinction  of  self  and  not  self  are  implicit.  Green's  point 
is  that  Locke  on  his  own  avowed  principles  is  not  entitled 
to  the  second  and  sounder  position,  a  position  which  may 
be  shown  to  involve  many  consequences  which  no  sen- 
sationalistic  philosophy  can  admit.  Green  seeks  to  pin 
Locke  down  to  his  sensationalistic  formulae,  interpreted 
with  the  utmost  rigour  of  the  law,  in  the  light  of  Hume's 
deductions,  whereas  it  is  apparent  on  every  page  of  the 
Essay  that  Locke  never  dreamt  of  their  bearing  such  a 
meaning.  Hence  it  is  that  Green  is  less  than  just  to 
Locke  and  deals  only  with  his  inconsistencies.  Professor 
Campbell  Eraser's  reconstruction  is  far  truer  to  his 
spirit  and  intentions.  In  truth  Green's  interest  is  not 
with  Locke's  theory  as  a  \vhole,  but  with  English  sen 
sationalism  as  that  first  disclosed  its  features  in  certain 
definitions  and  statements  of  the  Essay.  Locke's  first 
way  of  stating  the  case  implies  that  false  substantiation 
of  the  bare  particulars  of  sense  which  issued  in  the 

1  Treatise,  I.  p.  327  (Green's  edition). 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       203 

agnostic  sensational  atomism  of  Hume.  It  leads  directly 
to  the  ideal  theory  and  the  so-called  doctrine  of  repre 
sentative  perception  in  the  objectionable  form  in 
which  it  is  attacked  by  Reid.  "It  is  evident,"  says 
Locke,  "  the  mind  knows  not  things  immediately,  but 
only  by  the  intervention  of  the  ideas  it  has  of  them/' 
So  far  he  is  on  perfectly  safe  ground,  except  that  the 
word  '  intervention  '  has  already  a  subtle  suggestio  falsi. 
But  the  formula  which  Locke  places  at  the  very  opening 
of  Book  IV.  (and  which  therefore  naturally  takes  a 
prominent  place  in  the  mind  of  the  student  as  deter 
mining  the  sense  of  what  follows)  is  far  from  being  equally 
unobjectionable  ;  though  the  difference  may  seem  so 
slight  as  to  be  almost  imperceptible,  and  the  danger 
that  lurks  in  it  is  probably  only  apparent  to  us  in  the 
light  of  subsequent  events.  "  Since  the  mind,"  says 
Locke,  "  in  all  its  thoughts  and  reasonings,  hath  no 
other  immediate  object  but  its  own  ideas,  which  it  alone 
does  or  can  contemplate,  it  is  evident  that  our  knowledge 
is  only  conversant  about  them." — So,  again,  in  the  open 
ing  of  Chapter  II.,  he  repeats  that  all  our  knowledge  con 
sists  "  in  the  view  the  mind  has  of  its  own  ideas."  Now 
it  is  one  thing  to  say  that  the  mind  knows  things  only  by 
the  intervention  or  by  means  of  the  ideas  it  has  of  them, 
and  another  thing  to  say  that  ideas  constitute  the  "  im 
mediate  object  "  of  the  mind,  and  that  "  our  knowledge 
is  only  conversant  about  "  ideas.  The  last  is  so  far 
from  being  true  that  it  might  be  more  correct  to  say 
that  our  knowledge  is  never  conversant  about  ideas — 
ideas  never  constitute  the  object  of  the  mind  at  all— 
unless  in  the  reflective  analysis  of  the  psychologist. 
Otherwise,  our  knowledge  is  always  conversant  about 
realities  of  some  kind ;  to  say  that  we  know  by  means 
of  ideas  is  simply  to  say  that  we  know ;  but  ideas  are 
naught  except  as  signs  of  a  further  reality,  and  from  the 
first  they  are  taken  not  per  se,  but  in  this  symbolic 


204      BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

capacity.  As  Locke  himself  puts  it  in  his  excellent 
chapter  on  the  Reality  of  Human  Knowledge,  "  It  is 
the  knowledge  of  things  that  is  only  to  be  prized.  .  .  . 
If  our  knowledge  of  our  ideas  terminate  in  them  and 
reach  no  farther  .  .  .  our  most  serious  thoughts  will  be 
of  little  more  use  than  the  reveries  of  a  crazy  brain/' — 
Locke's  shifting  statements  show  us,  indeed,  "  the 
psychologist's  fallacy  "  in  full  blast.  If  we  once  yield 
ourselves  to  his  first  line  of  thought ;  if  we  admit  a 
start  from  ideas  per  se,  a  custom-woven,  private,  ideal 
phantasmagoria  will  be  our  only  substitute  for  the 
common  or  objective  world  of  real  persons  and  things. 
We  get  a  theory  of  Representative  Perception  that  is 
totally  indefensible ;  the  ideas  are  taken  as  really 
intervening  between  the  mind  and  things  ;  the  mechanism 
of  knowledge  is  converted  into  an  elaborate  means  of 
defeating  its  own  purpose.  It  becomes  a  tertium  quid,  a 
kind  of  screen  which  effectually  shuts  off  the  knower  from 
what  he  desires  to  know.  We  are  supposed,  first,  to 
know  the  ideas  on  their  own  account  as  mental  states 
or  mental  entities,  and  subsequently,  by  a  process  of 
conscious  inference,  to  refer  them  to  real  causes  and 
archetypes.  If  knowledge  at  any  stage  did  terminate 
thus  in  the  ideas  themselves,  it  is  difficult  to  see  either 
what  considerations  could  suggest  to  us  the  step  beyond 
their  charmed  circle  or  on  what  grounds  it  could  be 
justified.  This  is  in  fact  the  point  of  the  idealistic  and 
sceptical  criticism  which  Berkeley  and  Hume  brought 
to  bear  upon  Locke's  hypothetical  Realism.  Berkeley, 
as  Green  puts  it,  tries  to  avoid  Locke's  inconsistencies  by 
dropping  the  reference  to  transcendent  real  objects 
altogether :  for  idea  of  an  object  he  deliberately  sub 
stitutes  idea  simply.  To  him  the  ideas  are  the  objects, 
sensible  things  are  clusters  or  collections  of  ideas- 
actual  and  possible  perceptions  of  intelligent  beings. 
"  The  table  I  write  on  exists,  that  is,  I  see  and  feel  it ; 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       205 

and  if  I  were  out  of  my  study,  I  should  say  it  existed — 
meaning  thereby  that,  if  I  was  in  my  study,  I  might 
perceive  it  or  that  some  other  spirit  actually  does  per 
ceive  it."  In  his  recurring  phrase,  the  being  of  things 
"is  to  be  perceived  or  known,"  or,  as  he  puts  it  even 
more  strikingly,  "  the  object  and  the  sensation  are  the 
same  thing."  "  An  idea  can  be  like  nothing  but  an 
idea  "  and  the  supposition  of  independent  originals  of 
our  ideas  is  gratuitous.  "  If  there  were  external  bodies, 
it  is  impossible  we  should  ever  come  to  know  it."  The 
supposition  of  such  bodies  is,  in  short,  not  only  "  ground 
less  and  absurd,"  but  "  is  the  very  root  of  scepticism  ; 
for  so  long  as  men  thought  that  real  things  subsisted 
without  the  mind,  and  that  their  knowledge  was  only 
so  far  forth  real  as  it  was  conformable  to  real  things,  it 
follows  that  they  could  not  be  certain  that  they  had 
any  real  knowledge  at  all.  For  how  can  it  be  known 
that  the  things  which  are  perceived  are  conformable  to 
those  which  are  not  perceived,  or  exist  without  the 
mind  ?  " 1  As  Hume  clinched  the  matter  afterwards  : 
The  mind  has  never  anything  present  to  it  but  the 
perceptions,  and  cannot  possibly  reach  any  experience 
of  their  connection  with  objects.  Hence  Berkeley  pro 
ceeds,  "  All  this  sceptical  cant  follows  from  our  supposing 
a  difference  between  things  and  ideas.  .  .  .  The  argu 
ments  urged  by  sceptics  in  all  ages  depend  on  the  sup 
position  of  external  objects."2  He  is  resolved  himself 
to  make  a  clear  riddance  of  all  such  sceptical  cant.  On 
Berkeley's  principles  there  is  no  opening  for  doubt 
either  as  to  the  existence  of  a  real  world  or  as  to  the 
truth  of  our  knowledge  of  it,  because  the  knowledge, 
the  immediate  conscious  fact,  is  the  existence  and  (along 
with  a  possibility  of  similar  conscious  facts)  the  whole 

1  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge,  section  86.     [Also  sections  3-8 
and  20. — ED.] 

2  Ibid.,  section  87. 


206      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

of  the  existence.  '  That  what  I  see,  hear  and  feel  doth 
exist,  that  is  to  say,  is  perceived  by  me,  I  no  more  doubt 
than  I  do  of  my  own  being."  Unquestionably  not,  for 
if  existence  be  understood  in  this  sense,  the  two  facts 
are  simply  identical.  Doubt  cannot  touch  the  existence 
of  a  present  feeling  while  it  is  being  felt.  But  if  I  thus 
reduce  the  existence  of  a  permanent  external  world  to 
unreferred  feelings,  Hume  is,  of  course,  at  hand  to 
apply  the  same  argument  to  "  my  own  being  "  which 
Berkeley  here  and  elsewhere  treats  as  a  fundamental 
certainty.  These  same  perceptions  or  ideas  whose 
presence  in  consciousness  I  have  asserted  to  be  the 
existence  of  sensible  things,  constitute  the  evidence  of 
my  own  existence  :  in  fact  they  are  my  existence.  As 
Berkeley  himself  says,  ' '  the  duration  of  any  finite  spirit 
must  be  measured  by  the  number  of  ideas  or  actions 
succeeding  each  other  in  that  same  spirit  or  mind ;  .  .  . 
and  in  truth  whoever  shall  go  about  to  divide  in  his 
thoughts  or  abstract  the  existence  of  a  spirit  from  its 
cogitation  will,  I  believe,  find  it  no  easy  task/' x  My 
own  being,  in  fact,  as  something  more  than  the  existence 
of  my  present  conscious  states,  will  be  found  by  a  sound 
philosophy  to  rest  ultimately  on  a  process  of  rational 
construction  substantially  similar  to  that  which  estab 
lishes  the  existence  of  an  independent  object  of  know 
ledge.  Hence  an  Idealism  or  Spiritualism  which  does 
not  guarantee  the  rights  of  the  object  is  a  lop-sided  theory 
which  has  no  defence  against  the  further  inroads  of  its 
own  logic.  Put  forward  as  a  short  and  easy  method  with 
the  sceptics,  Berkeleianism  only  preluded  to  the  sceptical 
nihilism  of  Hume. 

Humianism,  so  far  as  that  is  necessary  to  our  argument, 
may  best  be  dealt  with  in  the  modernised  version  of  Mill. 
But  before  doing  so,  it  will  be  instructive  to  trace  the 
very  similar  process  of  criticism  by  which  the  realistic 

1  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge,  section  98. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   207 

elements  were  eliminated  from  the  original  theory  of 
Kant,  and  we  shall  see  how  their  elimination  leads  to 
similar  sceptical  results. 

It  is  important  to  observe  that  Kant's  starting-point 
is  a  hypothetical  dualism  in  many  respects  similar  to 
that  of  Locke.  Our  knowledge  refers  to  things  which 
are  other  than  our  knowledge  and  may  be  said,  in  that 
sense,  to  lie  beyond  it.  This  further  reference  (which 
we  have  some  reason  to  believe  essential  to  the  very 
nature  of  knowledge)  Kant  certainly  starts  with  ;  and 
whatever  results  his  theory  leads  him  to  as  regards  the 
kind  of  knowledge  we  have  of  things,  he  never  loses  hold 
of  what  he  calls  the  thing-in-itself  as  that  which  alone 
gives  meaning  to  the  cognitive  effort.  Our  knowledge 
of  things  may  be  imperfect  and  coloured  by  the  infusion 
of  subjective  elements,  but  if  there  were  no  '  things-in- 
themselves,'  the  whole  process  of  knowledge  would  be  a 
completely  unmotived  excursion  into  the  void.  Hence, 
as  Kant  puts  it  in  the  Preface  to  the  second  edition  of 
the  Critique,  with  his  whole  system  explicitly  in  view, 
"  while  we  surrender  the  power  of  cognising,  we  still 
reserve  the  power  of  thinking  objects  as  things-in- 
themselves.  For  otherwise  we  should  require  to  affirm 
the  existence  of  an  appearance  without  anything  that 
appears — which  would  be  absurd."  In  other  words, 
our  cognitions  may  be  Erscheinungen,  merely  pheno 
menal,  but  as  phenomena — as  cognitions — they  imply 
real  objects,  of  which  they  are  the  cognitions.  It  is,  of 
course,  the  peculiarity  of  the  Kantian  scheme,  that  our 
knowledge  is  so  organised  as  to  defeat  its  own  purpose 
and  cut  us  off  from  a  knowledge  of  things  as  they  really 
are.  So  far  as  our  knowledge  of  it  is  concerned,  the 
thing-in-itself  shrinks,  therefore,  for  Kant  into  a  mere 
unknown  somewhat ;  but  in  that  capacity  it  remains 
as  the  necessary  presupposition  of  the  knowing  process. 


208       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

It  would  be  superfluous  to  multiply  quotations  in 
support  of  a  position  which  even  those  who  try  to 
explain  it  away  must  admit  to  have  been  held  by  Kant. 
I  will,  therefore,  quote  only  one  typical  passage  from 
the  Prolegomena  in  which  he  elaborately  distinguishes 
his  own  doctrine  from  that  of  Idealism  : — 

"  Idealism  consists  in  the  assertion  that  there  are  no 
other  than  thinking  beings  ;  that  the  other  things  which 
we  believe  ourselves  to  perceive  are  only  ideas  in  thinking 
beings — ideas  to  which  in  fact  there  is  no  correspondent 
object  outside  of  or  beyond  the  thinking  beings.  I,  on 
the  contrary,  say,  Things  are  given  to  us  as  objects  of 
our  senses,  external  to  us  ;  but  of  what  they  may  be 
in  themselves  we  know  nothing,  knowing  only  their 
appearances — that  is,  the  ideas  which  they  cause  in  us 
by  affecting  our  senses.  Accordingly  I  certainly  admit 
that  they  are  bodies  external  to  us — that  is,  things  which, 
although  wholly  unknown  to  us  as  regards  what  they 
may  be  in  themselves,  we  yet  know  through  the  ideas 
which  their  influence  upon  our  sensibility  supplies  us 
with,  and  to  which  we  give  the  appellation  body  :  which 
word  signifies,  therefore,  only  the  appearance  of  that  to 
us  unknown,  but  not  the  less  real,  object.  Can  this  be 
called  Idealism  ?  Surely  it  is  precisely  the  opposite." 
He  declares  roundly  elsewhere  "  that  it  never  entered 
his  head  to  doubt  the  existence  of  independent  things 
(Sacheri)."  Kant  (in  the  passage  quoted  and  elsewhere) 
assumes  independent  things  not  only  as  existent,  but 
as  the  trans-subjective  cause  of  our  sense-affections. 
How  else,  he  says,  could  the  knowing  faculty  be  roused 
to  exercise,  if  not  by  objects  which  affect  our  senses  ? 
The  position  is  to  Kant  so  much  a  matter  of  course  that 
he  does  not  stop  to  argue  it.  And  so  it  remained  to  the 
end.  To  interpret  such  statements  as  preliminary  or 
provisional  on  Kant's  part  is  completely  unwarranted. 
If  they  had  been  a  piece  of  exoteric  condescension  or 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM       209 

accommodation  to  the  untrained  minds  of  his  readers — 
if  he  had  been  merely  educating  these  readers  up  to  a 
point  of  view  which  would  transform  their  whole  con 
ception  of  the  universe  and  render  the  thing-in-itself  an 
unnecessary  adjunct — then  Kant  must  have  given  us 
some  hint  at  least  of  this  pedagogic  use  of  language, 
instead  of  leaving  such  expressions  staring  at  us  from 
page  after  page  of  his  works  in  a  perfectly  unqualified 
way.  They  appear  not  only  in  works  written  while 
he  is  supposed  to  have  been  working  his  way  towards 
his  own  deeper  view,  but  are  to  be  found  quite  as  un 
ambiguously  in  writings  composed  long  after  his  whole 
scheme  lay  clearly  outlined  before  his  mind.  A  few 
statements J  may  certainly  be  pointed  to,  mostly  obscure 
in  their  drift  and  phraseology,  which,  if  they  stood  by 
themselves,  might  be  interpreted  in  an  idealistic  sense. 
But  when  they  have  to  be  placed  against  the  mass  of 
counter-evidence — the  numberless  explicit  assertions  of 
the  realistic  position  and  the  vehement  disclaimers  of 
Idealism — which  may  be  quoted  from  Kant's  writings, 
it  is  manifest  that  the  Idealism  that  seems  to  the  eyes 
of  later-born  critics  to  shimmer  in  the  words  was  not 
present  to  Kant  in  writing  them,  and  that,  whatever 
their  meaning  may  be,  an  interpretation  must  be  sought 
not  inconsistent  with  the  fundamental  Realism  of  the 
authentic  Kantian  philosophy,  whether  that  is  for 
mulated  in  the  first  edition  or  the  second,  in  the  Pro 
legomena  or  in  Kant's  express  statements  in  later  years. 
Of  these  last  I  will  only  refer  to  his  rejoinder  to  Eber- 
hardt  in  1790,  the  year  of  the  Critique  of  Judgment,  and 
his  public  declarations  in  regard  to  Fichte  and  his 

1  The  chief  passages  that  seem  opposed  to  a  realistic  interpretation 
occur  in  the  chapter  on  Phenomena  and  Noumena  in  the  first  Critique  ; 
but  Kant  is  there  speaking  in  another  reference.  He  is  speaking  not 
of  the  existence  of  things-in-themselves,  but  of  a  non-sensuous  in 
tuition  of  them.  Besides,  his  subsequent  declarations  are  sufficient 
to  show  that  they  are  not  intended  to  throw  doubt  on  the  existence 
and  causal  activity  of  things-in-themselves. 

O 


2io       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

system  in  the  year  1799.  Publicly  invited  by  Fichte 
to  disclarpf  the  derivation  of  sensation  from  the  impres 
sion  of  things-in-themselves,  the  aged  philosopher 
hastened  to  disown  the  Fichtean  idealism  which  he 
characterised  in  the  newspaper  as  a  pure  logic  from 
which  it  was  a  vain  hope  ever  to  extract  a  real  object. 
The  Wissenschaftslehre,  he  had  said  in  a  letter  to  a 
friend  the  year  before,  impressed  him  "  like  a  kind  of 
ghost."  '  The  mere  self-consciousness,  or,  to  be  more 
correct,  the  mere  form  of  thought  without  matter- 
consequently  without  the  reflection  having  anything 
before  it  to  which  it  could  be  applied — makes  a  queer 
impression  upon  the  reader.  When  you  think  you  are 
going  to  lay  hold  on  an  object,  you  lay  hold  on  yourself 
instead  ;  in  fact  the  groping  hand  grasps  only  itself." 

It  may  seem  strange  that  a  system  with  such  a  firm 
realistic  basis  should  have  been  the  parent  of  so  many 
idealisms,  whether  we  look  to  the  constructive  Idealism 
of  his  immediate  successors,  Fichte,  Schelling  and  Hegel, 
to  English  Neo-Hegelianism  or  to  the  sceptical  and 
positivistic  idealism  of  many  German  Neo-Kantians. 
But  the  reason  is  not  far  to  seek.  If  Kant  starts  from, 
or  implies  throughout,  a  hypothetical  dualism  of  the 
Lockian  type,  he  likewise  accepts  in  the  most  unqualified 
way  the  doctrine  which  we  found  in  Locke  and  Hume 
of  the  subjectivity  of  knowledge — the  necessary  limita 
tion  of  the  mind  to  its  own  ideas.  This  doctrine  we 
saw  to  be  true  in  what  it  affirms  ;  it  forms,  indeed,  the 
first  step  in  philosophical  reflection.  Consciousness 
cannot,  in  the  realm  of  fact  or  existence,  pass  beyond 
itself ;  its  own  states  are,  therefore,  all  that  is  im 
mediately  present  to  or  in  the  mind.  But  if  it  be  forth 
with  concluded  from  this,  that  it  is  impossible  by  means 
of  certain  facts  in  my  consciousness  indirectly  to  reach, 
or  in  other  words  to  know,  a  world  of  other  facts  beyond 
my  consciousness,  we  are  arguing  with  more  haste  than 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       211 

caution.  The  two  propositions,  at  all  events,  do  not 
mean  the  same  thing.  That  knowledge  is,  and  must  be, 
a  subjective  process  is  not  of  itself  sufficient  to  discredit 
its  results  and  stamp  its  efforts  in  advance  as  unavailing. 
Yet  historically  the  two  statements  are  generally  found 
together,  as  if  they  were  two  sides  of  the  same  truth  : 
knowledge  is  subjective,  therefore  it  can  never  give  us 
the  object  as  it  really  is.  So  it  was  with  Hume,  and  so 
it  is  with  Kant. 

By  Kant  the  position  is  not  usually  stated  quite  so 
broadly.  He  does  not  usually  say  in  so  many  words 
that,  because  knowledge  is  subjective,  it  can  bring  us  no 
true  report  of  real  objects.  To  Kant  it  is  the  sensuous 
or  receptive  character  of  our  perception  that  invalidates 
it.  Our  perception  is  derivative  ;  it  depends  for  its 
matter  upon  an  affection  of  our  sensibility  by  the  object. 
This  is  what  Kant  constantly  emphasises  as  stamping 
our  knowledge  with  phenomenality.  Sensations  are 
subjective  affections  which  nowise  express  or  reveal  the 
nature  of  the  object  but  only  its  relation  to  us.  As  the 
sun  melts  wax  (to  use  an  example  of  Locke's),  so  the 
thing  produces  a  certain  effect  upon  my  sensibility  : 
I  am  internally  modified  in  a  certain  way.  But  such  a 
modification  of  my  nature,  however  it  may  be  set  up  in 
me  by  the  thing,  cannot  possibly  reveal  the  nature  of 
the  thing  as  it  is  in  itself.  In  Kant's  own  words,  we 
know  "  only  the  mode  in  which  our  senses  are  affected 
by  an  unknown  something  "  (Werke,  IV.  63).  "  Sup 
posing  us  to  carry  our  empirical  perception  even  to  the 
very  highest  degree  of  clearness,  we  should  not  thereby 
advance  a  step  nearer  to  a  knowledge  of  the  constitution 
of  objects  as  things-in-themselves.  For  we  could  only, 
at  best,  arrive  at  a  complete  cognition  of  our  own  mode 
of  perception,  that  is,  of  our  sensibility "  (III.  73). 
"  It  is  incomprehensible,"  he  explains  elsewhere  (IV.  31), 
"  how  the  perception  even  of  a  present  object  should 


212       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

give  me  a  knowledge  of  that  thing  as  it  is  in  itself, 
seeing  that  its  properties  cannot  migrate  or  wander 
over  (hiniiberwandern)  into  my  presentative  faculty.'- 

This  is  further  emphasised  by  the  contrast,  which 
Kant  again  and  again  recurs  to,  between  our  sensuous 
or  receptive  intelligence  (intdlectus  ectypus,  derivatives) 
and  a  creative,  or  as  he  otherwise  terms  it,  a  perceptive 
understanding  (intellectus  archetypus,  originarius).  The 
latter,  he  explains  in  the  celebrated  letter  to  Marcus 
Herz,  must  be  conceived  as  all  activity  or  spontaneity  ; 
its  ideas,  therefore,  will  have  creative  efficiency.  They 
will  not  be  passively  related  to  foreign  objects  ;  they 
will  themselves  be  the  objects,  and  such  a  being's  know 
ledge  would,  of  course,  be  entirely  a  priori,  as  the  world 
known  would  be  entirely  self-produced.  In  complete 
contrast  with  such  an  intelligence,  we  may  conceive  a 
being  entirely  passive  or  recipient  in  its  relation  to  the 
object.  In  this  case,  the  ideas  of  the  subject  would  be 
altogether  empirical  or  a  posteriori,  due  to  piecemeal 
communication  from  the  side  of  the  object.  And,  as 
we  have  already  heard  Kant  say,  they  would  in  such  a 
case  give  only  the  way  in  which  the  subject  is  affected 
by  the  object — only  certain  '  passions  '  or  sensuous 
modifications  of  the  subject,  accompanied  by  a  causal 
reference  to  an  (otherwise  unknown)  object. 

Now,  according  to  Kant,  the  human  mind  is  neither 
purely  active  nor  purely  passive ;  human  knowledge  is 
a  compound  of  receptivity  and  spontaneity.  Kant 
assumes,  on  the  evidence  of  mathematics  and  pure 
physics,  that  part  of  our  knowledge  possesses  univer 
sality  and  necessary  validity,  and,  as  universality  and 
necessity  cannot  be  yielded  by  sense,  that  the  principles 
of  such  knowledge  must  be  a  priori,  drawn  in  the  act  of 
knowledge  from  the  nature  of  the  mind  itself.  Hence  it 
comes  that  the  crucial  question  for  Kant  is,  Granted 
these  a  priori  principles,  these  notions  of  the  under- 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   213 

standing,  how  can  they  apply  to  objects  which  are  given 
independently  of  them  ?  If  our  mode  of  perception  were 
intellectual  or  spontaneous  throughout,  creating  its 
objects  whole  (both  form  and  matter),  there  would,  of 
course,  be  no  such  difficulty.  But  our  perception  being 
sensuous,  dependent  for  its  matter  upon  foreign  objects 
that  exist  in  their  own  right,  what  guarantee  have  we 
that  ideas  which  have  their  source  in  the  mind  may  be 
validly  applied  to  independent  objects  ?  To  the  question 
as  thus  put  there  is  but  one  answer — we  have  no  guarantee 
at  all.  Kant's  way  out  of  the  difficulty,  therefore,  was, 
in  effect,  to  renounce  the  attempt  to  know  the  real 
objects  and  to  rest  content  with  the  subjective  modifica 
tions  of  his  own  sensibility.  That  these  a  posteriori 
subjective  affections  should  range  themselves  under  the 
a  priori  forms  of  sense  and  understanding  no  longer 
presents  any  difficulty  ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  obvious 
that  the  structure  of  the  mind  must  impress  itself  on 
whatever  it  receives  into  itself.  This  fusion  of  a  priori 
and  a  posteriori  elements  yields  us  the  so-called  objects 
of  sense — the  subjective  objects,  the  phenomena  or 
appearances  in  us — to  which  Kant  applies  the  term  ex 
perience,  and  to  which  he  limits  the  scope  of  our  cognition. 
It  will  be  seen  from  what  has  been  said  that  it  was 
not  primarily  the  subjective  origin  of  the  a  priori  prin 
ciples  that  led  Kant  to  pronounce  our  knowledge  merely 
phenomenal.  It  is  rather  to  our  sensuous  or  receptive 
attitude  in  cognition  that  the  phenomenalistic  taint  is 
due.  It  is  due  to  this  fundamental  characteristic  of 
human  intelligence,  rather  than  to  any  defect  inherent 
in  themselves,  that  the  categories  are  strictly  limited  to 
a  phenomenal  or  subjective  world ;  they  are  empty, 
as  Kant  says,  without  the  filling  of  sense.  But  though 
Kant's  phenomenalism  has  thus  its  roots  in  his  view  of 
the  a  posteriori  even  more  than  in  his  account  of  the 
a  priori,  his  theory  of  the  a  priori  is  unquestionably 


214-  BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

what  gives  his  system  its  distinctive  character.  But  for 
mathematics  and  physics  and  Hume's  sceptical  analysis 
of  necessary  truth,  Kant  might  have  remained  content 
with  a  theory  like  Locke's.  Locke  gives  a  substantially 
similar  account  of  a  posteriori  knowledge,  but  the  scep 
tical  implications  of  '  the  theory  of  ideas  '  have  not  yet 
developed  themselves.  The  connection  is  closer  between 
the  ideas  and  their  real  causes  or  prototypes — which 
Locke,  indeed,  believes  them  faithfully  to  represent,  so 
far  at  least,  as  the  primary  qualities  are  concerned.  The 
elaboration  of  the  a  priori  element  by  Kant,  and  the 
prominence  given  to  it  in  the  constitution  of  the  so- 
called  object  of  sense,  inevitably  widens  the  gulf  between 
ideas  and  things,  between  the  phenomenon  and  the 
thing-in-itself.  The  phenomenal  object,  drawing  so 
many  of  its  determinations  from  the  subject,  becomes 
detached  from  the  object  whose  appearance  it  is  sup 
posed  to  be,  but  which,  be  it  observed,  it  no  longer 
represents.  It  becomes  a  satellite  of  the  mind,  a  mental 
object.  And  eventually,  under  cover  of  the  ambiguous 
terms  '  object '  and  '  experience/  it  assumes  a  quasi- 
independence  of  the  mind  also,  and  is  then  ready  to  do 
duty  for  the  real  things  of  science  and  common  life. 

We  need  not  wonder,  then,  that  in  the  course  of  the 
exposition,  the  thing-in-itself,  the  transcendent  cause  of 
our  experience,  falls  into  the  background.  It  falls  into 
the  background  not  because  it  is  any  the  less  supposed 
to  be  there,  but  because  Kant  is  not  interested  in  the 
particular  matter  of  sense  of  which  it  is  the  source  and 
explanation.  He  is  altogether  absorbed  in  vindicating, 
in  view  of  Hume,  the  universal  and  necessary  elements 
of  experience.  He  has  to  show  how  by  the  aid  of  certain 
mentally  supplied  principles  of  synthesis — and  only  by 
their  aid — the  discontinuous  and  unconnected  particu 
lars  of  sense  are  worked  up  into  '  experience-objects,' 
and,  generally,  into  an  experience-cosmos  in  space  and 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       215 

time.  The  deduction  or  exposition  of  this  a  priori 
system  may  be  said  to  constitute  Kant's  whole  industry 
in  the  Critique.  The  a  posteriori  element,  though  equally 
necessary  to  experience  as  a  living  fact,  he  is  content 
to  refer  to  simply  as  given — given  from  another  source, 
as  he  says  somewhat  curtly  in  the  press  of  his  investiga 
tion  into  the  a  priori.  The  infrequency  of  reference  to 
this  other  source  is  the  less  to  be  wondered  at,  seeing 
that  the  thing-in-itself  had  become  attenuated,  under 
the  influence  of  Kant's  presuppositions,  into  no  more 
than  the  unknown  cause  or  correlate  of  our  sense- 
impressions — "  a  notion  so  imperfect,"  according  to 
Hume,  "  that  no  sceptic  will  think  it  worth  while  to 
contend  against  it."  1  As  nothing  could  be  said  of  the 
sense-matter  until  it  was  formed,  the  thing-in-itself 
seemed  merely  to  furnish  the  prick  of  sense  that  set  the 
a  priori  machinery  in  motion.  Kant  himself  says  in 
the  Aesthetic,  with  a  kind  of  naive  triumph,  that  the 
thing-in-itself  is  never  asked  for  in  experience.  In 
short  it  is  completely  obscured,  and  its  place  practically 
taken,  by  the  subjective  or  experience-object  which 
Kant  constructs,  and  which  he  interposes,  as  it  were, 
between  us  and  it. 

It  is  high  time,  therefore,  to  inquire  narrowly  into  the 
nature  of  this  '  experience  '  which  tends  to  swallow  up 
everything  else  in  Kant,  and  which,  in  the  mouths  of 
his  more  recent  followers,  becomes  a  magic  and  all- 
sufficing  formula. 

Experience  is  distinguished,  on  the  one  hand,  from 
mere  sensation.  Kant  holds,  and  rightly  holds,  that 
from  particular  impressions  of  passive  sensation  alone 
no  knowledge  could  possibly  arise.  These  sensations, 
if  they  exist,  are  unknowable ;  they  become  elements 
of  knowledge  only  when  actively  seized  and  rationally 
interpreted  by  the  mind.  Knowledge  implies,  besides 

1  Enquiry,  section  12. 


2i6      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

the  stimulus  of  sense,  a  nucleus  of  primitive  judgments, 
which  involve  the  basal  category  of  cause  and  ultimately 
the  whole  structure  of  reason.  If,  therefore,  sensation, 
or  the  sense-stimulus,  be  styled  subjective  or  merely 
subjective,  then  the  cognitions  or  perceptions *  which 
are  thus  constituted  out  of  the  impressions  by  the 
a  priori  resources  of  the  mind  may  be  said  to  be,  in 
comparison,  objective — that  is  to  say,  they  are  not 
merely  internal  states  of  the  subject,  indistinguishably 
fused,  as  it  were,  in  its  inner  life  ;  they  are  objects  or 
presentations  which  have  a  relative  permanence,  and 
which  may  be  contemplated,  so  to  speak,  at  arm's 
length.  They  are  objective,  however,  only  as  thus 
compared  with  sensations  (which  may  be  hypothetically 
denned  as  the  states  of  a  being  in  which  the  contrast 
of  subject  and  object  has  not  emerged,  and  for  which 
consequently  the  fact  of  knowledge  does  not  yet  exist). 
In  themselves,  as  perceptions,  they  are  still  subjective, 
still  modes  of  my  consciousness.  Their  objectivity  is 
an  immanent  or  subjective  objectivity,  as  compared 
with  the  transcendent  or  trans-subjective  objectivity  of 
independently  existing  things.  Indeed,  to  call  them  ob 
jects  is  perhaps  to  invite  misconception.  These  pheno 
menal  objects  are  more  probably  described  as  percepts, 
and  no  percept  carries  me,  so  far  as  its  own  existence  is 
concerned,  beyond  the  ring-fence  of  the  self.  Whatever 
reference  to  a  trans-subjective  world  my  percepts  may 
carry  with  them,  they  are,  as  percepts,  in  me  ;  they  are 
my  ideas,  in  the  wide  Lockian  sense  of  the  word,  my  Vor- 
stellungen,  as  Kant  so  often  says.  Adopting  the  favourite 
Kantian  expression,  we  might  say  that  experience,  just 
because  it  is  experienced,  is  eo  ipso  a  subjective  fact. 
Mediately,  of  course,  my  experience  is  the  only  means 
I  possess  of  passing  beyond  my  individual  subjectivity 

1  Kant's  distinction  between  cognitions  and  perceptions  is  not  here 
in  point. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       217 

to  the  trans-subjective  universe  of  other  men  and 
things.  But  in  its  immediacy,  as  a  fact  of  consciousness 
doubt  of  which  is  impossible,  it  cannot  bridge  the  gulf 
between  the  subjective  and  the  trans-subjective.  The 
sceptical  question  would  never  have  been  asked,  if  trans- 
subjective  reality  were  already  present — immediately 
present  in  the  heart  of  consciousness.  But  it  is  presuming 
too  much  upon  the  ambiguity  of  words  to  ask  us  to 
accept  the  immanent  object  as  actually  being  the  tran 
scendent  object — the  real  thing.  The  subjective  object 
is  certainly,  like  faith,  the  evidence  of  that  trans- 
subjective  world.  It  is,  we  may  hold,  the  substantial 
and  sufficient  evidence,  but  the  one  is  not  the  other. 
If  the  one  were  the  other,  doubt,  as  I  have  said,  would 
be  impossible  and  to  lead  evidence  would  be  ridiculous. 
Hence  when  Kant  argues,  as  he  so  often  does,  that  his 
system  is  immeasurably  superior  to  the  problematical 
Idealism  of  most  philosophers,  his  speech  bewrayeth 
him.  His  very  insistence  on  the  fact  that,  in  his  system, 
doubt  of  the  existence  of  material  things  is  impossible — 
that  he  is  as  certain  of  the  existence  of  objects  in  space 
as  he  is  of  any  fact  of  the  internal  sense — -only  proves 
that  these  material  things  in  space  are  simply  my 
spatially  arranged  perceptions.  Space  and  all  its  con 
tents,  as  he  is  so  fond  of  saying,  are  only  phenomena  of 
my  consciousness,  only  ideas  in  me.  Kant's  immediately 
known  real  things  in  space  recall,  in  fact,  Berkeley's 
very  similar  protestations  that  he  is  placing  reality  upon 
a  firmer  basis  than  ever  before.  Others  may  doubt 
whether  matter  exists  or  not ;  for  his  part,  he  has 
immediate  certainty  on  the  point.  Berkeley  plainly 
availed  himself  in  this  of  something  like  a  double  entendre  ; 
he  endeavoured  to  substitute  the  perception,  or  the 
object  immediately  present  to  consciousness,  for  the 
trans-subjective  real  of  which  it  is  the  perception.  But 
the  trans-subjective  to  which  all  subjective  facts  refer 


218       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

is  not  thus  to  be  got  rid  of.  Berkeley  restores  it  in  another 
form  ;  Hume  himself,  in  the  Enquiry,  seems  inclined  to 
leave  it  standing  in  the  attenuated  form  of  "  a  certain 
unknown,  inexplicable  something  "  ;  and  in  this  shape 
it  is  retained  by  Kant  as  the  thing-in-itself.  For  the 
counterstroke  of  all  this  somewhat  mystifying  talk  on 
Kant's  part  about  real  things  in  space  is  his  reminder 
that  these  objects  are,  after  all,  only  phenomena  in 
consciousness.  Their  reality  is  only  empirical ;  and  as 
the  only  empirical  reality  of  which  we  can  intelligibly 
speak  is  the  process  as  it  passes  in  my  consciousness  or 
yours,  Kant  stands  practically  on  the  same  ground  as 
Berkeley.  The  only  difference  between  Berkeley's  ideas 
of  sense  and  Kant's  empirically  real  phenomena  lies  in 
Kant's  more  adequate  account  of  space  and  of  the 
intellectual  elements  involved  in  perception.  This  dif 
ference  is,  of  course,  fundamental,  and  Kant's  analysis 
may  probably  be  used  so  as  to  make  subjective  idealism 
definitely  untenable  ;  but  in  such  Kantian  passages  as 
those  to  which  I  have  referred,  it  does  not  lift  us  at  all 
beyond  the  Berkeleian  standpoint. 

I  have  just  said  that  the  only  sense  in  which  we  can 
intelligibly  speak  of  empirical  reality  is  to  designate  the 
process  as  it  passes  in  my  consciousness  or  yours.  But 
does  Kant  always  use  empirical  reality  and  experience 
(Erfahrimg)  in  this  sense  ?  Certainly  he  sometimes 
does,  and  perhaps  always  intended  to  do  so — though 
good  intentions  cannot  be  credited  in  philosophy.  In 
addition  to  many  incidental  statements,  emphasising 
the  subjective  character  of  these  so-called  objects,  refer 
ence  may  be  made  to  a  passage  which  has  all  the  appear 
ance  of  being  a  carefully  weighed  official  declaration  on 
the  subject.  I  mean  the  sixth  section  of  the  Antinomy 
of  Pure  Reason,  where  Kant,  according  to  the  title, 
brings  forward  his  "  transcendental  idealism  as  the  key 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM       219 

to  the  solution  of  the  cosmological  dialectic."  Here 
Kant  repeats  a  great  number  of  times  and  in  the  most 
explicit  fashion  this  purely  subjective  and  individualistic 
interpretation  of  experience.  "  It  has  been  sufficiently 
proved  in  the  Aesthetic,"  he  says,  "  that  everything  which 
is  perceived  in  space  and  time — all  objects,  therefore,  of 
our  possible  experience — are  nothing  but  phenomena, 
that  is,  mere  ideas,  which,  as  represented,  that  is  to 
say,  as  extended  beings  or  series  of  changes,  have  no 
self-subsistent  existence  beyond  our  thoughts.  .  .  .  The 
realist  in  a  transcendental  sense  makes  out  of  these 
modifications  of  our  sensibility  self-subsisting  things — 
makes  mere  ideas,  consequently,  into  things  in  them 
selves."  But  for  transcendental  idealism  "  space  itself 
and  time  and  all  phenomena  are  not  in  themselves 
things.  They  are  nothing  but  ideas,  and  cannot  exist 
at  all  beyond  our  mind  (ausser  unserem  Gemuth).  .  .  . 
That  there  may  be  inhabitants  in  the  moon,  although 
no  man  has  ever  perceived  them,  must  certainly  be 
allowed  ;  but  that  only  means  that  we  might  meet  with 
them  in  the  possible  progress  of  experience  ;  for  every 
thing  is  real  that  stands  in  one  context  with  a  percep 
tion  according  to  laws  of  empirical  progress.  They  are 
real,  therefore,  if  they  stand  in  an  empirical  connection 
with  my  actual  consciousness,  although  that  does  not 
make  them  real  in  themselves,  that  is,  apart  from  this 
progress  of  experience.  .  .  .  There  is  nothing  really 
given  us  except  the  perception  and  the  empirical  progress 
from  this  perception  to  other  possible  perceptions.  For 
in  themselves  phenomena,  as  mere  ideas,  are  real  only 
in  perception,  and  perception  is  in  fact  nothing  but  the 
reality  of  an  empirical  idea,  that  is,  a  phenomenon. 
To  call  a  phenomenon  a  real  thing  before  it  is  perceived 
means  either  that  in  the  progress  of  experience  we  must 
meet  with  such  a  perception,  or  it  means  nothing  at  all. 


220       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

.  .  .  Phenomena  are  not  anything  in  themselves  but 
mere  ideas,  which  when  they  are  not  given  to  us  (in 
perception)  are  not  met  with  anywhere  at  all." 

This  elaborate  passage  might  be  reinforced  by  many 
emphatic  expressions  on  Kant's  part  to  the  same  effect. 
Thus  he  warns  us  that  "  all  objects  without  exception 
with  which  we  busy  ourselves  are  in  me,  that  is,  deter 
minations  of  my  identical  self."  He  speaks  of  the  mind 
as  prescribing  laws  a  priori  to  nature,  and  of  nature  as 
submitting  to  the  legislation  of  the  understanding  ;  but 
he  smooths  the  paradox  for  us  by  reminding  us  that 
"  this  nature  is  in  itself  nothing  but  a  sum  of  phenomena, 
consequently  not  a  thing-in-itself  but  only  a  number  of 
ideas  in  my  mind  (eine  Menge  von  Vorstellungen  des 
Gemuths) . "  In  such  passages  there  is  no  mistaking  Kant's 
meaning  ;  even  in  his  phraseology  he  recalls  Berkeley 
and  Mill,  except  that  for  associated  sensations  we  have 
rationally  constructed  perceptions.  Otherwise  Kant's 
phenomenal  world  of  present  perceptions  and  possible 
perceptions  corresponds  exactly  to  Mill's  world  of  actual 
sensations  and  permanent  possibilities  of  sensation  or 
Berkeley's  world  of  actual  and  possible  sense-phenomena. 
The  recurring  phrase  of  the  Critique,  "  possible  experi 
ence,"  is  itself  significant  of  the  affinity  of  standpoint. 
It  may  be  observed  also  that  when  this  view  is  firmly 
held,  as  in  the  long  section  quoted  from  the  Dialectic, 
"  the  non-sensuous  cause  of  these  ideas  "  "  the  tran 
scendental  object  "  —reappears,  as  if  Kant,  like  Berkeley, 
found  it  necessary  to  give  a  permanent  background  to 
what  would  otherwise  be  too  palpably  a  flickering, 
intermittent  and  disconnected  existence  in  the  shape  of 
experiences  of  this  or  the  other  individual  consciousness. 

But  it  is  equally  certain  that,  at  other  times,  the 
non-sensuous  cause  falls  into  the  background  with  Kant, 
and  he  speaks  of  the  phenomenal  objects  in  a  way  that 
ill  accords  with  the  purely  subjective  existence  which  is 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       221 

all  he  here  allows  them.  Kant  has  told  us  himself  that 
material  objects,  or  the  phenomena  of  the  external 
sense,  "  have  this  deceptive  characteristic  about  them 
that,  as  they  represent  objects  in  space,  they  detach 
themselves,  as  it  were,  from  the  soul,  and  appear  to 
hover  outside  of  it  " — "  although  (as  he  proceeds)  space 
itself  in  which  they  are  perceived  is  nothing  but  an 
idea,  whose  counterpart  is  not  to  be  met  with  in  the 
same  quality  outside  of  the  soul."  l  In  spite  of  this 
caveat  about  the  subjectivity  of  space,  it  is  impossible 
to  read  the  Critique  carefully  without  becoming  aware 
that  this  deceptive  characteristic  of  our  spatial  percep 
tions — this  subtle  detachment  of  themselves  from  con 
sciousness — has  its  influence  upon  Kant  himself.  Kant 
does  not  habitually  think  of  his  phenomenal  objects  as 
merely  subjective  experiences,  a  moment  here  then 
gone,  till  a  similar  experience  occurs  in  my  own  or  in 
some  other  human  subjectivity.  He  talks  with  some 
scorn  of  those  who  "  hypostatise  ideas  and  transfer 
them  outside  of  themselves  as  real  things,"  2  but  he  may 
easily  be  shown  to  fall  under  his  own  censure.  It  is 
already  dangerous  to  speak,  as  he  does  in  the  Aesthetic, 
of  ideas  as  having  external  things  for  their  objects, 
when  the  true  state  of  the  case,  on  the  Kantian  theory, 
is  that  the  ideas — i.e.,  our  spatial  perceptions — are  the 
external  things.  So,  a  few  pages  later,  he  defines  our 
perception  as  the  idea  or  representation  of  phenomenon 
(Anschauung  =  Vorstellung  von  Erscheinung),  where  the 
perception  is  not  identified  with  the  phenomenon,  but 
is  said  to  be  a  perception  of  it,  as  if  the  phenomenon 
existed  independently  of  the  conscious  process.  Such 
questionable  expressions  might  be  quoted  in  large 
numbers,  but  that  is  the  less  necessary,  seeing  that  the 
fallacy  is  traceable  to  the  leading  determinations  of  his 

1  Werke,  III.  608  (ed.  Hartenstein) . 

2  Ibid.,  p.  611. 


222       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

own  scheme  in  the  Analytic.  It  is  in  the  Analytic  that 
the  ambiguous  use  of  the  terms  '  object '  and  '  objective/ 
to  which  reference  has  been  made,  reaches  its  height- 
one  consequence  of  which  is  that  the  real  thing  to  which 
reference  is  made  in  knowledge  is  temporarily  shouldered 
out  of  the  system.  We  are  told  that  objects  are  made 
by  the  superinduction  of  the  categories  and  the  forms 
of  intuition  upon  the  matter  of  sense.  Such  objects,  it 
is  true,  are  still  phenomenal  or  purely  subjective- 
subjective  matter  of  sense  shot  through  with  subjective 
forms  of  thought — but  they  are  insensibly  thought  of 
as  having  a  permanence  which  does  not  belong  to  the 
come-and-go  of  our  subjective  experiences  ;  we  are  led 
to  regard  them,  not  as  individual  perceptions  of  indi 
vidual  subjects,  but  as  objects  valid  or  existent  for  all. 
This  idea  of  objectivity  as  universal  validity — validity 
for  all  human  beings  or  for  consciousness  in  general- 
becomes  of  determining  importance  for  the  Kantian 
thought,  and  in  it  all  the  ambiguities  of  the  system 
meet. 

Recognition  by  other  consciousnesses,  it  may  be  freely 
admitted,  is  an  all-important  test  of  trans-subjective 
reality.  That  which  is  recognised  by  others  certifies 
itself  to  me  as  an  objective  or  trans-subjective  fact,  not 
a  subjective  fancy.  The  recognition  is  a  decisive  ratio 
cognoscendi  of  its  independent  existence,  but,  conversely, 
it  is  the  existence  of  a  trans-subjective  reality  that  is 
the  ratio  essendi  of  the  recognition.  That,  at  any  rate, 
is  the  only  hypothesis  which  can  be  got  to  work  with 
more  than  superficial  plausibility.  Because  an  inde 
pendent  fact  exists,  everybody  recognises  it ;  but  no 
multiplication  of  subjective  recognitions  can  in  them 
selves  manufacture  a  real  object  in  any  other  than  a 
Berkeleian  sense.  To  Kant,  however,  by  the  help  of 
this  conception  of  validity,  the  phenomenal  object 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       223 

acquires  a  quasi-independence ;  it  seems  to  become 
more  than  the  actual  and  possible  subjective  experiences 
of  individual  conscious  beings — something  of  which  the 
individuals  have  ideas,  and  to  which  their  ideas  must 
conform.  Erfahrung,  or  experience,  a  term  which  should 
expressly  emphasise  the  subjectivity,  comes  to  signify 
for  Kant,  perhaps  unconsciously,  a  stable  and  connected 
world  of  things,  identified  neither  with  the  intermittent 
cognitions  of  individual  subjects  on  the  one  hand  nor 
with  the  admittedly  trans-subjective  world  of  things-in- 
themselves  on  the  other.  Sometimes,  as  in  the  passages 
already  quoted,  Kant  rouses  himself  and  emphatically 
declares  that  this  world  of  experience  is  only  "  a  play 
of  ideas  "  in  us  ;  but  at  other  times  he  clothes  it  with 
all  the  permanence  and  independence  which  the  ordinary 
man  attributes  to  real  things.  And  when  he  says  that 
no  inquiry  is  made  in  experience  after  the  trans-subjective 
reality,  that  is  true  only  because  he  has  virtually  installed 
the  phenomenal  object  in  its  place.  If  the  phenomenal 
object  were  consistently  understood  as  the  percept  or 
cognition  of  an  individual  subject,  it  would  be  absurd 
to  say  that  in  experience  we  rest  content  with  that ;  its 
dependent  and  explanation-craving  character  would  be 
too  apparent. 

It  need  hardly  be  added  that  there  is  no  justification 
for  the  intermediate  position  of  quasi-independence  in 
sinuated  by  Kant.  The  object  of  consciousness  in  general, 
or  the  social  object,  is  in  itself  a  pure  abstraction.  It 
expresses  an  agreement  in  content  between  a  number 
of  cognitions  which,  as  far  as  they  are  real  facts,  exist 
in  as  many  numerically  distinct  consciousnesses.  There 
is  no  '  consciousness  in  general/  and  consequently  its 
object  cannot  be  an  existent  entity  but  only  an  ens 
rationis.  But  although  this  seems  tolerably  plain  when 
thus  stated,  it  is  beyond  question  that  Erfahrung  or  the 


224      BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

world  of  phenomena  which  plays  such  an  important 
part  in  Kantian  literature  is  a  hybrid  conception  due 
largely  to  the  ambiguity  of  the  words  object  and  objective 
which  has  just  been  explained.  The  development  in  the 
hands  of  the  Neo-Kantians  of  this  conception  of  experi 
ence  as  the  exclusive  reality  will  show  us  the  danger  of 
departing  from  the  trans-subjective  reference  in  know 
ledge.  But  that  subject  must  be  pursued  in  a  separate 
lecture. 


LECTURE   IV. 

THE    EPISTEMOLOGY   OF   NEO-KANTIANISM   AND 
SUBJECTIVE   IDEALISM. 

IN  a  preceding  lecture  I  traced  the  insidious  extension 
given  by  Kant  to  the  term  '  experience/  in  virtue  of 
which  it  comes  to  mean  a  quasi-independent  world, 
identified  neither  with  the  facts  of  subjective  conscious 
ness  nor  with  trans-subjective  realities.  We  have  now 
to  follow  the  development  of  this  conception  of  experi 
ence  in  the  hands  of  the  Neo-Kantians.  In  their  hands 
it  soon  comes  to  figure  as  the  exclusive  reality,  and  the 
nature  of  their  results  will  show  us  the  danger  of  depart 
ing  from  the  trans-subjective  reference  in  knowledge. 

In  Kant,  as  we  have  seen,  this  reference  remains,  but 
the  experience-object  thrusts  the  trans-subjective  reality 
more  and  more  into  the  background.  Its  existence 
became,  therefore,  the  first  point  upon  which  the  Kantian 
system  was  assailed.  Jacobi,  Aenesidemus-Schultze, 
Maimon  and  Beck  agree  in  pointing  out  the  inconsistency 
of  the  thing-in-itself  with  other  fundamental  principles 
of  Kant's  philosophy.  Jacobi's  saying  is  well  known, 
that  "  without  the  supposition  of  the  thing-in-itself  it  is 
impossible  to  find  one's  way  into  the  system,  and  with 
this  presupposition  it  is  impossible  to  remain  in  it." 
For  if  causality  is  a  category  of  subjective  origin  and 
merely  immanent  application,  it  must  be  a  flagrant 
transgression  of  the  first  principles  of  Criticism  to  apply 
it,  in  this  transcendent  reference,  to  the  action  of  things- 

P 


226      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

in-themselves.  To  Fichte  it  was  simply  incredible  that 
Kant  could  ever  have  meant  to  make  such  an  assertion  ; 
and  accordingly  he  regarded  the  thing-in-itself  as  posited 
by  the  ego — that  is  to  say,  merely  as  a  reflection  of  the 
ego,  as  a  moment  in  the  ego's  own  creative  thought. 
The  development  of  speculative  thought  which  im 
mediately  followed  Kant  in  Germany  presents,  indeed, 
an  interesting  parallel  in  some  respects  to  the  fate  of 
Lockianism  in  England — a  parallel  which  may  just  be 
alluded  to  in  passing.  If  Kant  with  his  fundamental 
dualism  may  be  regarded  for  a  moment  as  a  new  edition 
of  Locke,  then  Fichte  may  be  compared  to  Berkeley. 
Like  Berkeley  his  main  polemic  is  against  the  object  as 
a  thing-in-itself,  but  he  leaves,  or  seems  to  leave,  the 
subject  as  a  metaphysical  reality  and  force.  With 
Hegel,  however,  the  subject — "  the  empty  ego,"  as  he 
calls  it — is  merged  in  the  process  of  its  own  predicates  ; 
and  the  way  in  which  the  Hegelians  of  the  Left  sub 
stantiate  categories  as  the  only  real  existences  recalls 
Hume's  resolution  of  the  universe  into  naked  ideas. 
But  the  Neo-Kantians  belong  to  our  own  generation, 
and  the  lesson  of  their  speculations  will,  therefore,  be 
more  instructive. 

Neo-Kantianism  admits  the  necessary  reference  of  per 
ception  to  a  thing-in-itself,  but  this  very  reference,  the 
Neo-Kantians  go  on  to  say,  is  itself  a  subjective  necessity. 
It  is  a  form  of  our  thought,  comparable  to  the  necessity 
we  feel  to  employ  the  category  of  substance  to  unify 
qualities  or  the  category  of  causality  to  bring  connection 
into  a  world  of  detached  objects.  In  like  manner,  the 
thing-in-itself  is  the  ultimate  notion  or  category  by 
which  we  round  off  external  experience.  In  short,  Kant 
has  proved  that  the  idea  of  the  thing-in-itself  or  the  tran 
scendental  object  is  a  necessary  element  in  experience  ; 
but  to  treat  this  idea  as  a  thing  is  a  lapse  into  Dogmatism 
at  which  the  Neo-Kantian  holds  up  his  hands  in  pious 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM       227 

horror.  In  support  of  this  rendering  of  the  critical 
theory,  several  passages  are  adduced  from  Kant  which, 
though  susceptible  of  an  entirely  different  interpretation, 
undoubtedly  seem  to  favour  such  a  view.  Thus,  for 
example,  in  the  chapter  on  Phenomena  and  Noumena 
in  the  first  edition  of  the  Critique,  Kant  speaks  of  "  the 
transcendental  object "  as  "  a  something  =  x,  of  which 
we  know  nothing  at  all  and  can  know  nothing  (accord 
ing  to  the  present  structure  of  our  understanding),  but 
which  can  only  serve  as  a  correlate  of  the  unity  of  apper 
ception,  to  establish  that  unity  of  the  manifold  in  sensuous 
perception,  by  means  of  which  the  understanding  unites 
that  manifold  in  the  conception  of  an  object.  This 
transcendental  object  cannot  be  separated  from  the 
data  of  sense,  because  in  that  case  nothing  remains  over 
by  which  to  think  it.  It  is  therefore  not  an  object  of 
knowledge  in  itself,  but  only  the  idea  of  phenomena  under 
the  conception  of  an  object  in  general,  which  is  determined 
by  the  manifold  of  the  phenomena."  I  have  italicised 
the  most  striking  phrases,  and  it  will  be  observed  that 
there  is  little  here  to  distinguish  the  so-called  "  tran 
scendental  object  "  from  that  permanent  in  perception 
(substantia  phenomenon)  which  Kant  proves  elsewhere 
to  be  the  foundation  of  our  experience  of  objects  and  a 
correlate  or  reflex  of  the  unity  of  apperception.  The 
thing-in-itself  is  described  as  the  correlate  of  the  unity 
of  apperception,  and  the  functions  of  the  two  are  not 
distinguished.  Both  the  unity  of  apperception  and  the 
transcendental  object  are  there  "  to  establish  a  unity  in 
the  manifold  of  sense-perception." 

Founding  on  this  and  similar  passages,  and  combining 
them,  as  he  believes,  into  a  consistent  meaning,  Cohen 
says  that  the  transcendental  object,  as  distinct  from  the 
idea  of  the  transcendental  object,  does  not  concern  us 
at  all.  Such  an  object  would  be  transcendent,  and  in 
this  positive  sense  is  to  be  denied.  The  object  is  called 


228       BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

transcendental  to  signify  that,  by  the  constitution  of 
our  thinking  function,  it  necessarily  intrudes  itself. 
But  this  notion  of  an  object-in-general  which  underlies, 
as  it  were,  all  particular  empirical  objects  is  nothing  but 
the  formal  unity  of  consciousness  expressing  itself 
through  the  categories,  and  now  reflecting  itself  back 
from  the  objective  world  of  perception  thus  constituted. 
He  quotes  a  passage  from  Kant  which,  taken  by  itself, 
agrees  almost  verbally  with  what  he  has  just  said : 
'  The  pure  notion  of  this  transcendental  object  (which 
really  in  all  our  cognitions  is  the  same  =  x)  is  that 
which  in  all  our  empirical  notions  is  able  to  yield  refer 
ence  to  an  object — that  is,  objective  reality.  Now  this 
notion  can  contain  no  definite  percept,  and  will  therefore 
refer  to  nothing  except  the  unity  which  must  be  met 
with  in  a  manifold  of  cognition,  so  far  as  it  stands  in 
relation  to  an  object.  This  reference,  however,  is  nothing 
else  than  the  necessary  unity  of  consciousness."  x  ''  When 
the  Copernican  criticism/'  Cohen  proceeds,  "  brought  to 
light  the  true  movement  of  the  object  round  the  forms 
of  the  mind,  it  disclosed  at  the  same  time  the  ground  of 
the  natural  phenomenon  that  we  make  the  common 
correlate2  our  senses  and  our  understanding  into  an 
absolute  (zum  Absoluten  der  Natur).  And  this  pheno 
menon  of  our  thought  proves  itself  to  be  so  natural  that, 
although  it  is  recognised,  it  still  retains  its  deceptive 
power.  Just  as,  in  spite  of  Copernicus,  the  sun  still 
appears  to  the  senses  to  move,  so  the  transcendental 
illusion  of  the  absolute  object  remains,  although  we  know 
perfectly  well  that  it  radiates  from  the  forms  of  our 
self."  "  The  noumenon  of  substance  is,  and  is  intended 
to  be,  nothing  more  than  the  extended  category  (die 
erweiterte  Categorie)."  "The  object  in  the  background, 
the  absolute  thing-in-itself,  the  supposed  cause  of  the 

\ 

1  Deduction  of  the  Categories  in  the  first  edition.     Werke,  III.  573 
(ed.  Hartenstein,  1867). 

2  [The  word  "  of  "  appears  to  have  dropped  out. — ED.] 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM      229 

phenomenon  .  .  .  has  shown  itself  to  be  the  veritable 
creature  of  the  understanding — has  shown  itself  indeed 
so  veritable  a  creature  that  the  illusion  cannot  be  dis 
pelled.  In  possible  experience,  that  is,  in  constructive 
perception  and  in  the  self-thought  (sdbstgedachten) 
notions  of  the  understanding,  lies  all  reality,  even  that 
reality  which  would  fain  be  more."  1  In  exactly  the 
same  spirit,  Lange,  who  was  largely  influenced  by  Cohen, 
denies  that  our  perceptions  come  about  through  affection 
of  the  sensibility  by  transcendent  things-in-themselves  ; 
he  only  allows  that  our  mental  organisation  is  such  that 
it  appears  so  to  us.  Our  whole  experience  is  in  Lange 's 
phrase,  "  the  product  of  our  organisation."  "  A  judg 
ment  referring  to  the  thing-in-itself  has  no  other  meaning 
than  to  round  off  the  circle  of  our  ideas."  2  • 

So  far,  however,  the  ego  still  remains  as  a  reality — a 
bearer  or  supporter  of  this  subjective  world  of  experience  ; 
or,  to  use  the  Copernican  metaphor  of  which  Cohen  is 
so  fond,  the  ego  remains  as  the  central  sun  round  which 
objects  revolve.  And  certainly  it  does  not  at  first  appear 
how  this  self-contained  subjective  world  is  to  subsist 
without  at  least  this  amount  of  foothold  upon  reality. 
That  only  proves,  however,  that  we  have  not  realised 
the  inexorable  logic  of  this  line  of  thought.  It  will  be 
noticed  that  Cohen  is  careful,  in  the  above  quotations, 
to  speak  of  Kant's  discovery  as  making  the  objects 
revolve  "  round  the  forms  of  the  mind,"  round  notions, 
not  round  the  ego  or  subject.  To  speak  of  the  ego  in 
this  explicit  fashion  as  a  reality  would  be  to  assert  the 
existence  of  the  ego  as  something  more  than  simply  a 
function  or  aspect  of  conscious  experience  ;  and  that 
would  be  to  commit  the  unpardonable  sin  (in  Neo- 

1  Kant's  Theorie  der  Erfahrung,  p.  253.     I  quote   from  the  first 
edition  of  1871.     I  do  not  know  how  far  Professor  Cohen  may  have 
modified  his  views  or  expressions  subsequently.    I  am  concerned  with 
his  position  only   as  illustrating  the   consistent   development   of   a 
particular  line  of  thought. 

2  Geschichte  des  Materialismus,  II.  126. 


23o       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

Kantian  eyes)  of  "  overstepping  the  bounds  of  possible 
experience/'  and  setting  up  a  transcendent  thing-in- 
itself  as  substance  or  cause.  For,  in  point  of  fact,  the 
reality  of  the  subject  stands  here  upon  exactly  the  same 
basis  as  the  reality  of  the  object.  The  transcendental 
object,  according  to  the  argument  we  have  just  followed, 
is  merely  a  notion  or  category  which  gives  the  finishing 
touch  to  our  subjective  experience-world — by  which,  as 
Lange  says,  we  round  it  off — but  which  cannot  possibly 
carry  us  out  of  this  experience-world  to  a  Beyond. 
According  to  this  purely  immanent  Criticism,  such  a 
Beyond  simply  does  not  exist.  Now  the  subject  is  in 
like  manner  a  notion  or  category — the  notion  of  notions, 
the  category  of  categories,  if  you  will — but  still  just  the 
ultimate  notion  which  puts  the  dot  upon  the  i,  and  gives 
the  finishing  touch  to  experience.  Many  passages  may 
be  quoted  from  Kant  as  evidence  that  he  regarded  the 
transcendental  unity  of  apperception  as  a  form  evolved 
in  the  process  of  experience,  and  a  pure  abstraction, 
therefore,  when  separated  from  the  process  whose 
formal  unity  it  constitutes.  Ignoring  the  difference 
which  exists  for  Kant  between  the  transcendental  unity 
and  the  noumenal  self,  Cohen  is  not  slow  to  utilise  such 
passages.  "  The  ego,"  he  says,  "  is  so  far  from  being  a 
substance,  understood  as  a  special  productive  faculty, 
that  it  is  resolved  into  a  process  in  which  it  arises  and 
which  it  is.  The  unity  of  the  action  is  at  the  same  time 
the  unity  of  consciousness/' 1  He  recalls  to  us  that 
Kant  even  abstracts  from  the  actual  existence  of  the 
ego — in  his  frequent  references — namely,  to  the  '  I 
think  '  which  must  be  capable  of  accompanying  all  my 
thoughts.  What  kind  of  faculty  is  that,  asks  Cohen, 
whose  actual  existence  or  non-existence  may  be  dis 
regarded  ?  Taking  Kant's  own  example,  he  proceeds  : 
"  The  transcendental  ego  is  a  form  of  synthesis.  .  .  . 

1  Kant's  Theorie  der  Erfahrung,  p.  142. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   231 

The  unity  of  consciousness  arises  in  the  synthesis  of  the 
drawing  of  a  line,  and  this  synthesis  consists  in  the 
notion  of  quantity  under  which  the  line  is  subsumed. 
Thus  the  transcendental  apperception  falls  together 
with  the  synthetic  unity  which  is  contained  in  the  cate 
gory.  ...  As  space  is  the  form  of  external  perception 
and  time  of  internal,  so  the  transcendental  apperception 
is  the  form  of  the  categories.  .  .  .  The  synthetic  unity 
is  the  form  which  lies  as  a  common  element  at  the  basis 
of  all  the  separate  kinds  of  unities  thought  in  the 
categories.  The  transcendental  unity  of  apperception 
(in  Kant's  own  words)  is  the  unity  through  which  all  the 
manifold  given  in  perception  is  united  in  a  notion  of  the 
object." 

Here  the  wheel  has  come  full  circle.  The  tran 
scendental  object  was  first  reduced  to  a  radiation  or 
reflection  of  the  subject,  and  now  the  subject  has  become 
merely  the  unity  of  the  object.  Both,  in  fact,  are  simply 
forms  assumed  by  this  "  one  all-embracing  experience  " 
(to  use  a  phrase  of  Kant's  on  which  Cohen  naturally 
lays  stress).  They  are  not  really  separate  facts  or  even 
separate  forms  ;  they  are  the  Janus-faces  of  a  single 
fact  called  experience.  Subject  and  object  are  forms 
which  this  experience  necessarily  takes,  and,  as  such, 
they  are  described  as  transcendental  conditions  of  the 
possibility  of  experience,  but  they  have  no  existence  or 
meaning  apart  from  this  immanent  reference  to  the 
experience  whose  forms  they  are.  As  Cohen  says,  sum 
marising  his  own  position,  "  the  form  is  not  a  primitive 
action  ;  it  is  a  form  in  the  sum  of  psychical  occurrence 
(im  psychischen  Gesammtgeschehen) ,  a  form  which  pre 
supposes  other  processes  and  coincides  with  part  of 
them."1  The  transcendental  subject,  therefore,  as  a 
real  source  and  locus  of  experience,  goes  the  way  of  the 
transcendental  object.  It  is  just  a  form  which  the 

1  Kant's  Theorie  der  Erfahrung,  p.  162. 


232   BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

current  of  psychical  events  has  a  way  of  taking,  but 
from  which  we  can  infer  no  real  being  behind  the  psychi 
cal  flux,  whose  the  experience  is,  or  to  whom  the  appear 
ance  appears.  As  soon  as  we  attempt  to  do  so,  we 
become  the  victims,  according  to  Neo-Kantianism,  of 
an  illusion  precisely  similar  to  that  described  by  Cohen 
in  the  case  of  the  object.  But  though  Cohen,  as  we  have 
seen,  follows  the  same  line  of  argument  in  both  cases, 
and  reduces  subject  and  object  alike  to  forms  of  thought 
to  which  no  trans-subjective  reality  corresponds,  he 
stops  short  of  branding  the  subject  also  as  an  illusion. 
He  does  not  write  in  a  sceptical  interest ;  he  proposes 
this  self-rounding  world  of  Erfahmng  or  experience  as 
the  one  and  all-sufficient  reality.  Kant's  supposed 
"  theory  of  experience  "  is  consistent  Criticism — the 
latest  birth  of  philosophy ;  and  accordingly  it  would 
be  stultifying  himself  to  speak  of  illusion,  in  so  many 
words,  in  connection  with  the  supreme  form  of  ex 
perience. 

Nevertheless  it  is  perfectly  apparent  that  the  whole 
structure  hangs  in  the  air.  This  purely  immanent  refer 
ence  of  the  categories  and  forms  of  thought  leaves  us 
with  no  real  being  whose  the  experience  is.  This  '  ex 
perience  '  or  Erfahmngswelt  has  no  locus  ;  it  evolves 
itself  in  vacuo,  and  in  the  course  of  its  evolution  evolves 
the  form  of  personality.  Lange,  who  otherwise  adopted 
Cohen's  results  as  true  Kantianism  and  true  philosophy, 
was  disturbed  by  this  lack  of  any  real  basis,  and  entered 
a  mild  protest  against  it.  "If  the  emphasising  of  the 
merely  transcendental  standpoint  be  carried  too  far,  we 
arrive  at  the  tautology  that  experience  is  to  be  ex 
plained  from  the  conditions  of  possible  experience  in 
general— that  the  synthesis  a  priori  has  its  cause  in  the 
synthesis  a  priori."  *  By  the  merely  transcendental 
standpoint  Lange  means  what  I  have  just  called  the 

1  Geschichte  des  Materialismus,  II.  126,  131. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM      233 

purely  immanent  or  inward  reference  of  the  categories 
and  forms  of  thought — the  proof,  for  example,  which 
deduces  a  unity  as  the  condition  of  synthesis,  but  which 
can  say  nothing  of  the  unity  apart  from  the  act  or 
movement  of  synthesis  of  which  it  is,  as  it  were,  the 
moving  form.  Such  a  proof,  Lange  says,  in  analysing 
experience  or  knowledge  into  conditions  which  are  con 
fessedly  abstractions  except  as  realised  in  the  act  or 
fact  of  knowledge,  is  really  explaining  experience  by 
itself — is  at  all  events  giving  no  account  of  the  real 
conditions  on  which  the  existence  of  experience  at  all 
depends.  Hence,  he  says,  if  the  transcendental  deduc 
tion  is  to  be  more  than  the  tautology  indicated  above, 
"  the  categories  must  necessarily  be  something  more 
than  simply  conditions  of  experience/'  In  other  words, 
he  is  seemingly  not  content  to  speak  with  Cohen  of  '  the 
notions  '  round  which  objects  revolve.  The  realistic 
basis  of  the  categories  lay  for  Kant  himself,  of  course, 
in  the  noumenal  self  ;  but  for  this  Lange  proposes  to 
substitute  '  the  physico-psychic  organisation '  as  the 
source  from  which  spring  all  the  forms,  notions  and 
Ideas  which  give  rise  to  the  appearance  of  a  world  in 
space  and  time.  The  physico-psychic  organisation  is 
thus  the  cause  or  ground  of  the  appearance,  and  at  the 
same  time  it  is  that  to  which  the  appearance  appears, 
and  thus  we  seem  to  secure  a  certain  anchorage.  But 
Lange  has  learned  his  Neo-Kantian  lesson  too  well  to 
admit  that  this  organisation  is  a  thing-in-itself.  The 
physico-psychical  organisation  is  itself  only  an  appear 
ance  or  phenomenon,  though  it  may  be  the  appearance 
of  an  unknown  thing-in-itself.  Hartmann  has  wittily 
but  not  unjustly  dubbed  this  position  of  Lange's  mere 
Confusionism.1  If  the  organisation  is  mere  appearance, 
we  are  no  better  off  than  we  were  with  Cohen  ;  if,  on 

In  his  Neukantianismus,  Schopenhauerianismus  und  Hegelianismus 


234      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

the  other  hand,  we  are  going  to  speak  of  a  real  being  at 
all,  this  problematical  way  of  referring  to  it  is  absurd. 
It  is  impossible  to  blow  hot  and  cold  in  this  fashion  with 
a  '  perhaps.'  Our  view  must  either  be  frankly  immanent, 
in  which  case  the  subject  is  merely  an  epistemological 
category,  or  it  must  be  frankly  transcendent,  in  which 
case  the  subject  is  the  real  being  in  whom  and  for  whom 
the  whole  process  of  experience  or  knowledge  takes  place. 
Lange's  recoil  from  the  consequences  of  Cohen's  reason 
ings  throws  an  instructive  light  upon  the  nature  of  these 
consequences,  and  therefore  I  have  dwelt  upon  his  posi 
tion  perhaps  longer  than  its  own  merits  justify.  This 
whole  Neo-Kantian  point  of  view  is  reduced  to  consist 
ency  by  Vaihinger,1  who  exposes  the  contradiction  latent 
in  Lange's  idea  of  the  physico-psychic  organisation.  He 
points  out  with  inexorable  logic  that  to  hypostatise  the 
subject,  even  in  this  half-hearted  way,  is  to  fall  back 
into  what  Cohen  calls  Dogmatism  ;  the  subject  has  in 
this  respect  no  prerogative  over  the  object,  both  being 
alike  epistemological  categories,  limitative  conceptions. 
So  far,  it  may  be  said,  Cohen  had  already  gone.  Vaihinger 
differs  from  him,  or  advances  beyond  him,  in  that  his 
attitude  is  essentially  sceptical.  "  Critical  Scepticism," 
he  says,  is  the  real  result  of  the  Kantian  theory  of  know 
ledge.  The  result  of  Criticism  is  purely  negative ;  it 
is  the  self-dissolution  of  speculation  (Selbstzersetzung  der 
Speculation),  inasmuch  as  it  restricts  us  rigorously  to 
the  immediate  world  of  subjective  states.  All  philosophy, 
he  says  again,  has  only  intra-subjective  significance  ; 
all  thought  moves  in  subjective  forms  whose  objective 
validity  can  never  be  verified,  and  whatever  instruments 
we  employ  to  know  reality,  they  are  still  subjective  in 
their  nature.  Criticism,  therefore,  or  consistent  Kan 
tianism  denies  the  trans-subjective  validity  of  every 
category  and  form  of  thought,  and  thus  brings  us  back, 

1  In  his  book,  Hartmann,  Duhring  und  Lange  (1876). 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       235 

in  a  more  refined  form  perhaps,  to  the  position  of 
Hume.  Hume  devoted  the  greater  part  of  his  industry 
to  showing  how  the  illusion  of  a  real  world  and  a  real 
self  would  naturally  arise,  in  the  absence  of  the  cor 
responding  realities  ;  how  these  illusions  would  weave 
themselves  out  of  the  dance  of  detached  and  homeless 
ideas.  Similarly  Hartmann  has  appropriately  labelled 
this  last  result  of  Neo-Kantian  thought  Illusionism. 
"  Ideas,"  said  Reid,  in  view  of  Hume's  results,  "  were 
first  introduced  into  philosophy  in  the  humble  character 
of  images  or  representatives  of  things.  .  .  .  But  they 
have  by  degrees  supplanted  their  constituents  and  under 
mined  the  existence  of  everything  but  themselves.  .  .  . 
These  ideas  are  as  free  and  independent  as  the  birds  of 
the  air.  .  .  .  Yet,  after  all,  these  self -existent  and 
independent  ideas  look  pitifully  naked  and  destitute 
when  left  thus  alone  in  the  universe,  set  adrift  without 
a  rag  to  cover  their  nakedness."  In  exactly  the  same 
way,  though  along  different  lines,  '  experience/  which 
was  introduced  into  philosophy  in  a  doubly  dependent 
character,  as  the  experience  by  a  real  being  of  a  real 
world — experience,  which  by  the  very  structure  of  the 
term  seems  to  cry  aloud  for  a  real  subject  and  a  real 
object — has  substantiated  itself  as  the  sole  reality. 
First  the  object  disappears  before  negative  criticism, 
and  the  world,  as  Hartmann  puts  it,  is  transformed 
into  the  dream  of  a  dreamer ;  at  this  stage  we  have  a 
purely  subjective  Idealism  or  Solipsism.  Then  the  sub 
ject  shares  the  fate  of  the  object,  and  the  dream  of  a 
dreamer  becomes  a  dream  which  is  dreamt  by  nobody, 
but  which,  if  one  may  say  so,  dreams  itself,  and  among 
its  other  dream-forms  dreams  the  fiction  of  a  supposed 
dreamer.1  This  self -evolving,  unsupported,  unhoused 
illusion  is  all  that  exists,  t 

1  Cf.     Hartmann's     Kritische     Grundlegung    des     transcendentalen 
Realismus,  p.  47. 


236      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

I  am  not  aware  that  absolute  scepticism  or  absolute 
illusionism  admits  of  any  direct  logical  reply.  But  it 
has  hitherto  been  regarded,  not  only  by  the  common 
sense  but  by  the  enlightened  common  reason  of  man 
kind,  as  a  reductio  ad  absurdum  of  the  line  of  thought 
which  leads  to  it.  It  is  a  result  which  we  deliberately 
refuse  to  accept  as  true.  In  face,  however,  of  such  a 
sceptical  dissolution  of  reality,  we  do  not  merely  intrench 
ourselves  in  this  deliberate  refusal,  leaving  the  sceptic 
in  possession  of  the  intellectual  field.  The  nature  of 
the  result  leads  us  to  examine  the  nature  of  the  premises 
and  the  principles  of  argumentation  which  have  led  to 
it.  This  was  what  Kant  and  Reid  both  essayed  to  do 
in  face  of  the  Humian  scepsis.  Now  that  a  definite 
development  of  the  Kantian  Criticism  brings  us  face  to 
face  with  a  subtler  scepsis  of  the  same  description,  a 
similar  course  must  be  adopted  ;  we  must  endeavour  to 
lay  our  hand  upon  the  fundamental  presuppositions 
which  predetermined  the  evolution  of  thought  toward 
this  end.  In  a  preceding  lecture  we  saw  reason  to  believe 
that  this  was  to  be  found  in  the  unwarrantable  extension 
given  by  Kant  to  the  term  '  experience/  and  in  his  view 
of  the  merely  immanent  use  of  the  categories  and  forms 
of  thought.  It  is  this  idea  of  immanence  which,  in  the 
hands  of  his  idealistic  followers,  swallows  up  the  tran 
scendent  reference  involved  in  knowledge — a  reference 
still  maintained  by  Kant  himself — and  leads  to  the 
fiction  of  an  experience  which  is  experienced  by  nobody 
and  is  an  experience  of  nothing. 

The  first  essential,  then,  is  to  restrict  '  experience  '  to 
its  true  and  proper  meaning.  As  soon  as  this  is  done, 
it  becomes  apparent  how  impossible  it  is  to  take  experi 
ence  as  something  self-contained,  self-explaining  and 
self-existent.  Those  who  profess  to  do  so  make  matters 
plausible  only  by  illicitly  importing  into  their  professedly 
pure  experience  a  multitude  of  trans-subjective  elements. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   237 

Where,  then,  is  the  boundary-line  to  be  accurately 
drawn  between  pure  experience  and  what  transcends 
experience,  between  the  subjective  and  the  trans- 
subjective  ?  It  is  accurately  drawn  only  when  by  pure 
experience  is  understood  my  own  conscious  states — the 
c  stream '  of  ideas  which  constitutes  my  mind  in  a 
phenomenal  or  psychological  reference.  Everything  else 
is  trans-subjective  or  extra-psychological — i.e.,  episte- 
mologically  transcendent.  Limiting  ourselves  thus,  let 
us  look  at  the  nature  of  this  immanent  world.  There  is 
a  passage  in  Clifford's  well-known  essay  "  On  the  Nature 
of  Things-in-themselves  "  which  seems  to  me  to  illus 
trate  in  an  apt  and  vivid  way  the  characteristics  of  our 
actual  consciousness.  It  may  be  quoted  without  pre 
judice,  as  it  is  introduced  by  Clifford  and  used  by  him 
in  quite  another  reference.  "  In  reading  over  a  former 
page  of  my  manuscript,"  he  says,  "  I  found  suddenly 
upon  reflection  that,  although  I  had  been  conscious  of 
what  I  was  reading,  I  paid  no  attention  to  it ;  but 
had  been  mainly  occupied  in  debating  whether  faint 
red  lines  would  not  be  better  than  blue  ones  to  write 
upon  ;  in  picturing  the  scene  in  the  shop  when  I  should 
ask  for  such  lines  to  be  ruled,  and  in  reflecting  on  the 
lamentable  helplessness  of  nine  men  out  of  ten  when 
you  ask  them  to  do  anything  slightly  different  from 
what  they  have  been  accustomed  to  do.  This  debate 
had  been  started  by  the  observation  that  my  hand 
writing  varied  according  to  the  nature  of  the  argument, 
being  larger  when  that  was  diffuse  and  explanatory, 
occupied  with  a  supposed  audience,  and  smaller  when 
it  was  close,  occupied  only  with  the  sequence  of  pro 
positions.  Along  with  these  trains  of  thought  went  the 
sensations  of  noises  made  by  poultry,  dogs,  children 
and  organ-grinders,  and  that  diffused  feeling  in  the  side 
of  the  face  and  head  which  means  a  probable  toothache 
in  an  hour  or  two." 


238       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

Now  all  this  sounds  perfectly  intelligible  when  the 
different  elements  in  the  section  of  consciousness  ex 
amined  are  referred  to  their  real  causes,  and  recognised 
as  the  effects  of  an  independent  world  of  causally  con 
nected  things.  But  the  richly  variegated  scene  which 
Clifford  conjures  up  may  serve  to  bring  home  to  us  the 
hopelessly  disconnected  appearance  which  the  simul 
taneities  and  sequences  of  our  psychological  life  would 
present,  were  they  not  constantly  pieced  out  and  con 
nected — interpreted  in  a  thousand  ways — by  reference 
to  a  system  of  extra-psychological  realities.  If  the  train 
of  thoughts  and  images  seems  to  proceed  for  a  time 
with  a  certain  orderliness,  under  the  guidance  of  associa 
tion,  this  sequence  is  accompanied  by  a  mass  of  changing 
organic  sensations,  which  arise  and  disappear  without 
any  reference  to  the  chain  of  thoughts,  and  so  far  as 
consciousness  is  concerned,  have  an  absolute  beginning 
out  of  nothing  and  an  absolute  end.  Or  it  may  be  that 
our  meditations  are  abruptly  interrupted  by  a  sight  or 
a  sound — the  sound  of  a  street-fight,  the  entrance  of  a 
friend,  "  the  noises  made  by  poultry,  dogs,  children  and 
organ-grinders  "  —by  a  percept  of  some  kind,  in  short, 
which,  so  far  from  having  any  connection  with  my 
immediately  preceding  states  of  consciousness,  is  shot 
from  a  pistol,  as  the  saying  is — projected  headlong  into 
their  midst  in  an  utterly  inexplicable  fashion.  The 
same  discontinuous  and  irregular  character  of  subjective 
experience  as  such  is  exemplified  every  time  I  turn  my 
head  and  bring  into  view  objects  undreamt  of  the 
moment  before.  It  seems  hardly  necessary  to  add 
that  this  complete  incoherence  of  the  contents  of  con 
sciousness  as  such  is  recognised  by  modern  psychologists 
as  irresistibly  impelling  us  to  the  hypothesis  of  a  world 
of  trans-subjective  realities.1  It  requires,  in  fact,  a 

1  Cf.,  for  example,  Mr  Stout's  article  on  the  Genesis  of  the  Cognition 
of  Physical  Reality.  Mind,  XV.  p.  32. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       239 

strong  effort  of  abstraction  to  realise  at  all  what  the 
state  of  affairs  would  be  without  such  a  supposition  ; 
for  we  involuntarily  read  a  trans-subjective  meaning 
into  these  apparitions  of  our  perceptive  consciousness. 
An  intruding  percept,  which  has  no  causal  connection 
with  what  preceded  rt  in  my  consciousness,  we  yet 
accredit  as  a  messenger  from  a  world  beyond — the  sign 
of  a  fact  whose  appearance  just  at  this  particular  time 
and  place  is  perfectly  determined  by  the  real  causal 
connections  of  the  trans-subjective  world  to  which  it 
belongs.  It  is  only  as  thus  correlated  with  an  orderly 
trans-subjective  world  that  I  can  possibly  bring  order 
and  connection  into  my  psychological  experiences. 
Without  this  reference  they  are  fitly  compared  to  "  a 
feverish  dream,  which  constantly  breaks  off  and  tacks 
on  afresh,  without  any  indication  how  the  individual 
pieces  are  connected  with  one  another,  or  whether  they 
are  connected  at  all."  l  To  talk  of  immanent  causality 
as  existing  in  such  a  world  is  an  abuse  of  language. 
Nobody  asserts  a  causal  connection  between  his  idea  of 
the  sun  and  his  idea  of  the  warmed  stone.  The  percept 
of  the  sun  may  often  undoubtedly  precede  the  percept 
of  the  stone,  but  just  as  often  I  may  see  the  stone  first 
and  the  sun  second.  Moreover,  I  often  have  the  percept 
of  the  sun  without  that  of  the  stone,  and,  similarly,  I 
may  perceive  the  stone  and  a  multitude  of  things  may 
intervene  to  prevent  my  perceiving,  or  even  thinking 
of,  the  sun.  Between  the  one  idea  and  the  other  there 
is  no  regular  connection,  and  indeed  no  man  thinks  of 
asserting  a  causal  relation  between  them.  The  causal 
relation  is  between  the  real  facts  which  are  the  con 
dition  of  these  two  ideas — between  the  trans-subjective 
sun  and  the  trans-subjective  stone.  In  this  sense  all 
our  causal  judgments  are  transcendent,  until  we  begin, 
as  psychologists,  to  study  the  subjective  mechanism  on 

1  Hartmann,  Grundprobletn  der  Erkenntnisstheorie,  p.  55. 


240       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

its  own  account.  It  is  doubtless  simultaneities  and 
sequences  among  our  ideas  that  put  us  upon  the  track 
of  these  trans-subjective  connections  ;  but,  once  estab 
lished,  no  appearance  of  A  in  consciousness  without  B, 
or  of  B  without  A,  or  of  A  and  B  separated  by  various 
intervening  ideas — no  one,  in  short,  of  the  hundred 
casualties  to  which  the  conscious  sequence  is  exposed — 
shakes  in  the  least  our  belief  in  the  continued  validity 
of  the  relation  in  the  real  world.  And,  it  may  be  added, 
unless  from  the  beginning  we  transcended  the  immediate 
data  of  consciousness — unless  from  the  outset  they 
were  taken  not  for  what  they  are,  but  for  what  they 
mean — we  should  not  fasten  either  upon  the  regularities 
or  upon  the  irregularities  of  our  experience  as  calling 
for  explanation.  There  would  be  nothing  to  explain  ; 
we  should  simply  take  everything  as  it  came.  We  should 
be  mere  historians  of  the  course  of  conscious  occurrences 
that  had  made  up  our  individual  existence.1 

Such  then  is  pure  experience  ;  this  is  what  is  actually 
immanent.  The  actual  world  of  subjective  experience 
only  requires  to  be  exhibited  thus  in  its  nakedness  to 
have  its  essentially  dependent  and  symbolic  character 
recognised.  It  is  only  when  related  to  a  world  of  inde 
pendent  realities  that  these  subjective  phenomena 
become  intelligible.  Nay,  it  is  only  in  this  relation 
that  knowledge,  or  the  very  conception  of  knowledge, 
could  arise.  Such  an  independent  and  essentially  trans- 
subjective  world  is  therefore  necessarily  assumed  by 
every  philosophy.  An  examination  of  the  various 

1  So  Volkelt  says  that  '  knowledge  '  from  the  purely  immanent 
point  of  view  would  consist  simply  "  in  einem  Erzahlen  der  von 
Moment  zu  Moment  in  seinem  Bewusstsein  vorkommenden  Einzel- 
vorstellungen."  Properly  speaking  there  would  be  neither  thought 
nor  knowledge  "  sondern  lediglich  ein  Berichten  uber  den  absolut 
zusammenhangslosen  Spectakel  den  ich  unbegreiflicherweise  in 
meinem  Bewusstsein  antreffe."  Compare  the  fourth  section  of  his 
Immanuel  Kant's  Erkenntnisslehre,  to  which  I  am  indebted  in  the 
foregoing  paragraph. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       241 

theories  of  pure  experience  or  pure  immanence  would 
show  that,  however  they  may  disguise  it  from  them 
selves,  they  all  make  this  realistic  assumption.  But  it 
is  not  necessary  for  us  to  go  further  than  Mill's  well- 
known  '  psychological  theory  of  matter  ' — the  modern 
version  of  Berkeley  and  Hume.  Berkeley's  own  theo 
logical  idealism  is,  of  course,  not  here  in  point,  because 
sense-phenomena  are  there  referred  to  the  divine  will 
as  a  trans-subjective  real  cause,  and  so  the  all-important 
epistemological  step  is  made.  But  Mill,  with  Hume's 
example  before  him,  will  not  wittingly  overstep  the  line 
which  severs  experience  from  what  is  and  must  be 
beyond  experience.  He  has  thus  to  supply  a  background 
to  the  tangled  confusion  and  abrupt  inconsequences  of 
our  actual  sensations  and  at  the  same  time  to  seem  to 
avoid  making  the  epistemological  transition  from  sensa 
tion  to  something  different  in  kind  from  sensation. 
Though  not  itself  actual  sensation,  this  explanatory 
supplement  must  be  in  a  manner  homogeneous  and 
continuous  with  sensation ;  though  e%  hypothesi  not 
itself  experience,  it  must  hoist  the  colours  of  experience, 
and  so  avoid  the  appearance  of  transcendency  which 
your  true  Empiricist  shuns  like  the  very  plague. 

Mill  states  the  necessities  of  the  case  in  a  sufficiently 
candid  way,  "  What  is  it  which  leads  us  to  say  that  the 
objects  we  perceive  are  external  to  us  and  not  part  of 
our  own  thoughts  ?  We  mean  that  there  is  concerned 
in  our  perceptions  something  which  exists  when  we  are 
not  thinking  of  it,  which  existed  before  we  had  ever 
thought  of  it,  and  would  exist  if  we  were  annihilated  ; 
and  further,  that  there  exist  things  which  we  never  saw, 
touched,  or  otherwise  perceived,  and  things  which 
never  have  been  perceived  by  man.  This  idea  of  some 
thing  which  is  distinguished  from  our  fleeting  impres 
sions  by  what,  in  Kantian  language,  is  called  Perdur- 
ability  ;  something  which  is  fixed  and  the  same  while 

Q 


242       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

our  impressions  vary ;  something  which  exists  whether 
we  are  aware  of  it  or  not — constitutes  altogether  our  idea 
of  external  substance.  Whoever  can  assign  an  origin 
to  this  complex  conception  has  accounted  for  what 
we  mean  by  the  belief  in  matter/' l  Mill's  own  explana 
tion  is  his  celebrated  theory  of  '  Permanent  Possibilities 
of  Sensation.'  No  undue  stress  need  be  laid  here  on  the 
use  of  the  term  '  sensation/  as  we  are  not  discussing 
the  merits  or  demerits  of  a  purely  sensationalistic  theory 
of  knowledge.  Let  us  take  it  without  prejudice  in  the 
widest  sense  as  equivalent  to  percepts  ;  for  we  find  a 
substantially  similar  theory  in  some  of  the  German  Neo- 
Kantians,  who  refer  in  this  connection  to  Mill,  and  use 
indifferently  such  expressions  as  '  potential  sensations/ 
'  potential  perceptions/  '  possibilities  of  perception/ 
'possible  consciousness/2  It  is  altogether,  therefore, 
upon  the  '  permanent  possibilities  '  that  the  stress  is 
here  laid.  Mill  makes  matters  so  far  easier  for  himself 
at  the  outset  by  the  trans-subjective  assumption  of 
other  selves.  He  then  proceeds  to  resolve  the  physical 
universe  into  actual  and  possible  sensations,  repeating 
Berkeley's  analysis  in  so  many  words  :  "  I  see  a  piece 
of  white  paper  on  a  table.  I  go  into  another  room. 
.  .  .  Though  I  have  ceased  to  see  it,  I  am  convinced 
that  the  paper  is  still  there.  I  no  longer  have  the  sensa 
tions  which  it  gave  me  ;  but  I  believe  that  when  I 
again  place  myself  in  the  circumstances  in  which  I  had 
those  sensations,  I  shall  again  have  them  ;  and  further 
that  there  has  been  no  intervening  moment  at  which 
this  would  not  have  been  the  case.  .  .  .  The  concep 
tion  I  form  of  the  world  existing  at  any  moment  thus 
comprises,  along  with  the  sensations  I  am  feeling,  a 
countless  variety  of  possibilities  of  sensation.  .  .  .  These 

1  Examination   of  Hamilton,   p.    221    (3rd   ed.).      [Ch.    XI.,   "The 
Psychological  Theory  of  the  Belief  in  an  External  World."] 

2  For  examples  compare   Volkelt,   Kant's  Erkenntnisstheorie,   pp. 
160-189. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM      243 

various  possibilities  are  the  important  thing  to  me  in 
the  world.  My  present  sensations  are  generally  of  little 
importance,  and  are  moreover  fugitive  ;  the  possibilities, 
on  the  contrary,  are  permanent,  which  is  the  character 
that  mainly  distinguishes  our  idea  of  Substance  or 
Matter  from  our  notion  of  sensation."  '  These  certified 
or  guaranteed  possibilities  of  sensation  "  —possibilities 
guaranteed  not  only  for  me  but  for  other  human  beings 
— constitute,  then,  according  to  Mill,  all  that  is  real  in 
the  physical  world,  when  we  abstract  from  the  actual 
sensations  being  experienced  by  the  aggregate  of  sensi 
tive  creatures  at  any  given  moment. 

We  cannot,  however,  too  carefully  bear  in  mind  that, 
according  to  the  immanent  view  of  subjective  idealism, 
these  possible  sensations  or  perceptions  are  only  actual 
—i.e.,  only  exist — in  the  moment  of  actual  perception. 
Minds  and  the  experiences  of  these  minds  are,  with  Mill 
as  with  Berkeley,  the  only  two  modes  of  existences  (if, 
indeed,  Mill  would  distinguish  between  the  mind  and 
its  '  states  of  consciousness  ')  ;  the  essence  of  sensa 
tions  is  percipi.  Consequently  possible  sensations  are 
not  to  be  conceived  as  constituting  a  separate  genus  or 
mode  of  existence  ;  a  sensation  unfelt,  a  perception 
unperceived,  is  a  contradiction  in  terms.  The  possi 
bilities  of  sensation  have,  therefore,  a  merely  imaginative 
or  fictitious  permanence,  for,  so  long  as  they  are  not 
realised,  they  simply  do  not  exist  at  all — they  are 
nothing.  That  is,  be  it  understood,  what  consistency 
imperatively  dictates.  They  cannot  be  more  than  this, 
unless  we  leave  the  ground  of  immanency  altogether 
and  pass  to  the  real  thing  of  which  sensation  is  the 
evidence.  It  is  certain,  however,  that  to  Mill  the  per 
manent  possibilities  mean  a  great  deal  more  than  the 
'  naked  possibilities  ' x  which  consistency  allows  him. 

1  The  phrase  is  Mr  Stout's,  in  an  acute  criticism  of  Mill's  doctrine 
(Mind,  XV.  23-25),  to  which  I  am  indebted  in  this  paragraph. 


244   BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM 

Mill's  possibilities  have  functions  assigned  them  which 
only  real  existences  can  discharge.  Modifications  take 
place,  Mill  tells  us,  in  our  possibilities  of  sensation,  and 
these  modifications  "  are  mostly  quite  independent  of 
our  consciousness  and  of  our  presence  or  absence. 
Whether  we  are  asleep  or  awake,  the  fire  goes  out,  and 
puts  an  end  to  that  particular  possibility  of  warmth  and 
light.  Whether  we  are  present  or  absent,  the  corn 
ripens  and  brings  a  new  possibility  of  food.  Hence  we 
speedily  learn  to  think  of  Nature  as  made  up  solely 
of  these  groups  of  possibilities,  and  the  active  force  in 
Nature  as  manifested  in  the  modification  of  some  of 
these  by  others/'  Now,  we  may  fairly  ask  how  a  change 
can  take  place  in  a  possibility  at  a  time  when  it  is  admit 
tedly  only  a  possibility — that  is  to  say,  at  a  time  when  it 
does  not  exist.  "  A  change  in  nothing,"  as  Mr  Stout 
puts  it,  "is  no  change  at  all."  Equally  baseless  is  the 
notion  of  one  of  these  possibilities  causally  modifying 
another  at  a  time  when,  ex  hypothesi,  both  are  non 
existent.  The  truth  is  that,  under  cover  of  the  am 
biguous  term  '  possibility,'  Mill  has  covertly  reintroduced 
the  trans-subjective  reality.  Real  things  may  very  well 
be  described,  in  reference  to  our  experience,  as  '  per 
manent  possibilities  of  sensation  ' — that  is  to  say,  they 
are  the  permanent  real  conditions  which,  in  appropriate 
circumstances,  are  ever  ready  to  produce  sensations. 
We  may  even  go  further  and  say  that,  if  anyone  is 
determined  to  be  a  purist  and  to  define  things  solely 
in  their  relation  to  sensitive  experience — solely  from  the 
effects  which  he  finds  them  to  produce — this  definition 
of  them  as  permanent  possibilities  of  sensation  is,  per 
haps,  the  most  accurate  we  can  hope  for.  And,  of  course, 
if  Mill's  phrase  is  to  be  so  understood,  there  is  no  further 
difficulty  about  the  extra-conscious  existence  and  the 
extra-conscious  causality  of  these  possibilities,  for  we 
are  back  again  upon  the  solid  ground  of  trans-subjective 


BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM       245 

reality.  But  it  is  plain  enough  that  this  cannot  have 
been  Mill's  conscious  meaning.  "  Otherwise,"  as  Mr 
Stout  says,  "  he  would  have  committed  a  circulus  in 
definiendo  of  the  most  inexcusable  kind."  It  is  equally 
evident,  however,  that  though  Mill  may  not  have  in 
tended  it,  no  other  meaning  will  suit  the  assertions  he 
makes  about  his  possibilities.  Under  cover  of  the 
ambiguity  of  language,  and  impelled  by  the  realistic 
instinct,  Mill  has  simply  reinstated  the  trans-subjective 
reality  in  a  different  form  of  words.  "  Ungefahr  sagt 
das  der  Pfarrer  auch,  nur  mit  ein  bischen  andern  Worten." 
The  theory,  therefore,  which  seems  so  ingenious  and 
plausible  indicates  in  truth  the  breakdown  of  subjective 
idealism.  The  realist  may  feel  tolerably  easy  when  the 
talk  is  of  '  modifications  '  taking  place  in  our  possi 
bilities  of  sensation  "  mostly  quite  independent  of  our 
consciousness  and  of  our  presence  or  absence."  But  he 
would  be  a  pedant  indeed,  who,  instead  of  talking  of 
real  things,  insisted  on  substituting  the  circumlocution 
'  permanent  possibilities  of  sensation/ 

It  is  not  difficult  to  see  how  Mill,  from  his  general 
standpoint  in  these  matters,  was  led  to  the  phrase  and 
the  theory.  It  is  only  in  sensation,  or  say  rather  in  per 
ception,  that  the  thing  reveals  its  existence  to  me  or  to 
others.  I  can  only  describe  it,  therefore,  in  terms  of 
precept  ion ;  when  I  do  not  perceive  it,  it  does  not  exist 
for  me.  So  far  as  experience  goes,  I  can  thus  manifestly 
never  get  beyond  the  rubric  of  perception,  past,  present, 
or  to  come.  Hence  Mill  identifies  the  thing  itself  with 
present  and  possible  sensations.  Exactly  the  same 
line  of  thought  leads  to  the  substantiation  of  experience 
and  possible  experience  in  the  writings  of  the  Neo- 
Kantians.  The  nature  or  predicates  of  the  thing  can 
only  be  learned  in  experience  ;  the  Neo-Kantian  accord 
ingly  generalises  his  different  experiences  of  any  trans- 
subjective  thing,  and  substantiates  these  as  a  pheno- 


246      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

menal  object.  The  world  of  such  objects  assumes  with 
him  the  same  independent  and  trans-subjective  position 
as  Mill's  world  of  permanent  possibilities,  and  with  just 
as  little  right.  What  we  are  to  think  of  this  professedly 
immanent  world  we  have  already  seen.  This  phenomenal 
world,  which  will  neither  be  subjective  appearance  nor 
the  frank  trans-subjective  thing,  but  suspends  itself 
in  vacuo  between  the  two,  is  a  philosophical  hybrid  to 
which  no  real  existence  or  fact  corresponds.  These  so- 
called  phenomena,  in  complete  detachment  from  the 
subjective  consciousness  of  mankind,  are  epistemologic- 
ally  transcendent,  not  immanent,  and  the  causality 
which  obtains  between  them  is  likewise  transcendent ; 
it  is  the  causal  action  of  one  real  thing  upon  another. 

Is  it  not  the  case,  in  short,  that  the  term  '  experience/ 
as  used  throughout  this  espistemological  discussion, 
whether  by  Neo-Kantian  or  by  English  Empiricist, 
covers  a  huge  petitio  principii  ?  The  question  at  issue 
is  the  possibility  of  a  knowledge  of  the  trans-subjective, 
but  I  cannot  experience  the  existence  of  another  being. 
I  can  be  aware  that  another  being  exists,  but  its  existence 
can  be  experienced  by  itself  alone.  I  know  that  you 
exist ;  my  experience  furnishes  ground  for  believing 
as  much.  But  you  are  not  part  of  my  experience  :  I 
do  not  experience  your  states.  In  short,  I  am  not  you. 
Similarly,  I  know  that  something  which  I  call  the  table 
exists,  because  it  resists  the  pressure  I  exert  against  it. 
The  table  is  the  trans-subjective  explanation  of  certain 
features  of  my  experience  ;  the  table  itself  cannot  strictly 
be  said  to  be  experienced.  The  reality  of  everything 
beyond  my  own  existence  is  thus  of  necessity  beyond 
experience,  for  the  experiences  of  each  being  are  simply 
its  own  states,  its  own  life.  By  the  use  of  this  term, 
therefore,  in  connection  with  knowledge,  the  trans- 
subjective  reference  is  cut  off  in  advance  before  the 
formal  discussion  begins. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       247 

This  is  so  neatly  illustrated  in  our  home-grown  philos 
ophy  that  I  make  no  apology  for  using  Professor  Bain's 
position  to  drive  my  argument  home.  Professor  Bain 
shall  be  answered  out  of  the  mouth  of  Mr  Spencer.  As 
is  well  known,  Professor  Bain  lays  great  stress,  and 
rightly  so,  on  the  contrast  between  passive  and  active 
sensation  as  a  source  of  our  belief  in  an  external  world. 
"  Movement/'  he  says,  "  gives  a  new  character  to  our 
whole  percipient  existence/'  "  The  sense  of  resistance 
is  the  deepest  foundation  of  our  notion  of  externality."  l 
In  this  Mr  Spencer  is  quite  at  one  with  him.  But  Mr 
Spencer  accepts  this  experience  as  the  sufficient  evidence 
of  '  an  existence  beyond  consciousness  ' — of  '  something 
which  resists/  Professor  Bain  is  more  subtle.  The 
sense  of  effort  and  of  effort  resisted  is  no  doubt  contrasted 
with  '  purely  passive  sensation/  but  the  contrast  is  still 
within  consciousness.  Our  experiences  of  resistance  are, 
after  all,  just  so  many  '  feels/  so  many  subjective 
changes.  "  The  exertion  of  our  own  muscular  power  is 
the  fact  constituting  the  property  called  resistance.  Of 
matter  as  independent  of  our  feeling  of  resistance,  we 
can  have  no  conception  ;  the  rising  up  of  this  feeling 
within  us  amounts  to  everything  that  we  mean  by 
resisting  matter."  Those  '  feels/  then,  are  the  material 
world.  "  We  are  not  at  liberty  to  say  without  incurring 
contradiction  that  our  feeling  of  expended  energy  is 
one  thing,  and  a  resisting  material  world  another  and 
a  different  thing ;  that  other  and  different  thing  is  by 
us  wholly  unthinkable."  2  Or  as  he  puts  it  more  gener 
ally — "  knowledge  means  a  state  of  mind ;  the  notion 
of  material  things  is  a  mental  fact.  We  are  incapable 
even  of  discussing  the  existence  of  an  independent 
material  world ;  the  very  act  is  a  contradiction."  3 

1  Senses  and  the  Intellect,  pp.  376-7. 

z  Mental  Science,  p.  199. 

3  Senses  and  the  Intellect,  p.  375. 


248      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

All  that  Professor  Bain  asserts  is  true,  is  even  obvious. 
Unquestionably,  so  far  as  experience  goes,  actual  and 
possible  perceptions  sum  up  the  case,  and  in  the  present 
instance  our  feelings  of  impeded  effort  are  all  the  ex 
periences  we  have  to  show.  The  independent  thing, 
the  '  something  which  resists/  is  admittedly  a  rational 
construction,  a  hypothesis  to  explain  our  experience  ; 
ex  vi  termini,  therefore,  it  is  beyond  experience,  though 
necessary  to  it  as  its  causal  explanation.  In  short,  the 
Berkeleian  analysis  of  Mill  and  Professor  Bain  is  abso 
lutely  true  as  psychology  ;  but  that  the  attempt  should 
have  been  made  to  substitute  the  psychological  facts 
for  their  trans-subjective  conditions,  and  thus  to  pass 
off  psychology  as  ontology  or  metaphysics,  is  one  of 
the  strangest  results  of  super-subtle  analysis.  As  Mr 
Spencer  puts  it,  "  the  very  conception  of  experience 
implies  something  of  which  there  is  experience."  l  The 
'  contradiction  '  of  which  Professor  Bain  speaks  is  of  his 
own  making,  and  lies  in  the  impossible  nature  of  the 
demand  he  formulates.  Mr  Spencer's  retort  is  simply 
to  state  what  the  position  amounts  to.  It  amounts  to 
"  a  tacit  demand  for  some  other  proof  of  an  external 
world  than  that  which  is  given  in  states  of  conscious 
ness  "  "  some  proof  of  this  outer  existence  other  than 
that  given  in  terms  of  inner  existence/'2  States  of 
consciousness,  in  short,  not  only  exist,  as  experience  ; 
they  have  a  meaning,  an  evidential  value,  and  can 
testify  to  the  existence  of  that  which  they  are  not. 
Only  in  this  respect,  as  symbolic  and  self -transcendent, 
are  '  mental  facts  '  to  be  called  knowledge.  But  this 
whole  aspect  of  consciousness  is  suppressed  in  advance 
by  Professor  Bain,  who  is  really  dominated  by  the  curious 
but  deeply  rooted  idea  that,  in  order  to  know  a  thing, 
it  is  necessary  actually  to  be  the  thing. 

1  Principles  of  Psychology,  II.  349. 

2  Ibid.,  II.  444. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM       249 

The  horror  of  the  transcendent,  which  we  have  thus 
seen  alike  in  followers  of  the  English  and  of  the  Conti- 
tinental  tradition,  undoubtedly  owes  its  wide  diffusion 
at  present  very  largely  to  the  influence  of  Kant,  with 
whose  idealistic  followers  it  has  become  a  philosophic 
superstition.  But  their  doctrine  of  immanency,  it  may 
be  added,  completely  obscures  the  truth  that  is  contained 
in  Kant's  doctrine  of  the  categories.  These  principles 
pf_  reason  werje_j)rjgin^ly^nj:enileji  to  lift  us_out_of  the 
n^  or  any  purely  empirical 


theory^  This  purpose  is  necess^jily^iistrated  if  they 
are  taken  entirely  in  an  immanent  reference.  Subjective 
matter  of  sense  may  be  transfixed  as  we  please  with 
subjective  principles  of  thought,  but  two  subjectives  do 
not  make  an  objective  ;  l  the  outcome  is  as  purely 
subjective  as  Hume's,  though  it  bears  a  different  com 
plexion.  Kant's  own  expressions,  however,  are  not  so 
unambiguously  immanent  as  his  idealistic  followers 
would  have  us  believe.  They  waver  in  a  way  which 
is  significant  of  two  conflicting  lines  of  thought  in  his 
mind  ;  and  in  his  doctrine  of  judgment,  and  of  the 
categories  as  the  forms  of  judgment,  he  was  at  one  time 
upon  another  track.  In  truth  he  had  struck  here  upon 
the  only  path  which  can  lead  us  out  of  subjectivity. 
The  passivity  of  sense  does  not  carry  us  beyond  our 
selves  ;  only  the  activity  of  reason  avails  to  do  so. 
Mental  activity  is  summed  up  in  the  judgment  and  the 
categories  are  different  forms  of  judgment.  In  them 
reason  expresses  its  own  necessities  —  its  necessities  of 
connection  and  explanation.  Through  them  it  may  be 
said  both  to  posit  an  objective  world  as  an  explanation 
of  experience  and  progressively  to  render  that  world 

1  It  is  this  difficulty,  doubtless,  which  leads  Kant  at  one  time  to 
say  that  it  is  the  addition  of  the  categories  to  the  pure  subjectivity 
of  sense  that  yields  us  objects,  while  at  another  time  he  tells  us  that 
it  is  their  application  to  the  matter  of  sense  which  confers  objectivity 
on  the  categories. 


250      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

intelligible.  In  perception  the  conscious  judgment  re 
affirms  the  instinctive  judgment  of  feeling,  and  refers 
the  subjective  affection  to  its  origin  in  the  real.  From 
the  outset  the  stimuli  of  sense  are  thus  projected— 
attached  as  predicates  to  a  real  world,  of  which  they 
are  at  once  the  qualities  and  the  effects.  In  this  primi 
tive  judgment  the  categories  of  substance  and  cause 
are  combined,  and  these  basal  categories  involve  all  the 
rest.  In  this  causal  judgment  we  once  for  all  overpass 
the  limits  of  the  individual  self.  It  was  not  without 
reason,  therefore,  that  Kant  recognised  in  the  judgment, 
and  in  the  thoughts  of  which  judgment  is  the  vehicle, 
the  instrument  of  our  enfranchisement  from  subjective 
bonds.  But  it  becomes  so  only  when  it  is  frankly  taken 
in  this  trans-subjective  reference.  The  categories  do 
construct  for  us  an  objective  world,  but  only  when  they 
are  transcendently  employed.  Transcendental  Realism 
rather  than  transcendental  Idealism  was  the  result  to 
which  the  Kantian  theory  of  judgment  fairly  pointed, 
and  many  of  his  expressions  may  be  read  in  this  sense. 
"  All  experience/' J  he  tells  us,  for  example,  "  in  addition 
to  the  perception  of  the  senses  by  which  something  is 
given,  contains  besides  a  notion  of  an  object  which  is 
given,  or  which  appears,  in  perception."  So  he  says 
again,  "  Cognitions  consist  in  the  definite  reference  of 
given  ideas  to  an  object."  2  The  notion  of  the  object  is 
doubtless  itself  subjective,  as  Neo-Kantian  subtlety 
urges  ;  how,  we  may  ask,  could  it  be  otherwise  ?  But 
it  is  the  notion  of  a  real  object,  a  trans-subjective  thing. 
It  is  the  presence  of  this  notion  that  differentiates  what 
Kant  calls  knowledge,  cognition  or  experience  from 
sensation  or  what  he  calls  mere  perception.  Or,  as  we 
have  been  led  to  express  it  in  the  last  few  pages,  the 

1  Werke,  III.  112  (ed.  Hartenstein) .     Experience  is  here  used  in  the 
specific  Kantian  sense  as  opposed  to  mere  perception  and  the  associ 
ative  play  of  ideas  in  the  soul. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  1 1 8. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM      251 

trans-subjective  reference  constitutes  the  very  essence 
of  knowledge  as  distinguished  from  experience  as  a 
series  of  subjective  happenings  which  take  place  but 
which  mean  nothing.  Kant  himself  did  not  consistently 
follow  out  this  line  of  thought.  But  it  is  perhaps  not 
too  much  to  say  that  a  fresh  interpretation  of  the  cate 
gories  in  the  realistic  sense  just  indicated  is  at  the  present 
time  the  only  promising  basis  of  a  sound  philosophy. 


CONCLUSION.1 

So  far,  it  may  be  said,  we  have  not  got  further  than  the 
knowledge  that  a  trans-subjective  exists  ;  that  is  to  say, 
our  trans-subjective  world  is  merely  Kant's  thing-in- 
itself  or  Mr  Spencer's  Unknowable — an  undetermined 
causal  somewhat,  "  a  notion  so  imperfect,"  according  to 
Hume,  "  that  no  sceptic  will  think  it  worth  while  to 
contend  against  it."  But  this  sceptical  relativism  is 
due  to  a  misconception.  If  our  categories  are  competent 
to  tell  us  that  a  trans-subjective  world  exists,  they  are 
also  competent  to  tell  us  what  its  nature  is.  It  is  true 
that  our  categories  are  subjective,  if  it  be  subjective  to 
express  the  necessities  of  connection  and  explanation 
which  reason  imposes  upon  us.  But  that  they  are 
merely  subjective  is,  in  the  nature  of  the  case,  incapable 

1  [The  preceding  Lectures  appeared  in  the  Philosophical  Review, 
Vols.  I.,  Nos.  2  and  5,  and  II.,  Nos.  2  and  3,  between  the  dates  March 
1892  and  May  1893.  The  author  contributed  to  the  same  Review, 
Vol.  III.,  No.  i  (January  1894),  a  discussion  entitled  "  Epistemological 
Conclusions,"  the  first  part  of  which  was  occupied  by  a  reply  to 
certain  criticisms  of  his  Lectures  by  Professor  John  Watson.  He  then 
went  on  :  "  I  will  take  the  liberty  of  appending  here  a  few  paragraphs 
in  continuation  of  my  four  articles  on  Epistemology  in  this  Review. 
When  the  articles  were  originally  given  as  a  course  of  Balfour  Lectures 
in  Edinburgh  in  the  spring  of  1891,  these  paragraphs  followed  im 
mediately  upon  what  has  already  appeared  in  the  Philosophical 
Review.  They  were  omitted  at  the  close  of  the  last  article  because 
the  article  already  exceeded  the  usual  length  and  had  reached  a 
point  at  which  its  more  immediate  subject  seemed  concluded.  But 
I  am  now  inclined  to  regret  their  omission,  because  by  returning  upon 
the  general  argument  I  think  they  tend  to  place  the  scope  of  the 
whole  inquiry  in  a  clearer  light  and  to  emphasise  the  precise  nature 
of  the  conclusion  reached." 

These  paragraphs  are  accordingly  restored  to  their  original  place 
as  the  Conclusion  of  the  Third  Series  of  Balfour  Lectures. — ED.] 


254      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

of  proof.  They  are  principles  of  mental  synthesis  ;  but 
why  should  they  not  be  at  the  same  time  principles  of 
real  connection  in  a  trans-subjective  world — a  world 
whose  real  connections  the  mental  synthesis  only  renders 
or  reconstructs  ?  The  possibility  of  doubt,  of  course, 
always  remains ;  for  if  we  cannot  prove  dogmatically 
that  the  forms  of  thought  do  not  apply  to  reality,  neither 
can  we  prove  that  they  do  apply.  The  feat  of  comparing 
our  percept  with  an  unperceived  thing  is,  as  Berkeley 
incisively  argued,  for  ever  impossible  ;  we  cannot  get 
behind  our  own  knowledge  and  know  without  knowing. 
Proof  of  this  sort  being  impossible,  we  are  thrown  back 
upon  a  species  of  trust  or  presumption — a  trust  that 
knowledge  in  its  fundamental  characteristics  renders 
correctly  the  world  of  existence,  or,  to  put  it  otherwise 
and  perhaps  more  simply,  a  trust  that  things  exist  as 
we  know  them.  In  presence  of  an  ultimate  sceptical 
doubt  of  the  nature  indicated,  we  are  necessarily  re 
duced  to  a  balance  of  probabilities.  Now,  to  suppose 
an  absence  of  correspondence  between  the  forms  of  know 
ledge  and  the  forms  of  existence — to  suppose  the  mere 
subjectivity  of  the  former — is  to  suppose  that  the 
mechanism  of  knowledge  has  been  expressly  devised  to 
defeat  its  own  purpose.  If  we  take  the  universe  for  a 
bad  joke,  such  a  supposition  will  have  much  in  its 
favour,  but  it  seems  to  me  incompatible  with  any  belief 
in  the  rationality  of  existence.  In  other  words,  the 
probability  in  favour  of  such  a  view  is  so  small  as  to  be 
a  negligible  quantity. 

The  idea  of  merely  subjective  validity  is  a  kind  of 
speculative  nightmare,  for  which  we  have  largely  Kant 
to  thank.  Yet  we  can  see  how  it  had  been  preparing  all 
through  the  modern  period.  The  problem  of  knowledge, 
when  it  comes  into  the  foreground,  inevitably  tends  to 
separate  the  knowing  subject  from  the  whole  world  of 
objective  reality.  The  philosophical  antithesis  is  no 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM   255 

longer  between  the  whole  and  the  part,  between  the 
permanent  unity  and  its  dependent  manifestations,  as  it 
is  when  the  line  of  thought  is  metaphysical  or  ontological. 
The  antithesis  is  now  between  the  subjective  conscious 
ness  and  the  world  of  real  things.  The  subject  is,  there 
fore,  placed  upon  one  side  and  the  whole  trans-subjective 
universe  upon  the  other,  and  a  chasm  is  made  between 
them.  The  knower  is  practically  extruded  from  the 
real  universe  ;  he  is  treated  as  if  he  did  not  belong  to  it, 
as  if  he  came  to  inspect  it  like  a  stranger  from  afar. 
His  forms  of  thought  come  thus  to  be  regarded  as  an 
alien  product  with  no  inherent  fitness  to  express  the 
nature  of  things.  Things  are  rather  conceived  as  in 
themselves  independent  of  these  forms,  so  that  the 
forms,  when  applied,  are  treated  as  an  unauthorised 
gloss,  a  distorting  medium.  A  little  reflection,  however, 
tells  us  that  to  conceive  matters  thus  is  to  convert  the 
necessary  duality  or  opposition  which  knowledge  involves 
into  a  real  or  metaphysical  dualism  for  which  there  is 
no  kind  of  warrant.  We  are  the  victims  of  metaphor,  if 
we  allow  ourselves  to  think  of  the  individual  knower  as 
standing  outside  of  the  universe  in  this  way,  or  if  we 
imagine  a  real  chasm  or  gulf  between  him  and  the 
objects  he  knows.  The  knower  is  in  the  world  which  he 
comes  to  know ;  and  the  forms  of  his  thought,  so  far 
from  being  an  alien  growth  or  an  imported  product,  are 
themselves  a  function  of  the  whole.  As  M.  Fouillee  puts 
it :  "  Consciousness,  so  far  from  being  outside  reality,  is 
the  immediate  presence  of  reality  to  itself  and  the  inward 
unrolling  of  its  riches."  1  When  this  is  once  grasped, 
the  idea  of  thought  as  '  a  kind  of  necessary  evil '  ceases 
to  have  even  a  superficial  plausibility. 

For  I  desire  to  repeat  here,  what  was  indicated  in  the 
first  of  these  articles,  that  the  epistemological  Realism, 
the  transcendency,  the  duality,  of  which  so  much  has 

1  L'Evolutionnisme  des  Idees-forces,  p.  291. 


256      BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON   REALISM 

been  said,  are  not  to  be  taken  in  the  metaphysical  refer 
ence  just  alluded  to.  The  two  substances  "  separated 
by  the  whole  diameter  of  being," i  which  modern 
philosophy  inherited  from  Descartes,  I  take  to  be  no 
better  than  an  invention  of  the  enemy.  It  was  the  most 
unfortunate  error  of  the  Scottish  philosophers  that  they 
identified  the  epistemological  and  the  metaphysical 
position.  Their  reassertion,  as  against  Hume,  of  the 
necessary  trans-subjective  reference  in  knowledge  was 
unfortunately  supposed  by  them  to  be  equivalent  to  a 
reinstatement  of  the  abstract  opposition  between  mind 
and  matter  as  two  absolutely  heterogeneous  substances. 
But,  if  matter  is  defined  as  the  precise  (metaphysical) 
opposite  of  mind — if  we  start  with  the  presupposition 
that  they  have  nothing  in  common,  that  the  one  just 
is  what  the  other  is  not — the  growth  of  the  subjective 
nightmare  is  perfectly  intelligible.  There  is  no  reason 
why  we  should  expect  the  mandate  of  reason  to  run  in 
a  completely  foreign  domain.  No  sort  of  knowledge, 
indeed,  would  be  possible  of  a  world  of  things  whose 
relation  to  consciousness  and  the  forms  of  thought  was 
conceived  as  mere  negation.  The  opposition  had  already 
led  legitimately,  in  the  history  of  modern  philosophy, 
to  the  denial  of  the  possibility  of  knowledge,  and  was 
not  to  be  overcome  by  a  mere  assertion  of  the  immediate 
presence  of  the  one  to  the  other  in  the  knowing  act. 
A  real  metaphysical  dualism  would  cleave  the  universe 
in  two,  leaving  two  absolutely  non-communicating 
worlds.  The  possibility  of  knowledge  becomes,  on  the 
other  hand,  the  surest  guarantee  of  metaphysical  monism 
— of  a  unity  which  underlies  all  differences. 

The  metaphysical  position  of  Cartesianism  into  which 
the  Scottish  philosophers  thus  relapsed  was  connected, 
there  can  be  little  doubt,  with  the  old  mechanical  or 
deistic  conception  of  creation  and  of  the  relation  of 

1  Hamilton's  Lectures  on  Metaphysics,  II.  120. 


BALFOUR  LECTURES  ON  REALISM      257 

God  to  the  world  of  nature — matter  being  looked  on  as 
something  absolutely  dead,  absolutely  undivine,  except 
that  once  upon  a  time  an  immense  quantity  of  it  was 
'  created '  and  set  in  motion,  since  which  time  it  con 
tinues  to  exist  as  a  kind  of  brute  fact  so  long  as  its 
'  being '  is  not  terminated  by  another  special  fiat  of  its 
Creator.  I  confess  I  know  as  little  as  Berkeley  what  is 
meant  by  the  being  or  existence  of  such  matter,  nor  can 
I  conceive  the  possibility  of  any  existence  placed  outside 
of  the  divine  consciousness  and  will  in  the  manner 
suggested.  The  feat  is  one  which  even  a  divine  being 
could  not  perform ;  there  is  no  region  outside  of  God 
into  which  he  could  extrude  his  creature  and  cut  it 
adrift  from  himself.  The  world  of  nature  cannot  be 
understood  by  an  intelligent  theist  otherwise  than  as 
the  ever-present  working  of  a  divine  power.  This  is  a 
lesson  which  most  of  us  have  learned,  as  children  of  the 
nineteenth  century.  But  the  abstract  dualism  of  meta 
physics  was  in  its  way  a  counterpart  of  the  mechanical 
theology  which  banished  God  from  his  own  world,  and 
so  made  that  world  an  unintelligibility  to  thought.  The 
world  conceived  thus,  as  a  mere  brute  fact,  is  formulated 
in  philosophy  as  the  unknowable  thing-in-itself .  It  was 
a  survival  of  this  dualistic  feeling  in  Kant  which  led  him 
to  scout,  as  he  did,  the  idea  of  what  he  calls  a  preforma- 
tion  system,  or  pre-established  harmony  between  the 
mind  and  things,  in  respect  of  the  categories  and  forms 
of  thought.  He  means  by  the  phrase  the  possibility  that 
the  forms  of  thought  are  both  subjective  and  objective, 
forms  of  the  subjective  intelligence  and  forms  of  the 
real  world  at  once.  This  supposition,  which  we  have 
seen  to  be  so  eminently  reasonable,  Kant  sets  aside 
with  an  ill-concealed  impatience  that  is  somewhat 
difficult  to  understand.  But  if  the  metaphysical  hetero 
geneity  of  the  two  sides  is  tacitly  presupposed,  then 
unquestionably  the  notion  of  a  pre-established  harmony 

R 


258       BALFOUR  LECTURES   ON   REALISM 

does  become  no  better  than  a  deus  ex  machina,  and  you 
have  no  guarantee  that  any  such  friendly,  and  as  it  were 
miraculous,  interposition  has  taken  place.  And  in  this 
way,  it  seems  to  me,  Kant's  contemptuous  treatment  of 
the  idea  may  be  understood.  But  the  error  lies  in  the 
original  supposition  of  heterogeneity  ;  it  is  this  abstract 
dualism  which  necessitates  the  mechanical  idea  of  a 
special  interposition  to  establish  correspondence.  If 
the  first  unfounded  supposition  is  dropped,  then  harmony 
does  not  require  to  be  established  by  special  decree  ;  it 
has  the  presumption  on  its  side.  We  may  go  further, 
and  say  that  when  the  matter  is  duly  considered,  this  is 
the  necessary  assumption  of  metaphysical  thought. 
Epistemological  investigation,  therefore,  if  it  is  not  to 
lead  us  back  to  the  sceptical  idealism,  or  to  the  impasse 
of  an  Unknown  and  Unknowable,  must  tacitly  presuppose 
this  metaphysical  unity  of  the  subjective  and  the  objec 
tive,  or,  to  put  it  more  strictly,  the  harmony  of  the 
subjective  function  with  the  universe  from  which  it 
springs.  Starting  from  this  basis,  Epistemology  may 
afterwards  return  to  prove  its  own  assumption,  so  far 
as  we  can  talk  of  proof  in  such  a  case.  Epistemology 
supplies  the  indirect  proof  that  this  is  the  only  hypothesis 
which  can  be  consistently  thought  out  without  dissolving 
in  absurdity  or  contradiction. 


Printed  in  Great  Britain  by 
WILLIAM  BLACKWOOD   &  SONS  LTD,. 


f  - 

University  of  Toronto 

Library 

tO 

O 

0 

g 

C\2            CQ 

/, 

H 

// 

&   cd 
•p   0 

0      ?H 

DO  NOT 

/ 

co 

// 

*§ 

0 

REMOVE 

/ 

SH    CQ 

H 

TJ    0 

£-4         ?™l 

<tj     JZJ 

THE 

-P 

•s    0 

C    0 
0  rH 
CQ 

CARD 

•H     h 
-P     P 
-P    0 
cd  CH 

FROM 

\ 

(X,   rH 

\\ 

1    aj 

0   pq 

fl 

THIS 

\ 

t»0  0 

>\ 

c  ^ 

^>\. 

F 

POCKET 

CO 

o  ,o 

1  —  1   t>- 
•H    LO 

^cl  cjj 

Acme  Library  Card  Pocket 
Uaaer  Fat.  •'Kef.  Index  File' 
Made  by  LIBRARY  BUREAU 

(X,   PH